Brennan Center for Justice at New York University School of Law
PROTESTS, INSURRECTION, AND THE SECOND AMENDMENT
African Americans and
the Insurrectionary
Second Amendment
By Darrell A. H. Miller, Melvin G. Shimm Professor of Law, Duke Law School
PUBLISHED JUNE 2021
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
2
Introduction
Insurrectionist theories of the Second Amendment typically begin with Thomas Jefferson and Lexington,
Massachusetts, rather than Cato and Charleston, South Carolina. To an external observer unfamiliar with
American history and inclined to take the framers’ generation at their word, the moral and historical
foundations of the insurrectionary Second Amendment must look bizarre. Instead of building an insurrectionist
theory around the one group — enslaved Africans who, by the framers’ own measure, had the most right to
resist tyranny, we have a Second Amendment theory of righteous revolution built on the grievances of slave
owners. But the peculiarity does not stop there. It must seem equally odd to this outsider that Second
Amendment insurrectionist theory never adequately accounts for the fact that this one group, African
Americans with centuries of moral justification behind them decided in the middle of the 20th century to
reject violent political dynamism in favor of nonviolence. Instead of using the insurrectionist theory of the
Second Amendment to bolster a separatist movement in the South or justify a sustained campaign of political
violence against Jim Crow and its enablers, African Americans and their allies in the 1950s and60s committed
themselves to passive resistance, moral suasion, and peaceful regime change.
What would Second Amendment insurrectionism look like if it started with the enslaved African and ended
with the march across the Edmund Pettus Bridge? This essay attempts to reckon with these twin paradoxes and
reorient our thinking about the credibility of the insurrectionary Second Amendment.
The Insurrectionary Second Amendment
America’s founding fathers were slaves — at least, that’s how they described themselves.
1
“‘Slavery’ was a
central concept in 18th century political discourse.”
2
It was “the absolute political evil” and during the
Revolutionary era manifested in “every statement of political principle, in every discussion of constitutionalism
or legal rights, in every exhortation to resistance.”
3
John Dickinson, Josiah Quincy, and John Adams all
referred to themselves as “slaves” when describing their political powerlessness.
4
Slavery in 18th-century terms
connoted a “specific political condition,” one marked by total subjugation, a manifest incapacity to maintain
any material interest or abstract right. It was an evil in itself, an intolerable abasement of the human condition
quite apart from any physical harm that the despot did or did not inflict.
5
As John Locke wrote, “he who makes
an attempt to enslave me, thereby puts himself into a State of War with me.”
6
And the threat to the colonists of
being reduced to slavery justified any measure of resistance, even violence.
Although the Declaration of Independence asserts that the justification for violent revolution is “self-evident,” it
offers reasons out of “a decent respect to the opinions of mankind.” The colonists claimed to have suffered a
“long train of abuses and usurpations . . . design[ed] to reduce them under absolute Despotism.” Under such
conditions, “it is their right, it is their duty, to throw off such Government” and form a new one.
7
The bill of
particulars against King George includes, among other evils,
kidnapping and transportation away to foreign shores;
8
withdrawing protection from the violence of others,
9
including denying victims justice for such violence;
10
the imposition of foreign laws, in derogation of the common law;
11
the denial of trial by jury;
12
the denial of trade;
13
and
the dissolution of assemblies for having asserted the rights of the people.
14
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
3
The Declaration insists that violent revolution was the last resort, the result of every reasonable, peaceful
petition to both the government of England and its people being rebuffed. It ends with an injunction that the
English remember “the circumstances of [American] emigration and settlement here.”
15
Nine decades later, the newly created Confederate States of America would take up the tropes of slavery and
debasement and resistance to justify their own attempt to violently overthrow the government and preserve a
slaveocracy. Jefferson Davis, in justifying the Southern rebellion, cited the Declaration in his inaugural address:
[G]overnments rest on the consent of the governed, and that it is the right of the people to alter or
abolish them at will whenever they become destructive of the ends for which they were established. . . .
In this [the Confederate States] merely asserted the right which the Declaration of Independence of
July 4, 1776, defined to be “inalienable.”
16
The Mississippi Declaration of the Causes of Secession warned that
[u]tter subjugation awaits us in the Union, if we should consent longer to remain in it. It is not a matter
of choice, but of necessity. We must either submit to degradation . . . or we must secede from the Union
framed by our fathers, to secure this as well as every other species of property. For far less cause than
this, our fathers separated from the Crown of England.
17
Even after the Confederacy was crushed, its dead-enders who formed white supremacist terrorist organizations
like the Knights of the White Camellia and the Ku Klux Klan appealed to natural rights to resist tyranny. One of
the first questions to supplicants to the Klan was, “Do you believe in the inalienable right of self-preservation of
the people against the exercise of arbitrary and unlicensed power?
18
In America, “[the] right of revolution has been and is a part of the fabric of our institutions.”
19
However, unlike in
other nations,
20
and even some state constitutions,
21
a right to alter or abolish tyrannical government is not actually
set down in the American Constitution. It is expressed in the Declaration of Independence.
22
But the Declaration is
not law and does not command the same kind of respect in the political imagination as the Constitution.
Instead, the framing for a right to rebel against tyranny has migrated over the last half-century from a political
document (the Declaration of Independence) to a legal one (the Second Amendment). It appears in academic
journals that focus on gun regulations
23
or military encounters — especially the securing of arms as
precipitating the Revolution.
24
It shows up in alarming declarations like the one that the Second Amendment
“isn’t about hunting ducks; it’s about hunting politicians.”
25
The insurrectionary Second Amendment takes a
number of forms, but at its most plausible, it seems to contemplate some kind of ability of individuals to wage a
long-term guerilla campaign against the forces of despotismonce all the other forms of peaceful political
change have failed. A Ninth Circuit judge once referred to it as the “doomsday provision.”
26
Even the late
Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia, in his headier moments in District of Columbia v. Heller (2008),
seemed rapt about the idea of violent resistance to government, writing “when the able-bodied men of a nation
are trained in arms and organized, they are better able to resist tyranny.”
27
Almost always, though, the public image of Second Amendment insurrectionism is the minuteman with his
musket, tricorn hat, and Common Sense rolled up in his pocket or (in some quarters) the Confederate soldier
charging the Union line with his rifle in one hand and the Stars and Bars in the other. In the American
constitutional imagination, the right to resist tyranny is symbolized by the counterfeit slave, not the real one.
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
4
Slave Laws, Slave Revolts,
and Insurrectionist Theory
Even as Locke was writing down his political theory of justified rebellion (to be liberally borrowed by Thomas
Jefferson in 1776), the colonists were steadily degrading the material, legal, and political position of Africans in
North America.
28
Africans were brought to the swampy shores of Jamestown in 1619, and, following a brief
period of legal limbo, their treatment hardened into the brutal, hereditary, and thoroughly racialized form of
slavery that became the exceptional version of the institution in the United States.
South Carolina updated its Slave Act in 1701, which among other things authorized government officials to
impress local whites to chase down escapees and fined those whites who refused to be conscripted into service.
Whites performing this duty were permitted to beat and, if necessary, kill any enslaved person who resisted.
29
Authorities were permitted to search homes for runaways, and any person caught after an unsuccessful self-
emancipation was subject to castration (if male), cropping of ears, or (for repeat offenses) crippling by cutting
of the Achilles tendon.
30
In 1705, Virginia passed a similar “Act Concerning Servants and Slaves.” It confirmed the civil law concept of
partus sequitur ventremthat slave status was inherited through the mother — in derogation of English
common law. It criminalized marriage and sex between races. It empowered private citizens to capture and kill
those who attempted to emancipate themselves and authorized their mutilation upon return to their owners. It
cut off enslaved persons’ independent ability to engage in trade. It forbade slaves from carrying firearms. And it
reinforced the absolute power of the owner, specifying that owners be acquitted of murder “as if such incident
had never happened” if they should kill a slave for daring to resist his enslavement.
31
A 1712 slave rebellion scare in New York lead to brutal repression of suspected participants and imposition of
the “Act for preventing Suppressing and punishing the Conspiracy and Insurrection of Negroes and other
Slaves,” which prohibited slaves from owning property or arms, specified a set of punishments for harboring
slaves away from their owners without permission, created unique tribunals for slaves charged with capital
crimes, and essentially authorized cruel and exemplary punishments for murder and rape.
32
Although passed by different colonial legislatures, many features of these laws were similar. They
permitted the kidnapping, transportation, and sale of the enslaved from their homes to foreign places;
protected and encouraged the infliction of private violence on the enslaved;
imposed civil law concepts like partus sequitur ventrem on the enslaved and denied them the benefits of
common law;
denied the enslaved trial by a jury of their peers;
denied the enslaved the opportunity to engage in a trade;
denied the enslaved an ability to possess arms; and
punished assemblies and imposed group punishment for acts of rebellion or resistance.
Generations before Thomas Jefferson would itemize the abuses of George III (among them, the imposition of
laws alien to English common law; transportation to foreign shores across the sea; impressment of Americans
“to become the executioners of . . . friends and Brethren”; the cutting off of trade; the withdrawal of the
protection of the law), the colonists instituted their own “long train of abuses and usurpations” with respect to
African Americans.
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
5
Of course, such self-evident injustice was bound to provoke a response. One occurred just outside what was
then known as Charles Town (now Charleston), South Carolina. On an early Sunday morning in September
1739, a band of about 20 enslaved Africans, mostly Kongolese from modern-day Angola, assembled at the
western branch of the Stono River, about 20 miles from Charles Town.
33
The Kongolese were Catholic
Christians and “believed . . . them[selves] a distinctive people.”
34
Some of these men may have had military
training, and some may have been familiar with firearms.
35
Their leader was a man known as either Jemmy or
Cato, and their first act of rebellion was to seize the small arms and gunpowder at Hutchinson’s store near the
Stono River Bridge. They must have figured that if they got to the guns first, then freedom would soon follow.
After taking the weapons and killing the two men at the store, they marched southward, swelling in number
until they numbered nearly 100. They raised a standard and marched to the beat of drums and shouts of
“Liberty!” Their object was perhaps to cross through Georgia to what is now St. Augustine, Florida, where the
Spanish governor had proclaimed that any African who had escaped the British would be free.
They had to know that their actions, if they failed, would mean death. Individual acts of rebellion by the
enslaved had culminated in execution in the past.
36
Just that spring, in response to several serial cases of self-
emancipation and as a warning to others tempted to flee to freedom, one escapee was whipped and another
hanged and left to rot.
37
At the banks of the Edisto River, the rebels stopped, expecting their ranks to swell
further until they became an unstoppable train to freedom.
But by noon, whites in the county were on alert, and by mid-afternoon, a posse of close to 100 had assembled
and moved onto the rebels’ positions. The fight was not suppressed all at once. Employing what General George
Washington would later call a “war of posts” or “Fabian” strategy, the Stono rebels “withdrew after a brief
encounter, relocated, and fought several battles over a protracted period.”
38
Only after several weeks was the
bulk of the rebellion quashed, and even then, one leader remained at large and was only captured and executed
three years later. According to what amounts to the “official” report of the rebellion, the enslaved “fought for
Liberty and Life,” prompting a later commentator to ask whether the Stono rebels were “the first Revolutionary
Americans.”
39
The Stono Rebellion was just one of a series of insurrections by enslaved persons that began almost as soon as
Africans were brought to America and continued until the Thirteenth Amendment abolished de jure slavery in
the United States in 1865. The list is long.
In 1800, a man named Gabriel owned as chattel by Thomas Prosser planned an uprising near Richmond,
Virginia. He may have been inspired by the successful revolution of enslaved Africans on the island of Sainte-
Domingue, now Haiti, in the 1790s. Gabriel’s unsuccessful plot enlisted thousands of individuals and involved
homemade weapons and then a march to seize arms and ammunition at the magazine at Richmond.
40
He even
planned to hoist a standard with the echoes of Patrick Henry emblazoned upon it: “Death or Liberty!”
41
Approximately 20 years later, in South Carolina, a free Black man named Denmark Vesey preached against
slavery with appeals to Christian morality and the Declaration of Independence. His plan was to seize the
armories and stables in Charleston, South Carolina, at midnight on June 16, 1822. The plot was thwarted by
white military repression, but talk of an incipient battle for freedom remained for years after.
42
Seven years
following, the Christian mystic Nat Turner planned another uprising in Southampton, Virginia, in 1831 to take
place on July 4, “fifty-years from the day the Continental Congress approved the wording of the Declaration of
Independence.”
43
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
6
Then there are the hundreds of unnamed patriots whose names were never recorded, among them: The Black
insurrectionist who went to the gallows declaring, “I have nothing more to offer than what George Washington
would have had to offer, had he been taken by the British and put to trial by them. I have adventured my life in
endeavoring to obtain the liberty of my countrymen.”
44
The anonymous “Free Negro” who penned a 1789
article recognizing that the same efforts to obtain freedom for which whites were valorized as heroes and
martyrs are treated with derision and contempt when employed by African Americans.
45
“Do rights of nature
cease to be such when a Negro is to enjoy them?” the unnamed writer asked, “[o]r does patriotism in the heart
of an African rankle into treason?”
46
And of course, this list leaves out all the small, successful rebellions that occurred regularly in North America
from 1619 to the end of slavery in 1865: Men, women, children, and the old who self-emancipated at great risk
to themselves, their families, and those they left behind. A hundred thousand individual Lexingtons and
Concords.
47
Insurrectionism and the
American Civil Rights Movement
To a disinterested observer less invested in America’s founding myths and less inured to its hypocrisies,
America’s insurrectionary constitutionalism must look all wrong — wrong dates, wrong reasons, wrong people.
The model of righteous violence in service of liberty must be the self-emancipated African American slave who
overpowers and outwits her captors; it’s certainly not her owner. How much more incomprehensible it must
appear, then, that this same group African Americans with the most warrant to resort to political violence
foreswore that tool as a political strategy in the middle of the 1960s.
Although the Thirteenth Amendment formally ended slavery in 1865, and African Americans obtained
birthright citizenship in 1868 and the franchise (at least for males) in 1870, the social, material, and political
position of Africans in America remained stunted for more than a century afterward. Severe and violent
responses to even the most modest expression of African American social and political participation occurred
regularly from the Gilded Age to the early 1950s.
One would think that this legacy of oppression would have generated a broad and sustained guerilla campaign
in the United States by African Americans and their allies. But it did not. As far back as 1865, the predominant
goal of African Americans was to integrate into the political and social culture, not to separate from it. The
appeal from the “Address from the Colored Folk of Norfolk Virginia” declared that “We are Americans, we
know no other country, we love the land of our birth and our fathers.”
Even when African Americans’ peaceful attempts to assert basic social and political rights generated violent
backlash, civil rights soldiers were taught not to respond in kind. Legions of students some barely out of their
teens were trained to submit to public violence rather than lash out during the “sit-in” movement of the early
1960s, a movement that began with four young men from North Carolina A&T State University in a
Woolworths in Greensboro.
48
As the movement spread, it kept its focus on nonviolent direct action.
49
Martin Luther King Jr., articulating
his philosophy of nonviolent, passive resistance, said that one essential characteristic was “a willingness to
accept suffering without retaliation, to accept blows from the opponent without striking back.” It is the
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
7
sufferingand the love required to restore the community that is the central feature of this kind of
revolution.
50
This courage to renounce political violence was on full display on Edmund Pettus Bridge on Bloody Sunday,
March 7, 1965, in a march for voting rights. The images of Black martyrs and their allies, including a young
John Lewis, broken and bloody at the hands of state law enforcement, gripped the nation. President Lyndon
Johnson, for one, caught the significance of the event. Announcing his plans to send the Voting Rights Act to
Congress, he said this: “At times history and fate meet at a single time in a single place to shape a turning point
in man’s unending search for freedom. So it was at Lexington and Concord. So it was a century ago at
Appomattox. So it was last week in Selma, Alabama.”
51
Political Process, Political Morality,
and Equitable Estoppel
Political process theory, famously articulated in John Hart Ely’s Democracy and Distrust,
52
is a theory of
judicial review of political institutions when minorities are consistently on the losing end of every political
argument. But what happens when judicial review also fails? Isn’t that the moment when violent political
dynamism becomes the only recourse? And what happens when the group that is entitled to use such violence
rejects it, and instead opts for nonviolent resistance?
On January 6, 2021, mobilized by the most chimerical of threats, members of the ethnic majority assailed the
Capitol of the United States, leading to the deaths of five people. In a spectacular case of saying the quiet part
loud, a sitting senator of the United States, Ron Johnson of Wisconsin — who literally had to take refuge from
this mob said this about the January 6 insurrectionists: “Even though those thousands of people that were
marching to the Capitol were trying to pressure people like me to vote the way they wanted me to vote, I knew
those were people that love this country . . . so I wasn’t concerned. Now . . . had the tables been turned . . . and
those were tens of thousands of Black Lives Matter and Antifa protesters, I might have been a little concerned.”
The senator’s implication is as clear as it is despicable only whites can use violence to overthrow a white
man’s government.
But there’s also another principle coming from the history of African Americans and insurrectionary theory.
Call it the political morality version of equitable estoppel. Equitable estoppel is the legal doctrine that states
that courts will not grant relief to a party who has not acted fairly. When one party forbearsrepeatedly to
deploy the full force of the law in response to a clear breach of rights but instead seeks accommodation and
peaceful resolution, the counterparty is estopped from seeking punitive redress at the slightest failure in
performance by the other.
Translated into public morality, the argument goes like this: African Americans have 400 years of moral and
political justification to violently dissolve the bonds that tie them to this country and its political leaders, and
they’ve spent 400 years offering grace. As former President Barack Obama put it so eloquently during the 2020
presidential election campaign:
If anyone had a right to believe that this democracy did not work, and could not work, it was those
Americans. Our ancestors. They were on the receiving end of a democracy that had fallen short all their
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
8
lives. They knew how far the daily reality of America strayed from the myth. And yet, instead of giving
up, they joined together and said somehow, some way, we are going to make this work. We are going to
bring those words, in our founding documents, to life.
53
It is Black struggles, Black tolerances, and Black forbearance that set the baseline for the legitimate use of
political violence in America. It is theirs to claim, and only theirs. No one gets to cut in line; no one today
possesses a greater right to alter or abolish government through violent means. And as long as African
Americans continue to foreswear violence as a tool of political change in favor of nonviolence and a peaceful
political solution — as they’ve done in Norfolk, Virginia, in 1865, in Greensboro, North Carolina, in 1960, and in
Atlanta, Georgia, in 2021 then that grace continues to expose the lie of any lesser claim.
Thanks to Joseph Blocher, Jake Charles, and Alice Ristroph for their comments on this essay.
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
9
Endnotes
1
Jack M. Balkin & Sanford Levinson, The Dangerous Thirteenth Amendment, 112 C
OLUM
.
L.
R
EV
. 1459, 1482 (2012).
2
B
ERNARD
B
AILYN
,
T
HE
I
DEOLOGICAL
O
RIGINS OF THE
A
MERICAN
R
EVOLUTION
232 (50th anniv. ed. 2017).
3
Id.
4
Id. at 23233.
5
See id. at 234.
6
J
OHN
L
OCKE
,
T
WO
T
REATISES OF
G
OVERNMENT
297
(Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1988)
(1690) (emphasis in original).
7
T
HE
D
ECLARATION OF
I
NDEPENDENCE
para.
1,
2
(U.S.
1776).
8
Id. at para. 21 (“For transporting us beyond Seas to be tried for pretended offences.”).
9
Id. at para. 8 (“He has refused for a long time, after such dissolutions, to cause others to be elected; whereby the Legislative powers,
incapable of Annihilation, have returned to the People at large for their exercise; the State remaining in the mean time exposed to all the
dangers of invasion from without, and convulsions within.”); see also id. para. 25 (“He has abdicated Government here, by declaring us out
of his Protection and waging War against us.”).
10
Id. at para. 17 (“For protecting them, by a mock Trial, from punishment for any Murders which they should commit on the Inhabitants of
these States.”).
11
Id. at para. 15 (“He has combined with others to subject us to a jurisdiction foreign to our constitution, and unacknowledged by our laws;
giving his Assent to their Acts of pretended Legislation.”).
12
Id. at para. 20 (“For depriving us in many cases, of the benefits of Trial by Jury.”).
13
Id. at para. 18 (“For cutting off our Trade with all parts of the world.”).
14
Id. at para. 7 (“He has dissolved Representative Houses repeatedly, for opposing with manly firmness his invasions on the rights of the
people.”).
15
Id. at para. 31.
16
Jefferson Davis, Inaugural Address of the President of the Provisional Government (Feb. 18, 1861), http://avalon.law.yale.edu/19th
_century/csa_csainau.asp.
17
A Declaration of the Immediate Causes Which Induce and Justify the Secession of the State of Mississippi from the Federal Union
(1861), http://avalon.law.yale.edu/19th_century/csa_missec.asp
.
18
Organization and Principles of the Ku Klux Klan, reprinted in 1
D
OCUMENTS OF
A
MERICAN
H
ISTORY
500 (Henry Steele Commager ed.,
Prentice Hall 1975) (1938).
19
Scales v. United States, 367 U.S. 203, 269 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting).
20
See Tom Ginsburg, Daniel Lansberg-Rodriguez & Mila Versteeg, When to Overthrow Your Government: The Right to Resist in the
World’s Constitutions, 60 UCLA L. R
EV
. 1184, 1196206 (2013).
21
T
ENN
.
C
ONST
.
art.
I,
§
1
(describing “an unalienable and indefeasible right to alter, reform, or abolish the government”).
22
D
ECLARATION OF
I
NDEPENDENCE
, supra note 7.
23
See, e.g., David B. Kopel, How the British Gun Control Program Precipitated the American Revolution, 6 C
HARLESTON
L.
R
EV
. 283, 324
(2012) (“The British never lost sight of the fact that without their gun control program, they could never control America.”).
24
See Stephen P. Halbrook, Encroachments of the Crown on the Liberty of the Subject: Pre-Revolutionary Origins of the Second Amendment,
15 U.
D
AYTON
L.
R
EV
. 91, 119 (1989) (“[T]he British could not take away the arms of all of the people, and independence was won.”).
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
10
25
David C. Williams, The Militia Movement and Second Amendment Revolution: Conjuring with the People, 81 C
ORNELL
L.
R
EV
. 879, 952
(1996) (quoting Linda Thompson, Six O’Clock Newscast (Indianapolis Eyewitness News, May 1, 1995)).
26
Silveira v. Lockyer, 328 F.3d 567, 570 (9th Cir. 2003) (Kozinski, J., dissenting).
27
Dist. of Columbia v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 598 (2008).
28
For a discussion of Locke’s problematic contribution to this history, see David Armitage, John Locke, Carolina, and The Two Treatises of
Government, 32 P
OLITICAL
T
HEORY
602, 609 (2004).
29
L.H. Roper, The 1701 “Act for the Better Ordering of Slaves”: Reconsidering the History of Slavery in Proprietary South Carolina, 64
W
M
.
&
M
ARY
Q.
395, 40203 (2007).
30
Id.
31
An Act Concerning Servants and Slaves (1705), reprinted in 1 S
LAVERY IN THE
U
NITED
S
TATES
:
A
S
OCIAL
,
P
OLITICAL
,
AND
H
ISTORICAL
E
NCYCLOPEDIA
540
(Junius Rodriguez ed., 2007).
32
William M. Wiecek, The Origins of the Law of Slavery in British North America, 17 C
ARDOZO
L.
R
EV
. 1711, 176768 (1996).
33
Peter H. Wood, Anatomy of a Revolt, in S
TONO
:
D
OCUMENTING AND
I
NTERPRETING A
S
OUTHERN
S
LAVE
R
EVOLT
63
(Mark M. Smith ed.,
2005).
34
John K. Thornton, African Dimensions of the Stono Rebellion, 96 A
M
.
H
IST
.
R
EV
.
1101, 1103 (1991).
35
Id.
36
P
ETER
H.
W
OOD
,
B
LACK
M
AJORITY
:
N
EGROES IN
C
OLONIAL
S
OUTH
C
AROLINA FROM
1670
T
HROUGH THE
S
TONO
R
EBELLION
286 (1974).
37
Id. at 311.
38
Thornton, supra note 34, at 1113.
39
S
TONO
, supra note 33, at 28.
40
Gabriel’s Attempted Uprising in Richmond, 1800, in A
D
OCUMENTARY
H
ISTORY OF
S
LAVERY IN
N
ORTH
A
MERICA
(Willie Lee Rose ed., 1976).
41
Susan DeFord, Gabriel’s Rebellion, W
ASH
.
P
OST
(Feb. 6, 2000), https://www.washingtonpost.com/archive/lifestyle/2000/02/06/gabriels-
rebellion/33c9061a-e33d-4f18-bf02-fe3cd294f5df.
42
William J. Rich, Lessons of Charleston Harbor: The Rise, Fall and Revival of Pro-Slavery Federalism, 36 M
C
G
EORGE
L.
R
EV
.
569, 579
(2005).
43
Seth Davis, The Thirteenth Amendment and Self-Determination, 104 C
ORNELL
L.
R
EV
.
O
NLINE
88, 10001 (2019).
44
Id.
45
Peggy Cooper Davis, Neglected Stories and the Lawfulness of Roe v. Wade, 28 H
ARV
.
C.R.-C.L.
L.
R
EV
. 299, 390 (1993).
46
Herbert Aptheker, The Negro in the Abolitionist Movement, 5 S
CI
.
&
S
OC
Y
148,
153 (1941) (quoting T
HE
A
MERICAN
M
USEUM
, 1788, V, 72;
VI).
47
It is estimated that approximately 100,000 persons successfully escaped slavery in the United States. Mary Niall Mitchell et al.,
Rediscovering the Lives of the Enslaved People Who Freed Themselves, W
ASH
.
P
OST
(Feb. 20, 2019), https://www.washingtonpost.com
/outlook/2019/02/20/rediscovering-lives-enslaved-people-who-freed-themselves.
48
Even some civil rights revisionists like Charles Cobb Jr. recognize that the political tactics of the civil rights movement and the training of
the movement’s core figures was in nonviolent direct action, not guerilla warfare. See C
HARLES
E.
C
OBB
J
R
.,
T
HIS
N
ONVIOLENT
S
TUFF
LL
G
ET
Y
OU
K
ILLED
:
H
OW
G
UNS
M
ADE THE
C
IVIL
R
IGHTS
M
OVEMENT
P
OSSIBLE
16061
(2014).
49
Bayard Rustin saw nonviolent direct action as an alternative tool to violence. “The simple truth is this,” he wrote, “unless we find non-
violent methods which can be used by the rank-and-file who more and more tend to resist, they will more and more resort to violence.”
R
AYMOND
A
RSENAULT
, F
REEDOM
R
IDERS
:
1961
AND THE
S
TRUGGLE FOR
R
ACIAL
J
USTICE
31 (abridged ed. 2011).
Brennan Center for Justice African Americans and the Insurrectionary Second Amendment
11
50
Martin Luther King Jr., Pilgrimage to Nonviolence, in N
ONVIOLENCE IN
A
MERICA
:
A
D
OCUMENTARY
H
ISTORY
392 (Staughton Lynd and Alice
Lynd eds., 1966).
51
Lyndon B. Johnson, Special Message to the Congress: The American Promise (Mar. 15, 1965), http://www.lbjlibrary.org/lyndon-baines-
johnson/speeches-films/president-johnsons-special-message-to-the-congress-the-american-promise.
52
J
OHN
H
ART
E
LY
,
D
EMOCRACY AND
D
ISTRUST
:
A
T
HEORY OF
J
UDICIAL
R
EVIEW
87
(1980).
53
German Lopez, Obama’s Democratic Convention Speech Gave a Clear Warning: Democracy Is at Stake in 2020, V
OX
(Aug. 20, 2020),
https://www.vox.com/2020/8/20/21377118/obama-dnc-speech-trump-democracy-voting-rights
.