Chapman University Digital Chapman University Digital
Commons Commons
Philosophy Faculty Books and Book Chapters
Science and Technology Faculty Books and
Book Chapters
12-19-2017
Libertarianism Libertarianism
Bas van der Vossen
Chapman University
Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_books
Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other Political Science Commons, and the
Political Theory Commons
Recommended Citation Recommended Citation
van der Vossen, Bas. “Libertarianism”,
Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Politics
, William Thompson (ed.),
2017. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.86
This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Science and Technology Faculty Books and Book
Chapters at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Books
and Book Chapters by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information,
please contact [email protected].
Page 1 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Libertarianism
Bas Van Der Vossen, Department of Philosophy, Chapman University
https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.86
Published online: 19 December 2017
Summary
Libertarianism is a theory in political philosophy that strongly values individual freedom
and is skeptical about the justified scope of government in our lives. Libertarians see
individuals as sovereign, as people who have a right to control their bodies and work,
who are free to decide how to interact with willing others, and who cannot be forced to
do things against their will without very strong justification.
For some, the argument in support of this view hinges on the principle of self-ownership.
To them, individual rights are morally foundational, the basic building blocks of their
theory. Many others, however, take a broader view, arguing that societies flourish when
they offer people large degrees of freedom in both personal and economic matters.
As a result, libertarianism sees the state as playing at most only a very limited role in
matters concerning distributive justice. Libertarians are skeptical about calls to reduce
material inequality for its own sake, strongly favor free trade, and defend opening
borders for migrants. They see policies that violate these commitments as inevitably
involving wrongs against free and equal persons.
Keywords: freedom, rights, self-ownership, equality, capitalism, free market, Robert Nozick
Introduction
Libertarianism is a set of views in political philosophy. Libertarians strongly value individual
freedom, seeing respect for individual freedom as a central requirement of justice. As a result,
they believe that there are strong limits to permissible coercion. While people can be
justifiably be forced to do (or not do) certain things—most prominently, people can be forced
to refrain from violating the rights of others—they cannot be coerced to serve the overall good
of society, or even their own personal good. Thus, libertarians typically endorse strong rights
to individual liberty and private property; defend civil liberties like equal rights for
homosexuals; endorse drug decriminalization, open borders, and abortion rights; and oppose
most military intervention.
Libertarian positions are most controversial in the realm of distributive justice. Libertarians
typically endorse something like a free-market economy, or an economic order based on
private property and voluntary market relationships among economic agents. Consequently,
libertarians usually oppose the kind of large-scale, coercive wealth redistribution in which
contemporary welfare states engage. Just as people have strong rights to individual freedom
Bas Van Der Vossen, Department of Philosophy, Chapman University
Page 2 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
in social affairs, libertarians argue, they also have strong rights to freedom of choice in the
economic realm. Thus, rights of freedom of contract and exchange, freedom of occupation,
private property, and the like are taken very seriously, leading libertarians to oppose most
forms of economic regulation, licensing laws, and redistributive taxation.
In these respects, libertarian theory is closely related to—indeed, at times practically
indistinguishable from—the classical liberal tradition, as embodied by John Locke, David
Hume, Adam Smith, and Immanuel Kant. It affirms a strong distinction between the public
and the private spheres of life; insists on the status of individuals as morally free and equal,
something it interprets as implying a strong requirement against nonconsensual subjection to
others; and believes that a respect for this status requires treating people as right-holders.
Some libertarians see these conclusions as following from a commitment to freedom as the
paramount value. They hold, for example, that each person has a right to maximum equal
negative liberty, which is understood as the absence of forcible interference from other agents
(e.g., Narveson, 1988; Steiner, 1994; Narveson & Sterba, 2010). Others focus more on the
idea of self-ownership. Most famously, this view is typically attributed to Robert Nozick
(Nozick, 1974; also Cohen, 1995); however, see the discussion that follows later in this article.
On this view, a commitment to freedom follows from the requirement that we respect
individuals’ dominion over their lives and persons.
While these approaches are the most well known and distinctively libertarian, many theorists
begin with other commitments and find that they lead to libertarian conclusions. Some depart
from consequentialist or teleological principles, which they see as best served by libertarian
policies (Epstein, 1995, 1998; Rasmussen & Den Uyl, 2005; Shapiro, 2007). Others adopt a
Rawlsian framework, either claiming that the spirit of John Rawls’ theory of justice
(particularly a concern for the least well off) calls for a far greater respect for individual
freedom than is usually thought (Tomasi, 2012), or that such more liberty-oriented
requirements flow from a public reason or justificatory approach (Gaus, 2010, 2012). Yet
others begin at still different points.
A major theme in all these approaches is an emphasis on insights from economics. Many
(perhaps most) libertarians feel the force of their conclusions because they believe that
market economies, coupled with strong protections of civil and political liberties, make
societies and people prosper, flourish, and leave behind the crushing problems of poverty.
Self-Ownership
One way to identify libertarian theories is by reference to their conclusions. However, some
libertarians see themselves as committed to what could be more adequately be termed
libertarian premises. Prime among these is the idea the individuals are self-owners.
This idea is usually attributed to Robert Nozick, especially by his opponents (Cohen, 1995;
Otsuka, 2003). One of the arguments that Nozick employed to criticize theories of justice that
aim at equality or some other distributional outcome was that such theories fail to respect
individuals as rights-holders. These theories invariably require redistributive taxation in order
to maintain the desired distributional outcomes, and such taxation means siphoning off part of
Page 3 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
people’s earnings. Since those earning represent people’s labor, and people initially have the
right not to be forced to work for certain ends, Nozick argued, redistributive taxation is
morally on a par with forced labor.
Nozick’s point was to make clear a choice that all theories of justice must face: Either we
respect people as having the right to be the primary controllers of their lives, labor, and
bodies, in which case they must be free to work, and not work, as they choose (so long as they
don’t violate the rights of others). This means working for whomever they want, on the terms
they want, and keeping the gains. Recognizing this, of course, leaves little room for
redistributive taxation. Or one can prefer a theory of justice that enforces certain
distributions. But in that case, one must endorse taking what people innocently produce
through their own labor, redirecting their work to purposes that they did not freely choose.
This latter option, Nozick wrote, involves claiming a kind of control over the lives of others
that is similar to a claim of ownership, and this is unacceptable. As Nozick (1974, p. 172) put
it:
These principles involve a shift from the classical liberals’ notion of self-ownership to
a notion of (partial) property rights in other people.
Most libertarians think that there’s at least a grain of truth in Nozick’s statement. And at first
glance, the principle of self-ownership does seem very plausible. We recognize people as self-
owners when we recognize that there are things that may not be done to a person without
their consent, but which may be done with that consent. For instance, we consider rape wrong
because it involves a body being used against the will of the person to whom it belongs. We
consider assault wrong for similar reasons. We consider (nonvoluntary) slavery wrong because
it presupposes that one is owned by others, not oneself.
Moreover, the principle of self-ownership is attractive for more theoretical reasons as well. It
is a strong endorsement of the moral importance and the sovereignty of the individual, it
expresses a deep respect for individuals’ status as autonomous and self-directed persons, it
refuses to treat persons as interchangeable objects (things that may be traded off for each
other) or beings that can be used for our purposes rather than theirs, and it seems to provide
a clear and simple starting point for our thinking about justice.
Nevertheless, this principle has turned out to be very controversial. Most important, self-
ownership has a number of counterintuitive implications. For instance, this view denies that
individuals have an obligation to help others in need, except through voluntary agreement or
prior wrongdoing. After all, any other such obligation would constitute a claim by others on
one’s life, labor, or person. Similarly, self-ownership seems to deny that it can be permissible
to use people in order to help others, even when those others are in extreme need and the use
is very insignificant (e.g., to gently push an innocent bystander in order to save 10 innocent
lives). Again, since individuals are normatively separate, their persons may not be used
nonconsensually, even for the benefit of others.
These implications seem extremely counterintuitive. When a person can be saved from
something very bad by using another person at no significant cost to that person, there seem
to be very demanding (indeed, potentially obligating) moral reasons to do so. Yet the full self-
ownership principle denies this.
1
The principle thus seems overly restrictive.
1
Page 4 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Another way in which full self-ownership may be too restrictive is that recognizing people’s
rights as full self-owners means condemning as wrongful even very minor infringements—the
kind of infringements that are practically necessary for everyday life to be possible. Consider,
for example, the possibility that tiny bits of pollution may fall upon unconsenting persons
when we drive a car. If self-ownership means that this is impermissible, then it seems that
driving cars is impermissible. Of course, there are many more such scenarios. Self-ownership
thus may end up prohibiting many of life’s activities. This is neither plausible nor much of a
theory that purports to take freedom very seriously
2
(Railton, 2003; Sobel, 2012).
These objections all take aim at one particular version of the idea of self-ownership: one that
understands the protections that self-ownership offers in their strongest possible form. Let us
call this full self-ownership.
3
While this version of libertarianism may be the most distinctive,
and is definitely the most often discussed and attacked, few libertarians actually hold this
position. Most libertarians, that is, endorse a conception of self-ownership that is weakened
along one or several dimensions in order to avoid these objections.
Consider, for instance, the following response to the objection that self-ownership is too
restrictive. Suppose that we understand the moral benefits that self-ownership is supposed to
confer on persons along the following two dimensions: one protecting persons from unwanted
uses of their bodies, and the other offering them the liberty to use their bodies. As the
objection points out, it is not possible to simultaneously maximize the value of both
dimensions—the protections that we have restrict the possible uses by others of their bodies—
and maximizing the protection-dimension implausibly restricts the use-dimension. The correct
response, however, would not be to reject self-ownership, but rather to loosen the protection
dimension somewhat in order to enhance the use dimension. Doing this would allow minor
infringements for the sake of self-ownership. As Eric Mack (2015) puts it, a good theory of
self-ownership offers people some “elbow room” (for a similar argument, see Brennan & Van
der Vossen, 2017).
4
Other Routes to Libertarianism
Weakened conceptions of self-ownership, however, raise important questions. For one, if self-
ownership turns out to have multiple dimensions, it loses some of its theoretic appeal. After
all, part of that appeal was the idea’s relative simplicity, which seemed to make it a good
starting point for a theory of political philosophy. If that is lost, libertarian theory might be in
need of additional support. Moreover, and second, if trade-offs are possible between those
dimensions, we will want to know why we might sacrifice one of the dimensions for the sake of
another. And in order to answer that question, we may need to invoke some further,
underlying value. Presumably, foundational principles are not based on underlying values.
Perhaps as a result of this, few libertarians actually treat the idea of self-ownership as a
foundational principle. That is, while most libertarians see self-ownership as a morally
important idea, few treat it as the starting point of their theories.
5
Instead, they seek to
develop theories that (a) honor people as rights-holders, sovereign individuals, whom we need
to treat as the primary claimants of their lives and bodies, while (b) avoiding many of the more
implausible elements of the maximally protection version of self-ownership. None of these
theories see self-ownership as self-evident or foundational. It is not the starting point or
2
3
4
5
Page 5 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
foundational premise of the theory of libertarian justice—something that does not need
defense itself. Rather, self-ownership becomes the conclusion—the thing that one ends up
endorsing in light of all the competing moral reasons and considerations.
Once we shed the idea that self-ownership must count as a foundational premise, there are
many different ways in which one might arrive at libertarian conclusions. Eric Mack (2002,
2010), for example, offers an argument for self-ownership, as one of several natural rights,
that is grounded in our nature as purposive beings. The protections and freedoms offered by
the idea are justified in order to grant to all individuals a separate sphere in which they can
act in accordance to their self-chosen purposes. Loren Lomasky (1987) derives personal rights
from a similar, if slightly different, idea about people as project pursuers. John Tomasi (2012)
holds that strong rights over our bodies are required by the ideal of democratic legitimacy.
And so on.
Another prominent example is a tradition of thought that invokes insights from economics.
Sometimes these arguments are consequentialist in nature, pointing out that overall human
welfare is best achieved in free societies (Epstein, 1995, 1998; Friedman, 1962). Others
maintain that a proper appreciation of justice as a principle of mutual advantage closely fits
the principles of a free society, including those of a market economy (Schmidtz, 2006).
Another example holds that libertarian or classical liberal conclusions follow from certain
themes in the Rawlsian tradition, such as the idea of democratic legitimacy (Tomasi, 2012) or
the nature of public reason justification (Gaus, 2012).
One influential strand of thinking in this tradition, closely related to F. A. Hayek and Ludwig
von Mises, argues that libertarian or classical liberal political conclusions follow from human
epistemic limitations. Free societies, and in particular free market systems, allow and
incentivize individuals to act on the information that they possess about their local
circumstances, needs, and desires, as well as their productive abilities and the trade-offs that
those might present. Any society that wants to deviate from this, the argument goes, will have
to collect, process, and fully understand all this dispersed and complex information, aggregate
it into some kind of social welfare function, and assign goods accordingly. This latter process
is simply beyond our capabilities. Free societies thus will predictably outperform other
societies on most important metrics (Hayek, 1960, 1973; Von Mises, 1949).
It is worth noting here that even though Nozick is often seen as someone who treats self-
ownership as a premise or foundational principle, it is far from clear whether this is a correct
reading of his viewpoint. One problem with this interpretation is that Nozick invokes the idea
of self-ownership only once in Anarchy, State, and Utopia—in the passage quoted in the
previous section of this article. The idea simply does not seem to do much work for him in
terms of supporting his arguments.
Second, if Nozick thought that full self-ownership was foundational, much of Part II of
Anarchy, State, and Utopia becomes very difficult to understand. There, he develops a large
number of arguments directed against redistributive conceptions of justice, many of which do
not invoke the idea of self-ownership at all. If that idea was his starting point, then none of
those arguments would be necessary, and so their presence (or prominence) would not make
much sense.
Page 6 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Perhaps most problematically, though, Nozick invoked ideas that directly contradict reading
him as a proponent of full self-ownership as a foundational principle. He argued that this idea
expresses the Kantian requirement that we treat people only as ends in themselves, and he
accepted that any plausible theory of rights must allow that they can be overridden in order to
prevent “catastrophic moral horror” (Nozick, 1974, p. 30). It seems, then, that self-ownership
is the view at which Nozick arrives, on the combined strength of all the arguments that he
provides, and so is not his foundational principle (Brennan & Van der Vossen, 2017).
Property and Distribution
It is distinctive of libertarian and classical liberal theories that they conceive of distributive
justice as largely (and sometimes exclusively) historical in nature. Even though distributional
issues can be relevant for assessing the justice of a society (a point that will be discussed in
more detail later in this article), libertarians generally see people’s rightful possessions as
whatever they acquired in legitimate (i.e., rights-respecting) ways.
The most common mode of just acquisition is through the legitimate transfer of prior just
holdings. This is why libertarians generally defend noncoerced, nondeceptive market relations
as just. Of course, not all modes of legitimate acquisition can depend on prior just holdings—
there must be a starting point, an original acquisition. Libertarians generally accept that
individuals can carry out such acts of original acquisition. More precisely, they accept that
individuals can acquire unowned goods unilaterally, without having to ask the consent of
approval of other people, some governing body, or anything else.
The most famous account of such original acquisition remains Locke’s labor theory. According
to Locke, when people work on previously unowned objects, subject to certain provisos, they
turn those objects into their private property. The precise nature of Locke’s argument, the
relation between labor and acquisition, as well as the nature of the provisos, are hotly
contested. The most famous version of this concept holds that through laboring, people quite
literally extend their claims of self-ownership over these external objects, thus drawing them
into their rights-protected sphere. As Locke (1690, chapter V) put it, laboring means mixing
one’s (owned) labor with an (unowned) thing.
This argument suffers from some well-known problems. For one, since laboring is an activity,
the idea of mixing it with an object seems at best a metaphor for something else. But in that
case, the argument is incomplete—we still need to know what really grounds property rights
(Waldron, 1988). Second, it simply is not true that mixing something owned with something
unowned is sufficient for appropriation. As Nozick (1974) pointed out, if I pour a can of
tomato juice that I own into the unowned ocean, I lose my tomato juice—I do not gain an
ocean. Third, if labor-mixing really were sufficient for generating claims in objects, why
should this be restricted to unowned goods? Why not say that mixing my labor with something
already owned generates a claim of coownership (Thomson, 1990, pp. 326–327)?
In light of these and other objections, many have offered different defenses of private
property. They point out the central moral importance of people having security over external
resources, whether this is understood in terms of support for political and civil liberties (Gaus,
2010), our ability to be project pursuers or purposive agents (Lomasky, 1987; Mack, 2010), or
the ability to be the authors of our lives (Tomasi, 2012).
Page 7 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
One influential argument ties the justification of property to the material prosperity and well-
being that it brings about. Rights of private property serve to divide the external world into a
number of discrete, individual parts, each exclusively controlled by its particular owner.
Organizing the social world in this way is preferable to collective use or ownership because it
helps avoid collective action problems. When things remain held in an open-access commons,
we all have an incentive to use as much as we can, leading to a general pattern of use that
ends up depleting the resource, to everyone’s detriment. Rights to private property not only
avoid such a “tragedy of the commons,” they also incentivize people to preserve their parts,
increase their productivity, and exchange what they own with others on mutually beneficial
terms (Schmidtz, 1994; Buchanan, 1993).
The justification of property provided by arguments like these does not rest on the principle of
self-ownership. As a result, it is not committed to seeing property rights as in any way
absolute, immune to just regulation, or even precluding any and all forms of taxation. Despite
what is sometimes suggested (Freeman, 2001), virtually all libertarians that reject self-
ownership as a starting point also accept that property rights need specification, can be
instantiated in quite different, yet morally acceptable forms, and might be overridden by other
moral considerations.
Such views do not entail the impossibility of unilateral original appropriation either.
Libertarians typically agree that people do not need the consent of others to bring about
property rights. People do not need the permission of others before they can begin using the
external world to provide for their own needs, as well as those of others. The moral benefits of
private ownership are important, and if there is a good justification for having a system of
private property, it should be possible to derive a justification for acts that begin to bring
about such rights as well (Van der Vossen, 2009; Mack, 2010).
6
Because libertarians take property rights very seriously and understand distributive justice in
largely historical terms, they are skeptical about the moral importance of distributions and
material equality. More precisely, they see a strong concern with material equality as
inconsistent with an appropriate concern for people’s moral equality. Since treating people as
moral equals means respecting them as the holders of rights, and since such rights are
resistant to policies aimed at equalizing material outcomes, such policies count as unjust.
Nozick (1974), in his famous discussion How Liberty Upsets Patterns, argues that because any
system of property must allow gifts and other voluntary transfers, and because these will
significantly upset whatever distribution is put in place, there is very limited room for
concerns with distributional equality. Others have argued that a concern for equality requires
treating people as equals—something that includes taking them seriously as rights-holders,
people who enjoy significant freedom to dispose of their property. However, treating people as
equals in this way often will produce unequal outcomes, in which case equalizing outcomes
itself violates the demands of equality (Schmidtz, 2006). Many others have offered different
arguments. For instance, Gerald Gaus (2010) argues that within public reason justification,
property rights would receive a kind of priority over redistributive goals (because of their
strong support for civil and political liberties).
None of this is to say that libertarians are not concerned with distributions at all. John Tomasi
(2012, p. 127) argues that many libertarians and classical liberals are committed to a kind of
distributive condition requiring that societies must be expected to work to the benefit of the
6
Page 8 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
least well-off. This seems to overstate the matter considerably, but it is certainly true that
many libertarians see their policies as promoting the general good, and this plays an
important role in their justification. Hence, libertarians are wont to point out that being poor
in a free society is much better than being poor elsewhere, that markets in general do not
work to the detriment of the poor, and so on.
That said, some libertarians see their views as consistent with a strong commitment to
distributional equality. According to what are often called left-libertarians, we can accept a
very strong reading of the self-ownership principle without also accepting significant material
inequalities. As G. A. Cohen (1995) pointed out, the latter follows from the former only if one
also accepts that external resources are not jointly owned. Thus, by insisting on some version
of joint or collective ownership of the external world, left-libertarians try to sidestep Nozick’s
argument that redistributive taxation involves expropriating the labor of what should be self-
owners. Left-libertarians grant Nozick’s claim, but only insofar as people’s income represents
the value of their labor alone, not the value of the external world.
The idea, then, is that while individuals are free to unilaterally appropriate external goods,
that freedom is qualified in ways that preserves some degree of equality. Hillel Steiner (1994),
for example, argued that people have a claim to the equivalent of an equally valuable unused
part of the world. Thus, people who appropriate more than their per-capita share owe those
who thereby receive less than their share of compensation. Michael Otsuka (2003) offers a
different interpretation, arguing that appropriation is constrained by the demand that others
have an opportunity for well-being that is at least as good as the opportunity received by the
appropriators.
Left-libertarians typically assert that this egalitarian demand follows from Locke’s proviso that
appropriators leave “enough and as good” for others. As a reading of Locke, this is highly
implausible. However, with some notable exceptions (Rothbard, 1978, 1982; Narveson, 1988,
chapter 7; Narveson, 1988; Feser, 2005), most libertarians agree that there is no unqualified
right to appropriate external goods. That said, most accept a far more constrained, and
therefore less egalitarian, interpretation of Locke’s requirement.
Thus, Nozick argued that no individual should be made worse off by the introduction of
private property. Eric Mack (2010) proposes a proviso aimed at securing a robust concept of
self-ownership for all. And Loren Lomasky (1987) has proposed that others must be left a
sufficient share of natural resources (for a similar take on Locke, see Simmons, 1992).
The State
Libertarians tend to be highly skeptical of political authority and state legitimacy. Such
skepticism follows readily from the principle of self-ownership, which requires that all agents
respect the moral rights of individuals, such as their rights over their persons and their
legitimate possessions. States, including the modern welfare state, fail to meet this standard
in rather spectacular fashion. Thus, many of the powers of the modern state are incompatible
with self-ownership.
Page 9 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
As before, however, it is important that much less controversial principles support similar
conclusions. Philosophical skepticism about state authority can be grounded in the widely
endorsed idea that people are, quite simply, not naturally subordinated to others. In this view,
something like voluntary consent or acceptance is required for people to be subject to the
authority of the state. For many, states have failed to satisfy this requirement.
Such philosophical anarchism, as it is often called, does not presuppose, but instead lends
support for libertarian views. The main reason for states being illegitimate is that they use
force where, absent consent or something similar, force is impermissible. States violate
people’s rights when they punish (or threaten to punish) a person for activities that endanger
no one else, such as riding a motorcycle without a helmet, taking drugs, refusing to purchase
health insurance, engaging in consensual sexual relations, or gambling. States violate
people’s rights when they expropriate their rightful possessions, impose unjust taxes, commit
fraud, or demand bribes. States violate people’s rights when they forcibly prevent them from
innocently contracting and associating with others, exercising their religion, occupy certain
professions because of their ethnic background, gender, or sexual orientation, and much,
much more.
Even though libertarians are generally quite hostile to state authority, this does not mean that
the state cannot permissibly undertake certain minimal activities. This includes most
obviously the enforcement of individual rights and freedoms. These activities do not
presuppose state authority since such activities are permissible with or without people’s prior
consent (unless, of course, such activities involve the violation of rights themselves).
Some controversy surrounds the question of whether people can be legitimately taxed to
finance these permissible state activities. Some think so, on the grounds that, roughly stated,
people can be required to pay for the morally permissible activity of rights enforcement
(Hayek, 1960). However, this is a difficult argument to sustain, for it remains unclear why the
very same ideas that require consent for other worthy state activities would not also require
consent for the financing of rights enforcement.
Of course, much of modern life seems to require a state. States structure and regulate much
of human life, they maintain peace and order, and they provide important public goods. And
while in most countries throughout history and around the world, the state has been a major
source of violence and oppression, there is no denying that many states also do many valuable
things. To many, then, the state seems indispensable. And to many, this seems a good
argument for thinking, contrary to libertarianism, that the state must be justifiable in some
way or other.
One popular argument for state authority holds that states can be legitimate if they are
democratic. Libertarians tend to be very skeptical about this view. A large body of empirical
findings has shown that voters tend to be radically uninformed, ignorant, and indeed biased
about political issues. And democratic deliberation does little, if anything, to improve this.
Indeed, it seems like it is rational for people to remain ignorant about politics. Given that
one’s causal influence on the quality of political decisions is negligible, and it is costly in
terms of time and effort to become informed, it is rational for people to remain ignorant. Most
people thus vote in ways that have more to do with signaling their ideological allegiance or
virtues, and less with the merits of the issues (Caplan, 2008; Somin, 2016; Brennan, 2016;
Pincione & Tesón, 2011).
Page 10 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
In addition to voter ignorance, many libertarians fear the more general dynamics of state
power. Public choice theory points out that since the best way to understand the behavior of
political agents is along roughly maximizing lines, there is little reason to think that the state
will generally behave in the public interest (Tullock & Buchanan, 1962). Thus, many
government policies impose widely dispersed costs on the populace to confer localized
benefits on a few, often politically well connected elites. Examples include the large-scale
bailouts of financial companies and agricultural subsidies.
Libertarians are not only skeptical about the benefits of politics. They also tend to be
optimistic about the possibility of bringing about the benefits that states can offer in
noncoercive, voluntary ways. Thus, libertarians see the anarchic provision of order and public
goods, as well as charitable giving, as genuinely viable options for addressing many of the
problems that states might solve, without many of the extremely negative results that states
cause (Huemer, 2012; Chartier, 2012).
International Issues
Libertarian principles apply not only within the boundaries of a state. The limited role that
libertarians see for legitimate government affects both domestic and foreign policy. Because
the main role of legitimate government is the upholding of individual rights, libertarians are
highly critical of the foreign policy of their governments, as well as many international
institutions and laws. The following sections give three examples of such issues.
Just War and Intervention
Given that libertarians see the enforcement of rights as the main justification for the use of
force, they insist on very strict limits to the war-making capacities of states. Thus, in principle,
wars might be waged only in self-defense or in the defense of others. Libertarians typically
dismiss ideas such as that war might be justified to safeguard national independence, culture,
or other common rationales. At the same time, to be justified, such wars must be carried out
in accordance with people’s rights. Thus, there will be strict limits in terms of collateral
damage, the ways in which innocent third parties might be harmed, and other considerations
(Machan & Rasmussen, 1995).
That said, libertarians are divided on how far these principles might go in defending actual
wars, and interventionist wars in particular. While most libertarians see their skepticism of
state power as extending to this issue, and thus oppose interventionist foreign policy, some
have defended foreign military interventions as a way of defending the liberty and rights of
people against oppression.
This issue is difficult because different parts in the libertarian theory pull in opposing
directions. On the one hand, libertarians generally accept that it is permissible to defend the
freedom and rights of others, including with force if need be. This suggests a rather
straightforward defense of foreign intervention as a means of protecting freedom. On the
other hand, many libertarians also question the justification and benefits of many state
activities, on the grounds that they often have unintended harmful consequences and are done
for questionable reasons. Indeed, military interventions have a history of making things
Page 11 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
worse, not better. It comes as no surprise, then, that the history of intervention is one in which
things rarely get better and often get even worse (for discussion of both sides of this
argument, see Tesón & Van der Vossen, 2017).
International Trade
The easiest issue, in libertarian terms, concerns international trade. Libertarians defend free
trade worldwide. They oppose state subsidies for domestic companies and favor abolishing all
import taxes. These policies are unjustifiable on the grounds that they coercively interfere
with the freedom of people to exchange their legitimately earned goods. And they are deeply
harmful to both the domestic public, which has to pay the higher price of goods that results
from these subsidies and taxes, and to foreign producers and consumers, who lose access to
valuable markets and products (Tesón, 2012; Lomasky & Tesón, 2015).
One notable background issue here concerns the relevant form of analysis for international
trade. Many nonlibertarians think about the ethics of international trade in terms of
establishing some kind of fair or level playing field for countries around the world. In this
view, the ethics of trade is primarily a matter of doing right by countries. Contrary to this,
libertarians insist that the ethics of trade is understood in individualist terms. The main
wrongs are the result of states (of already questionable legitimacy) coercively interfering with
trade in the international realm in ways that we would never accept in a domestic setting.
Immigration
Virtually all libertarians are highly skeptical of global migration restrictions. Because people
have a right to free movement unless there is some overriding justification for restricting
them, the practice of states to forcibly prevent large numbers of innocent people from
migrating from one place to another is plainly unjustified. Migration restrictions thus violate
the rights of those migrants who did not consent or otherwise authorize states to interfere
with their lives in these ways. Moreover, states that impose migration restrictions also violate
the rights of those among their own subjects who would like to associate, contract, and
otherwise interact with those foreigners who are prevented from arriving. As a result,
libertarians typically favor radically open borders.
A small, but notable minority disagrees, on the ground that large-scale migration might
undercut the institutional preconditions for free movement. James Buchanan (1995), for
instance, has argued that immigration may be restricted because it is impossible to know
exactly what the results will be of allowing many outsiders into a liberal society, and that
those consequences will be practically impossible to undo once the precarious balance that
supports freedom is disturbed. This argument, however, seems to beg the question of whether
states can prioritize the freedom and well-being of their subjects over the freedom and well-
being of foreigners in the first place. Pointing out that there are benefits to be had from doing
so, if indeed there are, does little to answer that question.
7
References
Barnett, R. (1998). The structure of liberty: Justice and the rule of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
7
Page 12 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Brennan, J. (2016). Against democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Brennan, J., & van der Vossen, B. (2017). The myths of the self-ownership thesis. In J. Brennan,
B. van der Vossen, & D. Schmidtz (Eds.), Routledge handbook of libertarianism. New York:
Routledge.
Buchanan, J. (1993). Property as a guarantor of liberty. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.
Buchanan, J. (1995). A two-country parable. In W. Schwartz (Ed.), Justice in immigration (pp. 63–
66). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Caplan, B. (2008). The myth of the rational voter: Why democracies choose bad policies.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Chartier, G. (2012). Anarchy and legal order: Law and politics for a stateless society. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Cohen, G. A. (1995). Self-ownership, freedom, and equality. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Feser, E. (2005). There Is No Such Thing As An Unjust Initial Acquisition. Social Philosophy and
Policy, 22, 56–80.
Epstein, R. (1995). Simple rules for a complex world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Epstein, R. (1998). Principles for a free society: Reconciling individual liberty with the common
good. New York: Basic Books.
Freeman, S. (2001). Illiberal libertarians: Why libertarianism is not a liberal view. Philosophy &
Public Affairs, 30(2), 105–151.
Friedman, M. (1962). Capitalism and freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gaus, G. (2010). Coercion, ownership, and the redistributive state: Justificatory liberalism’s
classical tilt. Social Philosophy and Policy, 27(1), 233–275.
Gaus, G. (2012). The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and
bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Grunebaum, J. (1987). Private ownership. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Hayek, F. A. (1960). The constitution of liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1973). Law, legislation, and liberty, Vol. 1: Rules and order. New York: Routledge.
Huemer, M. (2012). The problem of political authority. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Locke, J. (1690). Two treatises of government. P. Laslett (Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Lomasky, L. (1987). Persons, rights, and the moral community. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lomasky, L., & Tesón, F. (2015). Justice at a distance: Extending freedom globally. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Page 13 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Machan, T., & Rasmussen, D. (Eds.). (1995). Liberty for the 21st century. Lanham: Rowman and
Littlefield.
Mack, E. (2002). Self-ownership, marxism, and egalitarianism: Part II: Challenges to the self-
ownership thesis. Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, 1(2), 237–276.
Mack, E. (2010). The natural right of property. Social Philosophy and Policy, 27(1), 53–78.
Mack, E. (2015). Elbow room for rights. Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, 1(1), 194–221.
Mossoff, A. (Ed.). (2013). Intellectual property and property rights. Northampton, MA: Edward
Elgar.
Narveson, J. (1988). The libertarian idea. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Narveson, J., & Sterba, J. P. (2010). Are liberty and equality compatible? Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.
Otsuka, M. (2003). Libertarianism without inequality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pincione, G., & Tesón, F. (2011). Rational choice and democratic deliberation: A theory of
discourse failure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Railton, P. (2003). Locke, Stock, and Peril: Natural Property Rights, Pollution, and Risk. In P.
Railton, Facts, Values, and Norms (pp. 187–225). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rothbard, M. (1978). For a New Liberty, The Libertarian Manifesto. Revised edn. New York:
Libertarian Review Foundation.
Rothbard, M. (1982). The ethics of liberty. London: Humanities Press.
Rasmussen, D., & Den Uyl, D. (2005). Norms of liberty: A perfectionist basis for non-
perfectionist politics. University Park: Penn State University Press.
Schmidtz, D. (1994). The institution of property. Social Philosophy and Policy, 11(2), 42–62.
Schmidtz, D. (2006). The elements of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shapiro, D. (2007). Is the welfare state justified? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Simmons, A. (1992). The Lockean theory of rights. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Sobel, D. (2012). Backing Away from Libertarian Self-Ownership. Ethics, 123, 32–60.
Somin, I. (2016). Democracy and political ignorance: Why smaller government is smarter (2d
ed.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Steiner, H. (1994). An essay on rights. Oxford: Blackwell.
Tesón, F. (2012). Why free trade is required by justice. Social Philosophy and Policy, 29(1), 126–
153.
Page 14 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
Tesón, F., & van der Vossen, B. (2017). Debating humanitarian intervention: Should we try to
help? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thomson, J. (1990). The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasi, T. (2012). Free market fairness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Tullock, G., & Buchanan, J. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional
democracy.
Vallentyne, P. (1998). Critical notice of G. A. Cohen’s self-ownership, freedom, and equality.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 28, 609–626.
Vallentyne, P., & Van der Vossen, B. (2014). Libertarianism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford
encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Available online <https://
plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/libertarianism/> at https://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/fall2014/entries/libertarianism/ <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/
libertarianism/>.
Van der Vossen, B. (2009). What counts as original appropriation? Politics, Philosophy, &
Economics, 8(4), 355–373.
Von Mises, L. (1949). Human action: A treatise on economics. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Waldron, J. (1988). The right to private property. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Wall, S. (2009). Self-ownership and paternalism. Journal of Political Philosophy, 17(4), 399–417.
Notes
1. It is worth noting that on at least some readings, the principle need not rule out an unenforceable obligation to
save people. For a discussion of this point, see Vallentyne and Van der Vossen (2014).
2. Steven Wall (2009) has made a similar argument, pointing out that full self-ownership implausibly rules out even
soft paternalism.
3. To be a self-owner means, roughly, to have moral rights over oneself that are similar to the rights that one can have
when one owns inanimate objects. As with the broader idea of ownership, there are stronger and weaker versions of
self-ownership. Full self-ownership, then, is the idea that people have a maximal, universalizable set of claims and
liberties to control and dispose of their persons and bodies.
4. Note that, strictly speaking, this response does not entail rejecting full self-ownership. After all, the version of the
idea that reduces the protection dimension in order to enhance the use-dimension still can be within the set of
maximal univeralizable claims.
5. For instance, full self-ownership seems to permit voluntary enslavement. Agents have, it claims, not only the right to
control the use of their person, but also the right to transfer that right (e.g., by sale or gift) to others. But this is a
matter of controversy even among libertarians. Some, such as Rothbard (1982) and Barnett (1998), deny that such
transfer is even possible because others cannot control one’s will. Others, such as Locke (1690) and Grunebaum
Page 15 of 15
Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a
single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).
Subscriber: Chapman University; date: 19 February 2021
(1987), deny that the rights over oneself are so transferable, typically on the ground that such transfers undermine
one’s autonomy. Yet others disagree, seeing voluntary enslavement as indeed consistent with full self-ownership. (See
Vallentyne, 1998; Steiner, 1994.)
6. While libertarians are generally in broad agreement about the justification of property rights in external goods, they
remain divided about the justification of intellectual property rights. Some consider them crucial for incentivizing the
creation of new and better intellectual goods, while others see such rights as problematic impositions of monopoly
power by the state, excluding innocent people from the use of available resources. (See the collection of essays in
Mossoff, 2013.)
7. This argument sets aside the further objection that libertarians generally deny that the mere fact that something
produces a benefit is sufficient justification for bringing it about.
Related Articles
Equality and Political Philosophy
Exploitation
Basic Income
Paternalism
Justice Between Generations
Liberalism
Freedom of Speech