Indiana Journal of Law and Social Indiana Journal of Law and Social
Equality Equality
Volume 9 Issue 1 Article 4
1-26-2021
Honesty Is the Best Policy: Addressing Implicit Bias in the Honesty Is the Best Policy: Addressing Implicit Bias in the
Judiciary Judiciary
Catie Wheatley
Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ijlse
Part of the Law Commons
Publication Citation Publication Citation
Catie Wheatley, Honesty Is the Best Policy: Addressing Implicit Bias in the Judiciary, 9 Ind. J.L. & Soc.
Equality 94 (2021).
This Comment is brought to you for free and open access
by the Maurer Law Journals at Digital Repository @
Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana
Journal of Law and Social Equality by an authorized
editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
COMMENT
Honesty Is the Best Policy: Addressing Implicit Bias in the Judiciary
Catie Wheatley
INTRODUCTION
People are likely to have an image of the perfect judge. Perhaps a wise old
man in a long flowing robe sitting on high and handing down a measured and wise
judgment. King Solomon, for instance, is often referred to as an idealized impartial
judge.
1
Depictions show King Solomon on a throne with the requisite beard and
robes, and portray him as wise, authoritative, and unambiguously patriarchal. In
real life, however, judges are not godlike kings but mere mortals. And this is a good
thing. By allowing judges to be human we can escape a narrative that continues to
cast the aged, white, male patriarch as an infallible archetype. King Solomon’s
fallibility is evident: a judge who is willing to split a baby in half with a sword and
use maternal instincts against a woman in order to solve a fairly straightforward
problem.
2
But, if mythical perfection is out of the question, what does this mean for
judicial impartiality or the “capacity to decide cases with an open mind and without
bias for or against those who appear before [them]”?
3
It means that impartiality is,
as it always has been, an aspiration. It is a worthy aspiration. One on which it is
incumbent upon the legal profession to strive towards. But, as Charles Geyh et al.
describe it, a realistic assessment of impartiality is not a question of whether a
judge is impartial, but whether a judge is “impartial enough.”
4
In keeping with Geyh’s realistic view of impartiality, I argue for a realistic
view of implicit judicial bias, i.e. that it is inevitable but addressable. Part I will
situate judicial bias within current social science research on implicit bias and
establish an illustrative case study from Judge Richard Posner’s decision in Wassell
v. Adams.
5
Part II addresses why judicial bias matters based on the normative and
practical concerns of fairness and legitimacy. Part III then discusses current
prohibitions against bias in the American Bar Association’s (ABA) Model Code of
Judicial Conduct (“Model Code”) and the Code of Conduct for United States Judges
(“Code of Conduct”) and demonstrates that while they address explicit bias, they are
not intended to address implicit bias and cannot do so adequately. And, Part IV
proposes practical safeguards based on social science research and tailored to
judges’ unique role.
1
See, e.g., Madsen v. Women’s Health Ctr., Inc., 512 U.S. 753, 784 (1994).
2
1 Kings 3:1628.
3
CHARLES GARDNER GEYH, JAMES J. ALFINI, STEVEN LUBET & JEFFREY M. SHAMAN, JUDICIAL CONDUCT AND
ETHICS 1-3 (5th ed. 2013).
4
Charles Gardner Geyh, The Dimensions of Judicial Impartiality, 65 FLA. L. REV. 493, 493 (2013).
5
865 F.2d 749 (7th Cir. 1989).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 95
I. IMPLICIT BIAS IN THE JUDICIARY
A. Current Social Science Research and Its Application to the Judiciary
For over eighty years, social science research on bias has contributed to a
growing body of literature.
6
Part of this research has given rise to the concept of
implicit bias and how it affects behavior.
7
Because judges are responsible for their
own behavior and their job is to make decisions on other’s behavior, implicit bias
research should inform how we view the judicial role.
To begin, Jerry Kang differentiates explicit from implicit bias as that which is
“introspectively accessible” versus that which is “introspectively inaccessible.”
8
As a
result, while people may be unwilling to report explicit bias, people are unable to
report implicit bias.
9
Using the Implicit Association Test (IAT), Mahzarin Banaji
and Anthony Greenwald measured unconscious mental associations by measuring
response times to words and pictures.
10
They found that “schema-consistent
pairings,” for instance white faces with positive words, took less time for people to
recognize than “schema-inconsistent pairings,” or black faces with positive words.
11
Similarly, they found that schema-consistent pairings of women with the word
“family” took less time and fewer errors for people to recognize than schema-
inconsistent pairings of women with “career.”
12
Further, according to Banaji and Greenwald’s IAT research, implicit bias
levels significantly exceed reported, or explicit, bias levels.
13
Other researchers,
using measures like facial electromyogram and galvanic skin response techniques
also found that implicit bias measures sharply diverged from reported bias.
14
Scholars have described implicit and explicit bias as “dual attitudes” that exist side
by side; while the explicit attitude requires conscious retrieval, the implicit attitude
is automatic.
15
In analyzing implicit bias, Kang unequivocally states “no one is immune,” in
part because brains are good at sorting things.
16
With this in mind, determining
6
MAHZARIN R. BANAJI & ANTHONY G. GREENWALD, BLINDSPOT, at xiv (2013).
7
Id.
8
IU Maurer, Fuchs Lecture: Jerry Kang “Intending Equality, YOUTUBE (Apr. 17, 2015),
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=4CqrGmuwWrs [hereinafter Kang Fuchs Lecture].
9
Id.
10
BANAJI & GREENWALD, supra note 6, at 3941.
11
Jerry Kang, Mark Bennett, Devon Carbado, Pam Casey, Nilanjana Dasgupta, David Faigman, Rachel
Godsil, Anthony G. Greenwald, Justin Levinson & Jennifer Mnookin, Implicit Bias in the Courtroom, 59
UCLA L. REV. 1124, 1130 (2012).
12
BANAJI & GREENWALD, supra note 6, at 115.
13
See id. at 47, 67.
14
John F. Dovidio, Kerry Kawakami & Kelly R. Beach, Implicit and Explicit Attitudes: Examination of the
Relationship Between Measures of Intergroup Bias, in BLACKWELL HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY:
INTERGROUP PROCESSES 175, 183 (Rupert Brown & Samuel L. Gaertner eds., 2001).
15
Linda Hamilton Krieger & Susan T. Fiske, Behavioral Realism in Employment Discrimination Law:
Implicit Bias and Disparate Treatment, 94 C
AL. L. REV. 997, 1041 (2006) (citation omitted).
16
Kang Fuchs Lecture, supra note 8.
96 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
whether judicial bias really exists is a simple syllogism: all people have implicit
biases, judges are people, therefore judges have implicit biases. The views of leading
jurists correspond with this conclusion. Justice Cardozo said, “deep below
consciousness are other forces, the likes and the dislikes, the predilections and the
prejudices, the complex of instincts and emotions and habits and convictions, which
make the man, whether he be litigant or judge.”
17
In keeping with this view, social
scientists have confirmed that five prevalent “cognitive illusionsaffect judicial
decision-making
18
and have also found that judges can associate negative attitudes
with black people that influence judicial decisions.
19
In explaining their findings on
cognitive illusions, Chris Guthrie et al. concluded that “[j]udges, it seems, are
human . . . [and subject to] cognitive illusions that can produce systematic errors in
judgment.”
20
As a result, implicit bias can result in the unequal, albeit unintentional,
treatment of negatively stereotyped group members. To see how this could play out
for a judge deciding a case, consider Linda Krieger et al.’s statement that
“stereotypes can bias decision making implicitly by skewing the manner in which
inherently ambiguous information about the stereotyped target is perceived,
characterized, attributed, encoded in and retrieved from memory, and used in social
judgment.”
21
Because of this, a decision-maker like a judge could apply a negative
stereotype to a person while still “believ[ing] that his judgment and resulting
decision were based entirely on legitimate nondiscriminatory reasons.”
22
Banaji and
Greenwald have established a correlation between implicit bias and prejudiced
behavior that substantiates Krieger et al.’s conclusion.
23
However, simply because jurists draw implicit associations and can
rationalize them after the fact does not mean that they act on a particular bias
consistently. In fact, Krieger et al., drawing on psychological research spanning over
fifty years, found that whether an individual acts according to bias is situational.
24
Krieger et al. explains that people operate under a certain “tension” as a result of
dual attitudes.
25
In other words, some perceptions, thoughts, and motivations pull
toward one course of action while others simultaneously pull toward another.
26
This
means that a person will react differently to her stereotypes depending upon
17
BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO, THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS 167 (1921).
18
Chris Guthrie, Jeffrey J. Rachlinski & Andrew J. Wistrich, Inside the Judicial Mind, 86 CORNELL L. REV.
777, 778 (2001).
19
Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, Sheri Lynn Johnson, Andrew J. Wistrich & Chris Guthrie, Does Unconscious Racial
Bias Affect Trial Judges, 84 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1195, 1210 (2009).
20
Guthrie et al., supra note 18, at 778.
21
Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 1036.
22
Id.
23
BANAJI & GREENWALD, supra note 6, at 4850.
24
Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 1062.
25
Id. at 1040 (citation omitted).
26
Id. (citation omitted).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 97
whether the implicit or explicit attitude is dominating her judgment while she is
forming an impression about the stereotype’s target.
27
Jerome Frank, a prominent legal realist, is said to have quipped that judges
base their decisions on “what [they] had for breakfast.”
28
This is not my claim.
Rather, I take the view, in Geyh’s words, that “[i]n a post-realist age . . . the best
empirical work to date shows that the decisions judges make cannot be divorced
from the judges who make them because judicial decision-making is subject to a
complex array of legal and extralegal influences.”
29
Of these extralegal influences, I
focus on implicit bias because it is harder to quantify and identify than explicit
bias,
30
its effect on the common law can be felt for generations, and, despite the
current and unequivocal social science research on implicit bias, we have yet to
address fully its effect on judges.
B. Wassell v. Adams: An Illustrative Case Study in Implicit Judicial Bias
To illustrate implicit bias’s effect on judicial decision making, we can look at
Judge Richard Posner’s opinion in Wassell v. Adams
31
—a 1989 case that is in many
first-year torts curriculums. The plaintiff was Susan Wassell, a twenty-one-year-old
woman who was visiting Chicago to see her fiancé graduate from basic training at a
nearby naval base.
32
While visiting, Susan was attacked and raped in her hotel
room.
33
Late one night, hearing a knock and thinking it might have been her fiancé,
Susan opened the door to a man outside who asked for a glass of water.
34
She got
the water and brought it back; the man, saying the water was not cold enough, then
went into the bathroom.
35
When he came out, he was naked from the waist down,
and Susan ran from the room.
36
The man chased Susan out, caught her, and
dragged her back into the room, where he raped her several times.
37
After several
hours Susan managed to escape.
38
The hotel was four blocks away from a high crime area, and the owners
occasionally warned female guests not to walk in the neighborhood at night by
themselves.
39
However, the owners did not warn Susan.
40
Susan sued the hotel for
27
Id. at 1041.
28
See, e.g., Gregory S. Parks, Judicial Recusal: Cognitive Biases and Racial Stereotyping, 18 LEGIS. & PUB.
POLY 681, 682 (2015).
29
Charles Gardner Geyh, Why Judicial Disqualification Matters - Again, 30 REV. LITIG. 671, 715 (2011).
30
Kang Fuchs Lecture, supra note 8.
31
865 F.2d 849 (7th Cir. 1989).
32
Id. at 850.
33
Id. at 851.
34
Id.
35
Id.
36
Id.
37
Id.
38
Id.
39
Id.
40
Id.
98 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
negligence as a third party to her rape.
41
Under a comparative fault statute,
42
the
jury came back with the verdict that she was ninety-seven percent at fault for her
own rape, and the hotel owners only three percent at fault, thus reducing her
recovery.
43
Susan requested that the judge grant judgment for her notwithstanding
the verdict either because she was legally nonnegligent or the hotel owners had
wantonly disregarded her safety.
44
Alternatively, Susan requested a new trial
because the fault apportionment was contrary to the manifest weight of the
evidence.
45
The court denied both motions, and Susan appealed.
46
Upholding the verdict, Judge Posner, while not expressing any explicit
discourtesy,
47
rested on some concerning description and reasoning. For instance,
early in the analysis, Judge Posner identified the assailant as a “respectably
dressed black man.
48
The man’s race (or his attire) does not appear to be relevant
to the law or facts implicated in the case. But, mentioning traits like race when not
otherwise relevant can be evidence of either explicit bias or the unconscious
expression of implicit bias.
49
On the other hand, if race was relevant to the court’s analysis, then its
mention is even more concerning, because in the context of a comparative fault
analysis, it suggests that the court’s view was that Susan should have known the
stranger was a threat because he was a black man. This does not appear to be
explicit bias because Judge Posner does not make any such connection in his
analysis. However, the unnecessary disclosure of the man’s race juxtaposed with the
assignment of Susan’s fault in her own rape points to implicit bias. It is especially
suggestive of implicit bias given the extant backdrop of the pervasive social-sexual
myth of black men raping white women,
50
and even more so when coupled with the
fact that rapes are substantially more likely to be intraracial than interracial.
51
41
Id. at 852.
42
Id.
43
Id.
44
Id.
45
Id.
46
Id.
47
There were times, in fact, when Judge Posner showed a sensitivity to Susan’s plight. For instance, he called
the defendant’s claim that the hotel could not post a warning because it would be too expensive, “absurd[].”
Id. at 853. In addition, when he wrote that the plaintiff pretended, post-rape, to like the rapist, he clearly
stated that she did it “[t]o save herself” and refrained from suggesting that this cast doubt on her rape
assertions. Id. at 851.
48
Id.
49
See MODEL CODE OF JUDICIAL CONDUCT r. 2.3 cmt. 2 (AM. BAR ASSN 2010).
50
See Kimberle Crenshaw, Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist Critique of
Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and Antiracist Politics, 1989 U
NIV. CHI. LEGAL FORUM, no. 1,
at 159 n.54. Although Judge Posner does not disclose Susan’s race, she was white. Amy H. Kastely, Out of
the Whiteness: On Raced Codes and White Race Consciousness in Some Tort, Criminal, and Contract Law,
63 U. CIN. L. REV. 269, 283 & n.52 (1994).
51
From 197382, reported rapes with a black offender and white victim represented twenty-three percent of
rapes. P
ATSY A. KLAUS & MARSHALL DEBERRY, BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEPT OF JUSTICE, PROD.
NO. NCJ 96777, THE CRIME OF RAPE 3 (1985). The reporting guidelines changed in the 1980s and later
research found that intraracial rape accounted for about eighty-eight percent of rapes. LAWRENCE A.
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 99
Finally, Judge Posner upheld the jury verdict in spite of, and without even a nod to,
the fact that using comparative fault in rape litigation is painfully resonant with
the age old victim blaming epitaph that “she was asking for it.”
52
While these
implications each arguably fall short of overt bias, their cumulative resonance with
racism and misogyny nonetheless suggests a type of bias at work “deep below
consciousness.”
53
Of course, the appellate judge’s role is often to review for abuse of
discretion.
54
As a result, the easy explanation is that Judge Posner was simply
observing his proper role by deferring to the trial court and jury verdict. However,
Judge Posner is not shy about either correcting an application of law or pointing out
that he is limited to his role, even though he may not like it.
55
In fact, there is one
point in Wassell that Judge Posner is uncomfortable with, but his discomfort is
focused exclusively on whether the jury got the percentage of fault correct because
the jury asked a question about the hotel’s duty to warn that went unanswered.
56
But why is there no concern for the gender and racially problematic aspects
of the opinion or its applicable law? Judge Posner could have broken new ground in
third-party rape suits by applying a different standard.
57
For instance, one
alternative is the no-duty approach, which is to “recognize important differences in
the situation of the two actors that justify treating them differently.”
58
Under this
approach, courts would: (1) “see a difference in failing to prevent injury to oneself as
opposed to others,” (2) “recognize the different kind of costs that each actor pays for
not being more cautious or prudent,” and (3) “decide whether reducing or barring
recovery for rape victims will likely serve the social policy of curtailing high rates of
sexual assaults.”
59
Of course, it would have required innovation to institute a no-duty exception
in comparative fault doctrine for third-party rape suits. However, Judge Posner has
written innovative opinions on many other matters,
60
and innovation is consistent
GREENFELD, BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEPT OF JUSTICE, PROD. NO. NCJ-163392, SEX OFFENSES
AND
OFFENDERS: AN ANALYSIS OF DATA ON RAPE AND SEXUAL ASSAULT 11 (1997).
52
See Martha Chamallas, Symposium: Who Is the Reasonable Person? Gaining Some Perspective in Tort Law:
A New Take on Third-Party Criminal Attack Cases, 14 L
EWIS & CLARK L. REV. 1351, 1381 (2010); Leah M.
Slyder, Note, Rape in the Civil and Administrative Contexts: Proposed Solutions to Problems in Tort Cases
Brought by Rape Survivors, 68 CASE W. RES. 543, 567569 (2017).
53
CARDOZO, supra note 17.
54
Wassell v. Adams, 865 F.2d 849, 856 (7th Cir. 1989).
55
See State Oil Co. v. Khan, 93 F.3d 1358 (7th Cir. 1996) (following antitrust precedent even though he
referred to it as “moth-eaten,” “wobbly,” and “unsound”); Ind. Harbor Belt R.R. Co. v. Am. Cyanamid Co.,
916 F.2d 1174 (7th Cir. 1990) (lowering the standard of legal liability a railroad company faced for a
chemical spill); George M. Cohen, Posnerian Jurisprudence and Economic Analysis of Law, 133 U. PA. L.
REV. 1117, 1117 (1985) (discussing Judge Posner’s “innovative methodological approach”).
56
See Wassell, 865 F.2d at 856.
57
A third-party rape case is a subset of tort cases where a plaintiff sues a third party to an attack for
permitting dangerous conditions or failing to take other reasonable precautions to prevent such an attack.
Chamallas, supra note 52, at 1354.
58
Chamallas, supra note 52, at 1383 (citing Ellen M. Bublick, Citizen No-Duty Rules: Rape Victims and
Comparative Fault, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 1413 (1999)).
59
Id. (citation omitted).
60
Cohen, supra note 55.
100 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
with how he views the judge’s role.
61
In his words, a flexible, innovative approach is
required because the “multi-layered character of American law . . . thrust[s] on the
courts a responsibility for creative lawmaking that cannot be discharged either by
applying existing rules to the letter or by reasoning by analogy.”
62
And yet, in
Wassell this approach is notably absent. Judge Posner did not acknowledge the
policy implications of allowing courts to find victims responsible for their own rape,
express personal distaste for the outcome or implication, mention misogyny or
racism’s possible effect on the jury, or discuss whether finding Susan ninety-seven
percent responsible for her own rape could possibly vindicate her individual right to
redress.
63
Based on these analytical gaps, and Judge Posner’s view of rape published in
Sex and Reason in 1992,
64
I posit that Judge Posner did not see the role that
misogyny and racism played in allowing Wassell’s jury to find the white plaintiff
ninety-seven percent responsible for her own rape by a black manor the common
law rule that permits victim fault allocation in third-party rape suits in the first
place. After Sex and Reason’s publication, feminist scholars struggled with Judge
Posner’s rape discussion, particularly his conclusion that rape is “primarily a
substitute for consensual sexual intercourse rather than a manifestation of male
hostility toward women or a method of establishing or maintaining male
domination.
65
One critic paraphrased that in this view, rape and other acts of
subordination are not about subordination at all, but are merely efficient practices
based on “successful adaptations to biological market conditions.”
66
Excavating an old opinion through literary analysis is not proof that Judge
Posner wrote Wassell under the influence of unacknowledged bias.
67
Rather, I use it
here for illustrative value. Judge Posner was a fiercely academic, rational,
68
and
61
RICHARD A. POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW 1213 (1995).
62
Id. (emphasis added).
63
While Wassell presents a rape involving a black man and a white woman, under a theory of
intersectionality, black women may have a different experience than either black men or white women,
particularly when it comes to racism, feminism, misogyny, and rape. See Crenshaw, supra note 50, at 139,
140, 157160.
64
RICHARD A. POSNER, SEX AND REASON (1992).
65
Id. at 384; see, e.g., Robin West, Review Essay: Sex, Reason, and a Taste for the Absurd, 81 GEO. L. J. 2413,
244041 (1993). Naturally, research available at the time of Sex and Reason’s publication, and since then,
suggests that the motivation to rape is much more complicated. See A. Nicholas Groth, Ann Wolbert
Burgess & Lynda Lytle Holmstrom, Rape: Power, Anger, and Sexuality, 134 A
M. J. PSYCHIATRY 1239, 1239
(1977) (finding that interviewers of 133 convicted rapists concluded that their crimes “were not rapes in
which sex was the dominant issue; sexuality was always in the service of other, nonsexual needs”);
Crenshaw, supra note 50, at 158 (critiquing the exclusive focus on rape as an expression of male power over
women while identifying the rape of black women as part of a racially motivated terror campaign); Heather
Murphy, What Experts Know About Men Who Rape, N.Y.
TIMES (Oct. 20, 2017),
https://www.nytimes.com/2017/10/30/health/men-rape-sexual-assault.html (identifying that while exclusive
focus on convicted rapists may skew data, researchers continue to find that hostility to women and power
are relevant factors in explaining rape).
66
West, supra note 65, at 244546.
67
See Bruce A. Green, Legal Discourse and Racial Justice: The Urge to Cry “Bias!, 28 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS
177, 202 (2015) (stating that no social scientist would base a conclusion on one data point).
68
See Michael B. Brennan, Book Review, 79 MARQ. L. REV. 329, 329 (1995).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 101
dedicated jurist. He was not likely to say and do things that were overtly racist or
misogynistic, and there is no reason to suspect a history of disciplinary proceedings
for improper conduct toward women and racial minorities.
69
But if elements of the
Wassell opinion can be explained by implicit bias and a person as academic and
rational as Judge Posner can inadvertently manifest such bias, then without doubt,
any jurist is susceptible.
In state trial courts, examples of possible implicit bias play out in the records
of disciplinary proceedings. In In re Jordan, a disciplinary commission sanctioned a
judge for twice referring to an attorney appearing before him as “little girl.”
70
In
that case, the commission focused on the second time the judge said “little girl”
because it found that he used the phrase intentionally to demean the attorney.
71
Of
primary interest here, however, was the commission’s conclusion that the first use
of “little girl” may have been “an inadvertent expression of unconscious prejudice.”
72
This is evidence that disciplinary commissions at least tacitly recognize that
implicit bias is qualitatively different than explicit bias and are hesitant to
discipline it in the same way.
While in In re Jordan, the bias’s target was an attorney, there are also many
instances where trial court judges seemingly exhibit implicit bias toward litigants.
For instance, a New York trial judge, in a case dealing with international students,
told a prosecutor “you better deport these people” and “you better get them out.”
73
The disciplinary commission waffled about the words’ import.
74
Because it wasn’t “a
continuous pattern of . . . conduct” they were unwilling to conclude that bias was at
work and hedged their language about what “appear[ed] to indicate distrust and
dislike of all those from outside his community.”
75
However, distrust or dislike is
precisely the kind of passive antipathy that implicit association researchers have
identified and we are concerned with here.
76
II. WHY IMPLICIT JUDICIAL BIAS MATTERS
Given the strength of contemporary social science research on implicit bias, it
is clear that unconscious bias exists, and the judiciary is not immune from it. The
question, however, is does it matter. I argue that bias in the judiciary does indeed
matter because judges play a substantial role in a common-law system, because of
normative concern for legitimacy and fairness, and because of the related practical
concern for compliance and procedural justice.
69
While complaints issued against federal judges are not made immediately public, substantiated complaints
can lead to public censure and other sanctions that may become public knowledge. See 28 U.S.C §§ 35155
(2018).
70
GEYH ET AL., supra note 3, at 3-37.
71
Id.
72
Id.
73
Id. at 3-26.
74
Id.
75
Id. (emphasis added).
76
See infra text accompanying notes 85–87.
102 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
In a common-law system, judges have the unique role of applying legal
precedent to new facts. As a result, the common law is dynamic, and judges have
significant power in shaping it.
77
While this is true for judges presiding over courts
with both original and appellate jurisdiction, it is perhaps especially true for the
appellate courts. According to Judge Roger Traynor, the “intellectual process of
appellate judgment, [is] of the greatest public importance.”
78
At the same time, the legitimacy of government institutions and actors is a
primary concern because of a representative democracy’s unique theoretical
underpinnings
79
and because of the “wondrous” power that legitimacy has to
“convince[] losers in law and politics to accept their losses.”
80
As a result, it is
unsurprising that in our governmental system, the judiciary’s role is consistently
subject to legitimacy concerns,
81
many of which are tied to impartiality, both actual
and its appearance.
82
Because unchecked bias both directly reduces a judge’s ability
to decide impartially
83
and gives the appearance of partiality,
84
it stands as a
legitimacy measure.
One of implicit bias’s dangers is that it can consistently tip justice’s scales to the favor
of one group and the disfavor of another. This is the case even though scholars generally
think that people express explicit bias less now than at previous points.
85
For instance,
“rather than antipathy, many now show ambivalence and avoid members of stereotyped
77
See, e.g., VICTOR E. SCHWARTZ, KATHRYN KELLY & DAVID F. PARTLETT, PROSSER WADE AND SCHWARTZS TORTS:
CASES AND MATERIALS 1 (13th ed. 2015) (establishing that torts have largely been the creation of judicial
opinions).
78
Roger J. Traynor, Some Open Questions on the Work of State Appellate Courts, 24 U. CHI. L. REV. 211, 212
(1957).
79
In a representative democracy, the government should reflect the will of the people. See ROBERT NOZICK,
ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA 290 (1974). For this governmental system to have any meaning, the people
must understand the institutions of government to be acting legitimately, that is to say, discharging the
people’s will. See id. at 134 (stating that at the very least, “a legitimate government is one that most of its
subjects view as legitimately ruling.”).
80
JAMES L. GIBSON, ELECTING JUDGES: THE SURPRISING EFFECTS OF CAMPAIGNING ON JUDICIAL LEGITIMACY 130
(2012).
81
See Charles Gardner Geyh, Preserving Public Confidence in the Courts in an Age of Individual Rights and
Public Skepticism, in BENCH PRESS: THE COLLISION OF COURTS, POLITICS, AND THE MEDIA 21, 22 (Keith J.
Bybee ed., 2007).
82
See id. at 24, 3031.
83
See supra Part I.
84
See John Sides, White People Believe the Justice System is Color Blind. Black People Really Don’t., WASH.
POST (July 22, 2013, 12:20 PM), https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2013/07/22/white-people-
believe-the-justice-system-is-color-blind-black-people-really-dont/?utm_term=.7f330f928deb (reporting that
sixty percent of African Americans disagreed with the statement that “courts give all a fair trial” and that
perceptions of procedural injustice informed these attitudes).
85
See, e.g., Victor D. Quintanilla, Beyond Common Sense: A Social Psychological Study of Iqbal's Effect on
Claims of Race Discrimination, 17 MICH. J. RACE & L. 1 (2011), at 1718. According to Quintanilla, “[w]hile
blatant racism has waned, prejudice still persists . . . the field of social psychology has shown a continuing
divide between words and deeds toward people of color.” However, we should not construe this to mean that
all bias is subtle. See Joan C. Williams, Double Jeopardy? An Empirical Study with Implications for the
Debates over Implicit Bias and Intersectionality, 37 HARV. J.L. & GENDER 185, 188 (reporting that while
some gender bias was subtle “much was not subtle at all”). In addition, as Williams points out, once people
recognize a pattern of bias, even implicit bias is then easy to spot. See id. at 227.
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 103
groups . . . resulting in decreased helping behavior and cooperation, passive harm, and
neglect.”
86
At the same time, “many exhibit liking and trust toward in-group members,
resulting in facilitation and cooperation with other majority group members.
87
In a complex evaluative process, these mental errors can result in courts chronically
undervaluing out-group members, such as women and racial minorities, and chronically
overvaluing in-group members, such as white men. In Wassell, how can we explain the
possibility that Judge Posner just did not assign value to irrelevant racial descriptions, the
negative policy implications or plain injustice of holding a victim ninety-seven percent
responsible for her own rape, or to racism and misogyny’s effect of legitimizing and
encouraging human suffering? It could be that Judge Posner was simply unable to mentally
recognize that his opinion implicated issues of racial and gender equality;
88
he instinctively
valued them less than some other principles or policy outcomes,
89
or both.
There is good reason to think that implicit bias is especially likely to cause disparate
valuing when there is ambiguity in the law or a particularly close question. Despite implicit
racial prejudices, people are less likely to discriminate when there is a clear choice that
would associate them with biased attitudes and behaviors versus one that would not.
90
However, in the law, there are many instances when there are no clear choices. Karl
Llewellyn illustrates the point when he says that courts can decide a question, correctly, in
twenty-six ways and goes onto say “the major defect in [our] system is a mistaken idea . . .
that the cases . . . plus the correct rules . . . provide one single correct answer to a disputed
issue of law.”
91
Instead, Llewellyn says, “the available correct answers are two, three, or ten”
and the salient question is “[w]hich of the available correct answers will the court select
and why?”
92
Because judges in a common law system have considerable discretion in
applying the law, this opens the door to bias. Llewellyn describes the “felt need” and
“felt sense” that judges use in their decision-making
93
and instincts are undoubtedly
as essential to the judicial profession as they are in any other endeavor. However, it
is very likely that in ambiguous cases, the type of split-second subconscious
categorization described by implicit bias research informs “felt” needs and sense.
94
86
Quintanilla, supra note 85, at 18.
87
Id.
88
See supra discussion accompanying notes 50–56, 6163.
89
Judge Posner’s self-professed take on feminism is suggestive here:
[L]aw or government should [not] prescribe a particular role for women or discourage them
from exercising free choice regarding occupation, marriage, and style of life. Nor, however,
do[es] [he] believe that women should be put ahead of men or encouraged to lead separate
lives from men, or that ‘what’s good for women’ should be the lodestar for social governance
instead of what’s good for the United Statesor what’s good for humankind.’
Richard A. Posner, Conservative Feminism, 1989 U.
CHI. LEGAL F. 191, 191.
90
Quintanilla, supra note 85, at 20 (citing John F. Dovidio & Samuel L. Gaertner, Aversive Racism, 36
ADVANCES EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 1, 47 (2004)).
91
Karl N. Llewellyn, Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How
Statutes Are to Be Construed, 3 VAND. L. REV. 395, 396 (1950).
92
Id. (emphasis omitted).
93
Id. at 398.
94
See supra Part I.
104 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
In addition, information-rich environments or even the semblance of information
give people adequate cover to act on bias.
95
Because judges often have substantial
information supplied by the record, and, as both Llewellyn and Judge Posner
suggest, law’s application to facts is often ambiguous,
96
judicial decision-making is
fertile ground for implicit bias.
Judge Posner recognized the relationship between ambiguity and bias in
McReynolds v. Merrill Lynch.
97
In describing corporate practices in a discrimination
case, he said that the white brokers in question “are more comfortable teaming with
other white brokers” but that “they would doubtless ask a superstar broker to join
their team regardless of his or her race.”
98
Where there is uncertainty, however,
Judge Posner said, “people tend to base decisions on emotions and
preconceptions.”
99
To allow the law to consistently favor an in-group while consistently
disfavoring an out-group is fundamentally unfair. Fairness is central to judicial
impartiality and, not surprisingly, Merriam-Webster defines fair as “marked by
impartiality.”
100
In the first place, we should care about unchecked implicit bias’s
unfair effects on judicial decision-making for normative reasons. Our sense of
fairness helps us intuitively gauge how people treat us against how we want them
to treat us. In Llewellyn’s words, fairness is part of our “felt sense, and there is
significant collective recognition that we should treat others as we would like to be
treated.
101
However, fairness, like legitimacy, is not just a normative concept to aspire to
for its own sake. For the rule of law to provide order, there must be compliance.
102
Procedural justice, resting on perceptions of both fairness and legitimacy, helps
explain why people comply with the law despite adverse outcomes.
103
To do so,
procedural justice captures how individuals subjectively experience the legal
process.
104
Researchers have found that people care both about outcome and,
95
Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 105051.
96
See supra text accompanying notes 60, 91–92.
97
McReynolds v. Merrill Lynch, 672 F.3d 482 (7th Cir. 2012).
98
Id. at 489.
99
Id. One question is how Judge Posner could recognize this preference in McReynolds but not in Wassell.
One obvious difference is that the opinions were written twenty-eight years apart. Another possible
explanation is the “bias blindspot,” which is the name given to individuals’ tendency to think they are more
objective than others. See Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1173.
100
Fair, MERRIAM WEBSTERS COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY (11th ed. 2003).
101
Lisa Capretto, Scholar Points to One Thing Nearly All Major Religions Have in Common, HUFFPOST (Aug.
17, 2016), https://www.huffingtonpost.com/entry/principle-in-nearly-all-major-
religions_us_57b370a1e4b0edfa80d9e0e6 (identifying the Golden Rule as a principle common to most of the
world’s major religions).
102
RICHARD H. MCADAMS, THE EXPRESSIVE POWERS OF LAW: THEORIES AND LIMITS 3 (2015).
103
Tom Tyler, What is Procedural Justice?: Criteria Used by Citizens to Assess the Fairness of Legal
Procedures, 22 L. & SOCY REV. 103, 103 (1988).
104
Rebecca Hollander-Blumoff, The Psychology of Procedural Justice in the Federal Courts, 63 HASTINGS L.J.
127, 134 (2011).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 105
independently of outcome, the fairness of the process.
105
Based on this, procedural
justice scholars conclude that how an individual perceives the legal process’ fairness
is “critical to assessments of legitimacy and deference to legal authority.”
106
Our perceptions of fairness rest on unbiased, impartial decision makers. Tom
Tyler has identified seven factors that determine whether citizens feel judges acted
fairly.
107
Two factors are relevant to actions taken by the parties: the chance to have
representation and the opportunity to appeal. Five of the seven factors directly
pertain to the judge. They are the judge’s (1) effort at fairness, (2) honesty, (3)
ethical conduct, (4) quality of decisions, and (5) bias.
108
Tyler not only enumerates
bias as a stand-alone concern, but it is also implicit in the other four judicial
conduct factors. Thus, bias is highly relevant to legitimacy and compliance.
Moreover, litigation’s very purposes include other practical concerns that
raise the threat of lawlessness. Its purpose is largely to avoid vigilantism, act as a
deterrent, encourage desirable social conduct, make the injured person whole, and
provide justice for an individual’s right to redress.
109
Judicial decision-making
thwarts these purposes if subconscious undervaluing is taking place during a
judge’s evaluation process. We can easily imagine if a court undervalues certain
people’s claims, it will be unable to make them whole or fully validate their
individual rights to redress. At the same time, if the court overvalues other people’s
claims, it is less likely to deter them completely or acknowledge how socially
undesirable their conduct is. The disparity between one group’s lack of redress and
recovery against another group’s diminished deterrence and limited social sanction
can only diminish the legitimacy and power of our legal system . Simply put,
unchecked implicit bias is not only unfairit threatens the rule of law.
III. BIAS PROHIBITIONS IN THE CODE OF CONDUCT AND MODEL CODE
The ethical rules in both the Code of Conduct and the Model Code currently
contain prohibitions against bias. The Code of Conduct’s Canon 3(A)(3) specifies
that “[t]he duty to be respectful includes the responsibility to avoid comment or
behavior that could reasonably be interpreted as harassment, prejudice or bias.
110
Similarly, the Model Code’s rule 2.8 prohibits undignified and discourteous
behavior
111
and rule 2.3 insists that “[a] judge shall perform the duties of judicial
office, including administrative duties, without bias or prejudice.”
112
Examples of
discourteous conduct that have given rise to discipline are verbally abusing and
intimidating parties in a courtroom, subjecting people to unwarranted searches,
105
Id. at 132.
106
See, e.g., id.
107
See Tyler, supra note 103.
108
Id.
109
See SCHWARTZ ET AL., supra note 77.
110
CODE OF CONDUCT FOR UNITED STATES JUDGES Canon 3(A)(3) (JUDICIAL CONF. 2014).
111
MODEL CODE OF JUDICIAL CONDUCT r.2.3, 2.8 (AM. BAR ASSN 2010).
112
Id.
106 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
criticizing jurors after a verdict, and using profanity in the courtroom.
113
Sanctions
for these acts include public reprimands, public reproval, suspension, removal,
etc.
114
Examples of racial bias that have given rise to disciplinary proceedings
include using racial epithets, making racial “jokes,” referring to certain crimes in
racial terms, stereotyping racial groups, and using racially charged language.
115
Examples of gender bias include using gender loaded language and insults to
disparage, making inappropriate comments during domestic abuse cases, referring
to women as children, pontificating that a woman’s place is in the home, calling
women terms of endearment in a professional context, and commenting on women’s
appearance.
116
Sanctions in bias proceedings are similar to those resulting from
discourtesy and include reprimands, public reproval, suspension, and removal.
117
In these examples, there are two common themes: 1) the conduct in question
is overt, and 2) the biases most readily addressed tend to be explicit, or at least
perceived to be explicit.
118
While the current rules are effective when used to correct
overt conduct that expresses explicit bias, they are a poor fit for addressing implicit
bias. For instance, the prohibitions against bias and discourtesy do not easily reach
a Wassell-type situation. Recall that in Wassell, Judge Posner was not discourteous
and did not engage in any conduct that was clearly prejudiced toward women or
racial minorities.
119
Where a judge’s implicit associations may surreptitiously allow
his brain to value women and black men less, fail to recognize racism at play in
irrelevant references to skin color, or refuse to acknowledge the potential for
misogyny and racism to inform a legal rule or jury verdict there is a gossamer-like
quality that makes comparisons with using the “n-word” in open court
problematic.
120
Moreover, much of the Model Code and the Code of Conduct’s concern for
impartiality is focused on conflicts, not on bias per se.
121
For instance, in Caperton
v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., the Court used the word bias often,
122
but its context was
violation of a disqualification rule similar to Model Code rule 2.11.
123
And the issue
in the case was whether a West Virginia Supreme Court judge had a conflict in a
113
GEYH ET AL., supra note 3, at 3-3 n.5.
114
Id.
115
Id. at 3-23 to 3-28.
116
Id. at 3-36 to 3-41.
117
See id. at 3-23 to 3-28.
118
See Alex Kozinski, The Real Issues of Judicial Ethics, 32 HOFSTRA L. REV. 1095, 1095 (2004) (“The canons
focus on the tensions and potential conflicts that are most easily detected by an outside observer.”).
119
For instance, Judge Posner was seemingly sympathetic to Susan’s efforts to do whatever she could to get
away from her attacker. See supra note 47. Additionally, while “respectably dressed black man” is certainly
suspect in the context of the opinion, the language itself is not inherently prejudiced. See supra text
accompanying notes 4852.
120
Compare supra Section I.B. with supra text accompanying notes 11316.
121
See Green, supra note 67, at 18384.
122
See Caperton v. A.T. Massey Coal Co., 556 U.S. 868 passim (2009).
123
“Bias” is used similarly in the disqualification rule for federal judges. See CODE OF CONDUCT FOR UNITED
STATES JUDGES Canon 3(C) (JUDICIAL CONF. 2014).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 107
lawsuit before his court because one of the litigants made very large contributions
to the judge’s campaign.
124
As the Supreme Court stated in Caperton,
disqualification is normally the
redress for a conflict that gives the appearance or has the actual result of impeding
a judge’s impartiality.
125
However, disqualification is not a viable option for cases
involving implicit bias. Because all people subconsciously categorize others, we
would have no judges left to adjudicate if we required judges to disqualify every
time their brains engaged in an implicit association.
126
Finally, while social science research splits biases into the neat categories of
explicit and implicit, it also recognizes that people may not always report their own
biases or may attempt to hide them.
127
As a result, we should be careful about
assuming that all instances of judicial bias will be easily identifiable as implicit or
explicit, fit in a neat analytical framework, or be addressed mechanically through
the measures proposed in Part IV. As In re Jordan suggests, it is possible for a
judge to simultaneously express an implicit bias alongside an explicit bias,
128
and it
may be hard to distinguish the two. We should also assume that judges are
sometimes able to hide their explicit biases or might be able to use implicit bias as
cover for what is in fact explicitly biased behavior. My goal is not to give biased
judges a get out of jail free card, but rather to curb true implicit associations when
these associations are married to a judge’s good faith commitment to deliver
impartial justice. I do not intend my analysis to reach judges who deliberately hide
their equally deliberate bias.
For the bulk of jurists who are acting in good faith and are subject to implicit
associations, the need for tailored guidelines is especially pressing because scholars
have noticed that while overt racism has waned, “the manifestation of prejudice has
grown more subtle.”
129
As a result, while the bias prohibitions in the Model Code
and the Code of Conduct generally do what they were intended to do, we need
additional mechanisms to continue working toward our aspiration of an impartial
judiciary.
IV. BEYOND THE STATUS QUO: NOT LETTING PERFECT GET IN THE WAY OF GOOD
Before turning to the recommendations, it is worth noting a subtle difference
between the purpose of the Model Rules and Code of Conduct provisions just
discussed and the measures I propose. The guides to professional ethics exist to
govern misconduct.
130
Because implicit bias is a split-second neurological response
124
See Caperton, 556 U.S. at 872.
125
See id. at 88889.
126
See Green, supra note 67, at 184.
127
See supra text accompanying notes 2427; see also infra text accompanying notes 15960.
128
See supra text accompanying notes 70–72.
129
Quintanilla, supra note 85, at 17.
130
See GEYH ET AL., supra note 3, at ix.
108 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
that occurs unconsciously,
131
we should be slow to term it misconduct by rote and
automatically discipline it as such for two reasons. First, the culpability for
manifesting implicit bias as compared to explicit bias is less. How can a person be
morally responsible in any meaningful sense when she does not know what she is
doing?
132
Second, we intend ethical rules and their corresponding disciplinary
processes to act as deterrents.
133
Because individuals are not initially in the driver’s
seat when it comes to their own implicit bias, ethical rules and discipline will be less
effective as deterrents.
However, just because implicit judicial bias is unintentional does not mean it
cannot cause grievous injustice. Sentencing’s racially disparate effect, especially
death sentences, suggest just how immoral the result of unchecked implicit bias can
be.
134
While we may not have initial control as individuals over the quick
categorization that our brain goes through when faced with different types of
people,
135
collectively we have control over what we do from thereand willful
ignorance is not a sufficient excuse. With that in mind, the Model Code and Code of
Conduct should incorporate the methods below with their other aspirations and
expectations for judicial conduct. With these expectations in place, disciplinary
committees could sanction a judge for not engaging proactively in curbing her
implicit bias but not for having an unconscious bias to begin with.
The question is whether, since implicit bias occurs in an unconscious process,
there is anything we can do about it. The research is clear that our implicit
associations do not always lead to biased decision-making.
136
Surveying social
science research on behavior across many decades, Krieger et al. concluded that
“whether attitudes predict behavior depends on the attitude, the context, and the
person.”
137
In examining the correlation between bias and behavior, there are two key
factors that influence when they will be closely correlated: motive and opportunity
to deliberate.
138
When motive and opportunity are present, attitudes and behavior
correlate less.
139
Krieger et al. build out these two factors into the saliency of social
131
See supra text accompanying notes 812.
132
In analyzing the purposes underlying our criminal law, arguably our legal system’s most punitive area,
Stuntz and Hoffman identify three overlapping purposes, including retribution. WILLIAM J. STUNTZ &
JOSEPH L. HOFFMAN, DEFINING CRIMES 11 (2nd ed. 2014). For the purpose of retribution, “punishment . . . is
a moral good because crime is a moral wrong.” Id. We can analogize between crime and judicial misconduct
here to the extent they are both socially undesirable activities that cause harm.
133
See Randall T. Shepard, Foreword to CHARLES GARDNER GEYH, JAMES J. ALFINI, STEVEN LUBET & JEFFREY M.
SHAMAN, JUDICIAL CONDUCT AND ETHICS, at v-vi (2013) (stating that while the rare judge might be a “crook”
many others are trying to discharge the duties of their office faithfully and use the ethical rules as a
roadmap to handle avoidable pitfalls with “greater ethical sensitivity”).
134
See Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1148.
135
See supra Section I.A.
136
See Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 1049.
137
Id.
138
Russell H. Fazio & Michael A. Olson, Implicit Measures in Social Cognition Research: Their Meaning and
Use, 54 A
NN. REV. PSYCHOL. 297, 304 (2003).
139
Id.
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 109
norms, the decision-maker’s perceived sense of control, the decision-maker’s desire
to avoid the bias, and relevant information.
140
The checks proposed below
incorporate these concepts and, because the research shows that these factors
predict the greatest variance when each is present,
141
my solutions will be most
effective when used together. While the proposed solutions are not enough to root
out all implicit bias, as this section’s title suggests, my goal is to provide a
framework for taking a meaningful step forward. I focus on using systems that are
already largely in place in order to minimize the force of objections to moving
forward.
The first question is how to provide judges with evidence of their own implicit
bias so that they will be motivated to address it. Kang et al. suggest that one step is
having judges take the IAT just like other individuals and professional groups do.
142
In order to promote participation and avoid unnecessary shaming, the assessments
should be confidential with respect to individual judges, but the aggregated data
over time should be collected by court administrators in order to target and refine
efforts. Kang et. al. also suggest judicial training on cognitive illusions, the
fallibility of heuristics, and how to become sensitized to biases similar to the type
used in other professional settings.
143
Most state court systems can build this into
their current continuing legal education requirements
144
so that they require
implicit bias training hours each year. In fact, Kang has already supplied a primer
on implicit bias for courts in partnership with the National Center for State
Courts.
145
While there are optional training programs for the federal judiciary, there is
no mandated training,
146
so it would take an extra step to implement this
suggestion for the federal bench. The Federal Judicial Center is the body charged
with providing training to federal courts and it currently offers workshops on
implicit bias.
147
For both state and federal courts then, access to adequate training
materials is unlikely to be an issue.
148
Because annual judicial conferences already
140
Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 1050.
141
See Fazio & Olsen, supra note 138; see also Alexandra Kalev, Erin Kelly & Frank Dobbin, Best Practices or
Best Guesses? Assessing the Efficacy of Corporate Affirmative Action and Diversity Policies, 71 AM. SOC. REV.
589, 589 (2006) (finding that diversity measures were most effective when training, assigned responsibility,
and steps to reduce minority isolation were employed together).
142
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 117577.
143
Id.
144
Forty states have continuing education requirements. Legal Education/Bar Admission Resource Guide,
NATL CTR. FOR ST. CTS., https://ncsc.contentdm.oclc.org/digital/collection/legserv/id/86 (last updated May 16,
2019).
145
JERRY KANG, NATL CTR. FOR STATE COURTS, IMPLICIT BIAS: A PRIMER FOR COURTS (2009),
https://cdm16501.contentdm.oclc.org/digital/collection/accessfair/id/248.
146
S.I. Strong, Symposium: Judicial Education and Regulatory Capture, 2015 J. DISP. RESOL. 1, 14 (noting that
judges “are largely in control of their own educational agendas”).
147
Programs and Resources for Judges, FED. JUD. CTR., https://www.fjc.gov/education/programs-and-resources-
judges#SF (last visited Sept. 1, 2020).
148
In addition to the other resources mentioned, the ABA has a resource page dedicated to implicit bias
training for attorneys and judges. Diversity and Inclusion 360 Commission, A
M. BAR ASSN,
https://www.americanbar.org/diversity-portal/diversity-inclusion-360-commission.html (last visited Sept. 1,
110 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
exist and judges typically attend them,
149
the easiest way to administer this
requirement may be to push the training out in partnership with these conferences.
However, the key is to require the education because if an external body does
not require it, judges are less likely to opt into this training. A mandate helps
establish norms and contributes to motivation.
150
In addition, people who are
uncertain in their knowledge are likelier to make more effective educational
choices.
151
While a confident judge is undoubtedly helpful in many contexts, because
people are unable to perceive their own implicit bias,
152
and tend to think that they
are less biased than others,
153
a lack of uncertainty is especially problematic in this
context. By requiring the training, judges are not left to self-diagnose what social
scientists know is a typical blind spot.
The question is then which external body should mandate implicit bias
training for federal judges. The answer is not the legislature. While there are some
areas in which the legislature must exercise judicial oversight,
154
opening up this
sensitive and nascent oversight role to the politics between the federal judiciary and
Congress and the politics between Congress and its constituents,
could affect the
judiciary’s independence and perceptions of its legitimacy,
155
would be excruciating
to watch,
156
and would almost certainly result in the false and unfair cry of “Bias!”
of such concern to Bruce Green.
157
With this in mind, the best suggestion is for a
dedicated Judicial Conference committee to work with the chief judges to determine
the most effective way to execute and enforce a training requirement.
Accountability and transparency are essential to successful efforts to
counteract implicit bias because of the role of social norms in negating the
2020). While the efficacy of these trainings is largely untested, there are at least some interventions
workshops that, while only tested in small numbers, are showing positive effects. See Jessica Nordell, Is
This How Discrimination Ends?, A
TLANTIC (May 7, 2017),
https://www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2017/05/unconscious-bias-training/525405/ (reporting on an
implicit bias workshop at the University of Wisconsin).
149
See, e.g., JUDICIAL COUNCIL OF THE NINTH CIRCUIT, NINTH CIRCUIT UNITED STATES COURTS 2009 ANNUAL
REPORT 22 (2009), https://www.ca9.uscourts.gov/judicial_council/publications/AnnualReport2009.pdf.
150
See infra notes 158–63 and accompanying text.
151
Strong, supra note 146.
152
See supra text accompanying notes 89; Strong, supra note 146, at 15.
153
See Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1173.
154
For instance, Congress is the only body that can establish the lower federal courts. See U.S. CONST. art. III,
§ 1.
155
See CHARLES GARDNER GEYH, WHEN COURTS AND CONGRESS COLLIDE 28082 (2008).
156
For instance, consider the political grandstanding on both sides of the aisle accompanying the recent
Kavanaugh nomination hearings. See Cavett Feazel, Kavanaugh’s Confirmation Hearings a Display of
Political Grandstanding, CIVILIAN (Oct. 9, 2018), https://sites.law.lsu.edu/civilian/2018/10/kavanaughs-
confirmation-hearings-a-display-of-political-grandstanding-september/.
157
Because implicit bias affects almost everyone but is hard to determine on a case-by-case basis, it would be
hard to prove an implicit bias accusation, but also equally hard to disprove. See Green, supra note 67, at
180. As a result, it is unwise to use such accusations as a political club, which is almost certain to occur, at
least periodically, if the legislature has oversight over this area. See GEYH, supra note 155, at 5152
(describing the periodic upheaval that occurs between the public, Congress, and the Supreme Court in
relation to disfavored opinions); Green, supra note 67, at 181 (discussing the way people might respond to
disfavored opinions with unprovable bias allegations).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 111
expression of bias. To see how this plays out, consider the case of the aversive racist.
Aversive racism describes racial bias among people who claim to hold egalitarian
beliefs but who nonetheless act on “indirect, subtle, and less obvious racial
biases.”
158
Notably, aversive racists do not discriminate if strong norms against
discrimination are present and the discrimination would be apparent to themselves
or others.
159
Without transparency, there is no mechanism of visibility by which
bias can become apparent to self or others.
160
At the same time, accountability helps
reinforce and establish norms because it signals their relevancy and strength.
161
Adopting language in the Model Code and Code of Conduct will promote
salient norms, transparency, and accountability in relation to our expectation that
judges take active steps to reduce the impact of their implicit biases on their judicial
decision-making. Expressing norms in ethical guidelines increases focus on specific
behaviors, which serves the interest of transparency because its very idea depends
on the assumption that another actor is watching.
162
Moreover, the Model Code and
Code of Conduct’s language should be updated so that judges, while not subject to
discipline for experiencing an implicit association, should be subject to discipline for
not participating in good faith efforts to curb their implicit associations. If the
guidelines have no teeth, there is nothing that will trigger formal accountability
and the efforts will be less effective.
163
In addition to norms and motivation, having the opportunity for “mindful
reflection on individuating features,”
164
is essential to overcoming an unconscious
reaction.
165
One way to create the opportunity to deliberate is for judges to make
the internal commitment before and during each case, bench memo, brief, hearing,
opinion, and order to not make decisions influenced by bias. In the first place, this
creates the opportunity to consider “individuating features.” In the second, research
has demonstrated that people will not make decisions based on bias when the choice
is clearly biased.
166
Judges can further operationalize this commitment by looking
for situational explanations to replace individual stereotypes
167
and deliberately
considering “countertypical associations” before and during judicial decision-
making.
168
Countertypical association is exposure to members of stereotyped groups
that we would respond to positively or exposure to a member of a negatively
158
Dovidio et al., supra note 14, at 179.
159
Id.
160
See Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 105051.
161
See id.; MCADAMS, supra note 102, at 7, 16, 62 (“By publicly endorsing a particular behavior, law tends to
make that behavior salient, thereby producing self-fulfilling expectations that it will occur.”).
162
See Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 105051.
163
See Kalev et al., supra note 141, at 590 (finding that corporate diversity efforts were most effective when
responsibility was assigned).
164
Quintanilla, supra note 85, at 24.
165
See Kang et al., supra note 11, at 117778.
166
Krieger & Fiske, supra note 15, at 1050.
167
Nordell, supra note 148.
168
See also infra text accompanying notes 196–97 (discussing the use of indirect countertypical associations to
reduce bias in lieu of diversity).
112 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
stereotyped group that does not share the stereotypical trait.
169
Judges could
incorporate countertypical associations by a screensaver, desk photo, or work of art
in their office.
170
Granted, there is no way to enforce compliance or ensure that a judge is
meaningfully deliberating, but as Alex Kozinski succinctly pointed out, “[j]udicial
ethics, where it counts, is hidden from view.”
171
We already count on judges to do
their best to discharge their duties faithfully and there is good reason to believe
that if court systems adopt norms protecting against implicit judicial bias, judges
will act responsibly to self-regulate in this area, just as they do in many others.
172
One potentially intransigent obstacle in creating the opportunity to
deliberate is the workload for judges. Over the past 100 years, cases in district
courts have shown an eleven-fold increase.
173
For federal appellate courts, the
increase was sixty-four fold.
174
In contrast, the population only increased by a factor
of four, district judges by a factor of ten, and circuit judges by a factor of six.
175
At
the state level, growth in cases over time has outpaced the increase in judges as
well with state judges increasing at only half the rate of cases.
176
I recognize that
this limits the opportunity to deliberate, but pending costly and systemic change,
these proposals are crafted with the judicial system’s status quo ante in mind.
A final method to curb implicit judicial bias is increasing the diversity on the
bench and in chambers. In the first place, it may be that judges who are members of
out-groups experience fewer implicit associations favoring in-groups than in-group
members.
177
Studying a small pool of judges, Jeffrey Rachlinski et al. found that
eighty-seven percent of white judges had a pro-white bias in contrast to forty-three
percent of black judges.
178
In addition, black judges had a significantly weaker pro-
white bias than their white counterparts.
179
At the same time, research shows that
countertypical associations, or exposure to people who run counter to our implicit
schemas, reduce the expression of implicit bias.
180
Lastly, some commentators
169
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1173.
170
See id.
171
Kozinski, supra note 118, at 1106.
172
See Geyh, supra note 29, at 69697 (discussing the judge’s responsibility to decide her own disqualification
motion); Shepard, supra note 133.
173
Albert Yoon, Law Clerks and the Institutional Design of the Federal Judiciary, 98 MARQ. L. REV. 131, 133
(2014).
174
Id.
175
Id.
176
CHARLES GARDNER GEYH, COURTING PERIL: THE POLITICAL TRANSFORMATION OF THE AMERICAN JUDICIARY 26
(2016).
177
Rachlinski et al., supra note 19.
178
Id.
179
Id. (finding that black judges made the schema-inconsistent match twenty-six milliseconds faster than the
schema-consistent match while white judges made the schema-inconsistent match 216 milliseconds faster
than the schema-consistent match).
180
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1170 (citing Nilanjana Dasgupta & Shaki Asgari, Seeing Is Believing:
Exposure to Counterstereotypic Women Leaders and Its Effect on the Malleability of Automatic Gender
Stereotyping, 40 J.
EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 642, 64954 (2004)).
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 113
postulate that people in the in-group and people in the out-groups can “see two
different realities.”
181
For instance, “[w]hite people . . . might only hear a racist
remark, [but] people of color might register subtler actions, like someone scooting
away slightly on a busbehaviors the majority may not even be aware they’re
doing.”
182
Currently, white men hold judgeships in the greatest number. In federal
courts, white men are 45.6% of circuit court judges and 49.3% of district court
judges.
183
In comparison, women hold thirty-seven percent of circuit judgeships and
thirty-four percent of district judgeships.
184
By race, black people are thirteen
percent of circuit judges and fourteen percent of district judges.
185
Even more
concerning is the fact that one circuit has only one woman out of nine judges, seven
of thirteen circuits have only one black person sitting on them (this includes the
Eleventh Circuit which has the largest population of black people in the country),
and one circuit has no black judges at all.
186
For district courts, the disparity is
worse. Eleven of ninety-one courts have no women on them and forty-four have no
black people serving on them.
187
Even starker, black women hold only 4.4% of
circuit judgeships and 6.1% of district judgeships.
188
State court judges and clerks in both federal and state courts have a higher
ratio of white men, too. For instance, black judges are between seven to nine
percent of state court judges across all levels
189
and female judges occupy thirty-one
to thirty-six percent of state judicial seats across all courts.
190
At the same time, the
181
Nordell, supra note 148.
182
Id.
183
BARRY J. MCMILLION, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., R43426, U.S. CIRCUIT AND DISTRICT COURT JUDGES: PROFILE OF
SELECT CHARACTERISTICS 8, 20 (2017), https://fas.org/sgp/crs/misc/R43426.pdf.
184
Id. at 4, 15.
185
Id. at 5, 17.
186
Id. Other racial minorities are also underrepresented. For instance, there are four circuit courts with no
Hispanic judges and nine circuit courts with no Asian American judges. Id. at 5.
187
Id. at 15, 17. As with circuit courts, Asian American and Hispanic judges are also underrepresented. Asian
Americans hold 2.8% of district judgeships despite being 5.8% of the total U.S. population and Hispanic
judges hold about 10% of district judgeships and represent 18% of the U.S. population. Id. at 20; The Rise of
Asian Americans, P
EW RES. CTR. (June 19, 2012), http://www.pewsocialtrends.org/2012/06/19/the-rise-of-
asian-americans/; Antonio Flores, How the U.S. Hispanic Population Is Changing, PEW RES. CTR. (Sept. 18,
2017), http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/09/18/how-the-u-s-hispanic-population-is-changing/. By
comparison, black people make up about 13% of the population and women about 50.8%. Kristen Bialik, 5
Facts About Black Americans., PEW RES. CTR. (Feb. 22, 2018), http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-
tank/2018/02/22/5-facts-about-blacks-in-the-u-s/; QuickFacts, U.S.
CENSUS BUREAU,
https://www.census.gov/quickfacts/fact/table/US/SEX255217#viewtop (last visited Aug. 29, 2020).
188
MCMILLION, supra note 184, at 8, 20.
189
National Database on Judicial Diversity in State Courts, AM. BAR ASSN,
http://apps.americanbar.org/abanet/jd/display/national.cfm (last visited Sept. 9, 2019)
[https://web.archive.org/web/20190909143807/http://apps.americanbar.org/abanet/jd/display/national.cfm].
190
2017 US State Court Women Judges, NAWJ, https://www.nawj.org/statistics/2017-us-state-court-women-
judges (last visited Aug. 30, 2020).
114 Indiana Journal of Law and Social Equality [9:94
estimated percentage of minority members in judicial clerkships is 6.5% and women
in judicial clerkships is about eighteen percent.
191
Perhaps because these numbers are so stark, Kang et al. recognize the value
in diversifying the bench but also recognize that it would be a costly endeavor.
192
While increasing judicial diversity at the federal level may require fewer economic
resources because an appointment process is already in place,
193
it would still take
significant political resources for alignment around diverse candidates. It is
possible, however, as the Obama Administration’s record shows.
194
In contrast,
because many states select judges through election,
195
ensuring diverse results
would be a very complicated and resource-laden endeavor that would likely require
revamping entire selection processes through constituent and legislative support.
With this in mind, one possible stopgap measure to true diversity is to stimulate
countertypical associations by using pictures, videos, and other indirect contact.
196
Indirect countertypical associations are not a substitute for actual diversity, and
cannot be expected to promote accountability, transparency, and other norm-
reinforcing interactions among peers to the same degree. However, they are likely,
as Kang et al. suggest, worth experimenting with.
197
Finally, it is possible that judges will be unable to acknowledge their implicit
bias because they will not want to lose face or delegitimize their rulings.
198
However, drawing a broad conclusion like this is suspect given that judges
occasionally admit general error in writing in legal opinions
199
or, notably,
acknowledge bias even after leaving office.
200
It might be helpful to remember our
original premise, which is that judges are human. And humans are capable of
change.
201
191
ELIZABETH CHAMBLISS, IILP REVIEW 2017: THE STATE OF DIVERSITY AND INCLUSION IN THE LEGAL PROFESSION
16, 23, http://www.theiilp.com/resources/Pictures/IILP_2017_Demographic_Survey.pdf.
192
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1170 (“[A]ny serious diversification of the bench, the bar, and staff would take
enormous resources, both economic and political.”).
193
See FAQs: Federal Judges, U.S. CTS., http://www.uscourts.gov/faqs-federal-judges.
194
Under President Obama, sixty-nine percent of circuit court appointees and sixty-two percent of district
court appointees were nontraditional appointees, i.e. not white males. MCMILLION, supra note 184, at 9, 22.
195
Forty-two states provide for the election of at least some judges. Charles Gardner Geyh, Why Judicial
Elections Stink, 64 OHIO ST. L. J. 43, 52 (2003).
196
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1171.
197
Id.
198
See MCADAMS, supra note 102, 22021.
199
See City of Erie v. Pap’s A.M., 529 U.S. 277, 316 (1999) (Souter, J., dissenting) (acknowledging a contrary
position to one earlier stated and explaining it as “[i]gnorance, sir, ignorance” (quoting McGrath v.
Kristensen, 340 U. S. 162, 178 (1950) (Jackson, J., concurring)).
200
See James C. McKinley, Jr., Ex-Brooklyn Judge Seeks Reversal of His Verdict in 1999 Killing, N.Y. TIMES
(Dec. 12, 2013), https://www.nytimes.com/2013/12/13/nyregion/ex-brooklyn-judge-seeks-reversal-of-his-
verdict-in-1999-murder-case.html.
201
For instance, consider that in 2016, a C-SPAN caller made headlines after identifying as a white man from
North Carolina and asking how he could become less biased, so he could “be a better American.” Paul
Walter, Caller Admits Racism and Is Gently Advised, C-SPAN (Aug. 22, 2016), https://www.c-
span.org/video/?c4618001/user-clip-caller-admits-racism-gently-advised.
2021] Honesty Is the Best Policy 115
CONCLUSION
Because the days of casting judges as perfectly impartial are gone, and
because the social science research on implicit bias is clear, we should embrace a
view of the judiciary that allows them to be human but also promotes fairness,
legitimacy, and procedural justice. This means acknowledging that judges
experience implicit bias, while neither concluding that impartiality is dead nor
avoiding responsibility for implicit bias’s effects. Rather, just as the ermine cloak
used to be the litmus paper on which we gauged our judges’ purity, now we should
use their actions in response to, and in the face of, implicit associations to prove
their sincerity in curbing unfairness resulting from unchecked implicit bias.
The methods I propose are intended to help us, and our judges, do just that.
Court systems can employ these steps through existing administrative, ethical, and
disciplinary frameworks by requiring judges to take the IAT, mandating implicit
bias training, increasing judicial diversity while employing other opportunities for
countertypical associations, and operationalizing mindful deliberation. In addition,
norm-reinforcing steps like disciplinary sanctions for not participating in these
measures and updates to the Model Code and Code Conduct should be employed.
These efforts are unlikely to be perfect, but I share Kang et al.’s view that “[e]ffort is
not always sufficient, but it ought to count for something.”
202
202
Kang et al., supra note 11, at 1169.