MOVING AWAY FROM
THE DEATH PENALTY
Arguments, Trends and Perspectives
Moving Away from the Death Penalty:
Arguments, Trends and Perspectives
MOVING AWAY FROM THE
DEATH PENALTY
ARGUMENTS, TRENDS AND PERSPECTIVES
New York, 2015
MOVING AWAY FROM THE DEATH PENALTY:
ARGUMENTS, TRENDS AND PERSPECTIVES
© 2015 United Nations
Worldwide rights reserved. This book or any portion thereof may
not be reproduced without the express written permission of the
author(s), editor, or the publisher, except as permitted by law.
The ndings, interpretations and conclusions expressed herein are those of
the author(s) and do not necessarily reect the views of the United Nations.
The designations employed and the presentation of the material in this
publication do not imply the expression of any opinion whatsoever
on the part of the Secretariat of the United Nations concerning the
legal status of any country, territory, city or area, or of its authorities,
or concerning the delimitation of its frontiers or boundaries.
Editor: Ivan Šimonovi´c
Design and layout: dammsavage studio
Cover image:
The cover features an adaptation of a photograph of the feet of a man convicted
of murder, seen during a hanging. Photo credit: EPA/Raed Qutena. The back
cover graphic line represents a declining percentage of United Nations Member
States that practice the death penalty (those that have not abolished it in law or
practice), from 89% in 1975, ending at 27% in 2015, in 10 year increments.
Electronic version of this publication is available at:
www.ohchr.org/EN/NewYork/Pages/Resources.aspx
Sales no.: E.15.XIV.6
ISBN: 978-92-1-154215-8
eISBN: 978-92-1-057589-8
CONTENTS
Preface – Ban Ki-moon, United Nations Secretary-General p.6
Introduction An Abolitionist’s Perspective, Ivan Šimonovi´c p.8
Chapter 1 – Wrongful Convictions p.22
Kirk Bloodsworth, Without DNA evidence I’d still be behind bars p.24
Brandon Garrett, DNA evidence casts light on aws in system p.30
Gil Garcetti, In the United States, growing doubts about the death penalty p.39
Saul Lehrfreund, Wrongful convictions and miscarriages of justice
in death penalty trials in the Caribbean, Africa and Asia p.48
Chapter 2 – Myth of Deterrence p.66
Carolyn Hoyle & Roger Hood, Deterrence and public opinion p.68
Je Fagan, Deterrence and the death penalty in international perspective p.84
Chapter 3 – Discrimination p.100
Damien Echols, The terrors of prison fade slowly p.103
Stephen Braga, Damien Echols and the West Memphis Three Case p.107
Stephen Bright, Imposition of the death penalty upon the poor, racial
minorities, the intellectually disabled and the mentally ill p.115
Arif Bulkan, The death penalty in the Commonwealth Carribean:
Justice out of reach? p.130
Usha Ramanathan, The death penalty in India: Down a slippery slope p.150
Alice Mogwe, The death penalty in Botswana: Barriers to equal justice p.170
Innocent Maja,The death penalty in Zimbabwe: Legal ambiguitites p.180
Chapter 4 – Values p.184
Sister Helen Prejean, Death penalty: victims’ perspective p.187
Mario Marazziti, World religions and the death penalty p.192
Nigel Rodley, The death penalty as a human rights issue p.204
Christof Heyns & Thomas Probert, The right to life and
the progressive abolition of the death penalty p.214
Paul Bhatti, Towards a moratorium on the death penalty p.227
Chapter 5 – Leadership p.234
Federico Mayor, Leadership and the abolition of the death penalty p.236
Mai Sato, Vox populi, vox dei? A closer look at the ‘public opinion’
argument for retention p.250
H.E. Mr. Didier Burkhalter, Federal Councilor and Minister of
Foreign Aairs of Switzerland, Leadership through dialogue p.259
H.E. Mr. Tsakhia Elbegdorj, President of Mongolia,
Mongolia honours human life and dignity p.266
Laurent Fabius, Minister of Foreign Aairs and International
Development of France, Towards universal abolition of the death penalty p.268
Mohamed Moncef Marzouki, former President of the Republic
of Tunisia, Challenges related to abolition of the death penalty in
Arab and Islamic Countries: Tunisia’s model p.272
Prime Minister Matteo Renzi, President of the Council of
Ministers of the Italian Republic, The role of leadership p.276
H.E. Dr. Boni Yayi, President of the Republic of Benin,
A ght for the progress of humanity p.282
Chapter 6 – Trends and Perspectives p.284
Salil Shetty, Global death penalty trends since 2012 p.286
Afterword, Zeid Ra’ad Al Hussein, United Nations
High Commissioner for Human Rights p.295
Acknowledgements p.297
6 7
PREFACE
Today, more than four out of ve countries have either abolished
the death penalty or do not practice it. Globally, there is a rm trend
towards abolition, with progress in all regions of the world. Member
States representing a variety of legal systems, traditions, cultures and
religious backgrounds have taken a position in favour of abolition
of the death penalty. Some States that opposed the abolition of the
death penalty in the recent past have moved to abolish it; others have
imposed a moratorium on its use. The application of the death penalty
appears to be conned to an ever-narrowing minority of countries.
Those remaining States cite a number of reasons for retaining the
death penalty, including what they see as its deterrent eect; that it
is consistent with public opinion; that it is equally applied against all
perpetrators; and that there are sucient judicial safeguards to ensure
defendants are not wrongfully convicted.
Over the past two years, the Oce of the High Commissioner for
Human Rights has convened a series of important panel discussions
on the death penalty, seeking to address these issues. The events drew
on the experiences of government ocials, academic experts and civil
society from various regions which, in recent years, have made progress
towards abolition or the imposition of a moratorium. They covered
key aspects of the issue, including data on wrongful convictions and
the disproportionate targeting of marginalized groups of people. This
publication brings together the contributions of the panel members
as well as other experts on this subject. Taken as a whole, they make a
compelling case for moving away from the death penalty.
The death penalty has no place in the 21st century. Leaders across the
globe must boldly step forward in favour of abolition. I recommend
this book in particular to those States that have yet to abolish the
death penalty. Together, let us end this cruel and inhumane practice.
Ban Ki-moon
Secretary-General, United Nations
“The death penalty has no place in the 21st century. Leaders
across the globe must boldly step forward in favour of
abolition. I recommend this book in particular to those
States that have yet to abolish the death penalty. Together,
let us end this cruel and inhumane practice.—Ban Ki-moon
United Nations Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon attending OHCHR’s global panel: “Moving away from
the death penalty – wrongful convictions”, New York, 28 June 2013 © UN Photo/Evan Schneider
8 9
INTRODUCTION:
AN ABOLITIONIST’S PERSPECTIVE
Why yet another book on the death penalty? The answer is simple: As
long as the death penalty exists, there is a need for advocacy against it.
This book provides arguments and analysis, reviews trends and shares
perspectives on moving away from the death penalty.
This book, rst published in 2014, has been updated and expanded,
providing victims’ and United Nations human rights mechanisms’
perspective, a new chapter on the role of leadership in moving away
from the death penalty. The new High Commissioner for Human
Rights, Zeid Ra’ad Al Hussein, appointed in 2014, has provided
an afterword.
Abolishing the death penalty is a collective eort which requires
commitment, cooperation and time. As a student in 1977 in the
Socialist Federal Republic of Yugoslavia, I was allowed to write my
high school graduation essay on the abolition of the death penalty.
At the time, Yugoslavia practiced the death penalty and had limited
freedom of expression. Against this backdrop, I am especially thankful
for the courage and support of my teachers.
Much has happened since 1977: Yugoslavia broke up more than 20
years ago, and all its successor states have abolished the death penalty.
Globally, most countries have gradually been moving away from the
death penalty—by reducing the number of crimes punishable by
death, introducing additional legal safeguards, proclaiming a morato-
rium on executions or abolishing the death penalty altogether.
Amnesty International reports that in the mid-1990s, 40 countries
were known to carry out executions every year. Since then, this
number has halved. About 160 countries have abolished the death
penalty in law or in practice; of those, 100 have abolished it alto-
gether. In 2007, when the death penalty moratorium resolution
was rst adopted by the United Nations General Assembly, it was
supported by 104 states. In the most recent vote, in 2014, it was
“In the 21st century a right to take someone’s
life is not a part of the social contract
between citizens and a state any more....
— Ivan Šimonovi´c
Human rights activists light candles in observance of the World Day against the Death Penalty. © EPA/MK Chaudhry
10 11
supported by 117 states.
1
In 2014 there were at least 607 documented
executions
2
. While the number of executing states remained the same
in 2014 as in 2013, the number of documented executions dropped
by 22percent.
While this is grounds for optimism, there are also reasons for concern.
The number of death sentences imposed in 2014 worldwide was at
least 2,446, which represents a 28percent increase over 2013.
3
Can
the recent steady global trend towards abolition be reversed?
Some human rights achievements dating back to the early 1990s
are currently facing renewed challenges.
4
Armed conicts involving
non-state actors, triggering ethnic and religious divisions, are prolifer-
ating globally. Many states and regimes face instability. Fear of violent
extremism, organized crime and especially drug tracking make
tough punishment for these crimes appealing. It creates an impression
of commitment and is much easier and cheaper than increasing the
eciency of the law enforcement and justice systems. It is still to be
seen whether these setbacks will stall or reverse the trend of moving
away from the death penalty. This book seeks to contribute to eorts
to prevent this from happening.
In 2012, 35 years after my graduation essay, now as United Nations
Assistant Secretary-General for Human Rights, I was able to con-
tribute to a discussion on the death penalty at the United Nations
in New York. The panel discussion on “moving away from the death
penalty” that I moderated in 2012 included a distinguished group
of member states representatives, experts, civil society activists
and a victim of wrongful conviction. The panel identied three
main reasons for member states’ decisions on the death penalty:
the possibility of wrongful convictions, crime deterrence or the
1 UN Doc. A/69/PV.73, pp.17-18 (18 December 2014)
2 Amnesty International, Death Sentences and Executions in 2014 (London, Amnesty International,
2015)
3 The number of death sentences imposed in Egypt—509—signicantly contributed to this
trend. By the end of 2014 Pakistan lifted a six-year moratorium. The real number of executions
is unknown. Some countries—including China, in which most executions take place—do
not publicly release data on executions. China appears to be moving cautiously away from the
death penalty, initially reducing the number of crimes punishable by death and introducing
additional safeguards, which may heavily and positively inuence overall trends.
4 A series of world conferences in the early 1990s made signicant progress on human rights. But
the principles agreed to there are currently being challenged.
lack thereof, and discrimination against marginalised groups in
its implementation
5
.
Recognizing their importance, the Oce of the High Commissioner
for Human Rights in New York organized debates on each of these
three issues, involving member states, non-governmental organiza-
tions and academia. We benetted from the valuable support of the
permanent missions to the United Nations of Chile, Italy and the
Philippines as co-organisers for two of these panels
6
. Together with
the permanent mission of Italy, we organised an additional panel on
national experiences with a moratorium on executions
7
. Finally, in
April 2015, at the United Nations Congress on Crime Prevention
and Criminal Justice in Doha, Qatar, we also organised a panel dis-
cussion on the death penalty, drugs and terrorism
8
.
United Nations Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon participated in four
of these events as the keynote speaker, and has provided a preface to
this book, which presents contributions by panellists at these events and
other prominent authorities on issues surrounding the death penalty.
The views expressed in these articles reect the personal positions of
their authors and not necessarily the institutional position of the Oce
of the High Commissioner for Human Rights or the United Nations.
As the editor of the book, I hope that you will nd their ideas interest-
ing and challenging, whether you agree with them or not.
The panels on which this book is based, apart from the one held in
Doha, took place in New York, thus beneting from the proximity
of a number of top-level death penalty experts, civil society activists
as well as two victims of wrongful conviction. Nevertheless, we are
fortunate to be able to present an even larger number of articles by
African, Asian, Caribbean and European authors.
5 See brochure on the panel Moving away from the death penalty: Lessons from National Experiences
(UN OHCHR, New York 2012, 25 p.)
6 OHCHR Global Panel: “Moving Away from the Death Penalty-Deterrence and Public Opin-
ion”, co-sponsored by the permanent missions of the Philippines and Chile, 24 January 2014
UNHQ, New York; OHCHR Global Panel: “Moving away from the Death Penalty - Discrim-
ination against Marginalised Groups”, 24 April 2014, UNHQ, New York
7 “Best Practices and Challenges in implementing a Moratorium on the Death Penalty”,
UNHQ, New York, 2 July 2014.
8 “Panel discussion: Death Penalty, Drugs and Terrorism”, 13
th
United Nations Congress on
Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice, Doha, Qatar, 14 April 2015.
12 13
The question of the death penalty’s deterrent eect, which is
addressed in chapter 2, has attracted scholarly and political attention
for centuries. Are public executions brutal relics of the past or e-
cient preventive measures? Does capital punishment for relatively
minor crimes increase the frequency of more severe crimes because
the risk to perpetrators is no greater? Does it expose crime witnesses
to greater risk? The great majority of countries have stopped public
executions and reduced the application of the death penalty to only
the most severe crimes, but does the death penalty deter crime at all?
Government actors often feel public pressure to retain the death
penalty as a crime control measure. However, there is no evidence
that it is in fact a deterrent. In countries that have abolished the
death penalty, this has in general not resulted in an increase in serious
crime. The most comprehensive survey on the relationship between
the death penalty and murder rates, which was carried out for the
United Nations in 1988 and updated in 1996, found that “research
has failed to provide scientic proof that executions have a greater
deterrent eect than life imprisonment. Such proof is unlikely to be
forthcoming. The evidence as a whole gives no positive support to
the deterrent hypothesis.
10
Statistics from countries that have abol-
ished the death penalty show that the absence of the death penalty
has not resulted in an increase in serious crime.
In 2012, research from the US-based National Research Council
conrmed the United Nations report’s conclusions: “Research to
date on the eect of capital punishment on homicide is not informa-
tive about whether capital punishment decreases, increases or has no
eect on homicide rates.
11
Recent US government statistics conrm
the lack of supporting evidence for the deterrent eect of capital
punishment.
12
10 Roger Hood, The Death Penalty—A Worldwide Perspective (Clarendon Press, 1996), p.238. The
fth edition of this book, co-authored by Carolyn Hoyle and Roger Hood, who have also
contributed to this volume, was published in 2015.
11 National Research Council, Deterrence and the Death Penalty (Washington, DC, National Acade-
mies Press, 2012).
12 According to the U.S. Department of Justice’s annual FBI uniform crime report for 2012, the
national murder rate remained approximately the same in 2012 as in 2011. The northeast, the
region with the fewest executions, had the lowest murder rate of any region, and its murder
rate decreased 3.4 per cent from the previous year. The south, which carries out the most ex-
ecutions of any region, again had the highest murder rate in 2012. U.S. Department of Justice,
Crime in the United States, 2012 (Washington, DC, 2013).
The book consists of six chapters. The rst three chapters are dedi-
cated to the three issues identied at our initial 2012 panel as decisive
for decision-making on moving away from the death penalty and
on which we held individual panels in 2013 and 2014: wrongful
convictions (chapter 1), the myth of deterrence (chapter 2) and
discrimination (chapter 3). They were supplemented with three
additional chapters, covering other issues highly relevant to decisions
about the death penalty. Values related to the sanctity of life and the
limits of state power are discussed in chapter 4. Chapter 5 deals with
the role of leadership in moving away from the death penalty. Chap-
ter 6, looking forward, provides data and examines trends.
Chapter 1 addresses wrongful convictions from the personal perspec-
tives of a wrongfully convicted person, an academic, a civil society
activist and a former prosecutor. It is not easy for governments and
leading representatives of justice systems to acknowledge that, despite
heavy investment in the legal process, wrongful convictions occur. It
is even more alarming that they occur in death penalty cases, includ-
ing in the most sophisticated justice systems.
DNA test results have conrmed long-standing warnings by aca-
demia and civil society in this regard. In the United States, the rst
country to use post-conviction genetic testing on a large scale, 140
death row inmates have been exonerated since the 1970s.
9
Had public pressure to identify and punish perpetrators made wrongful
convictions more likely in the murder and rape cases for which exoner-
ating DNA evidence became available? Wouldn’t similar pressure have
occurred in other serious crimes in which such a test was not possible?
If this is a problem in advanced industrial countries, with well-re-
sourced legal systems, what about those with less sophisticated legal
systems with fewer safeguards, opportunities for review and resources?
It is clear that wrongful convictions do occur and that it is unacceptable
for them to end in execution. The death penalty is simply too nal,
given the imperfections of even the most sophisticated legal systems.
9 For an analysis of some of their cases, see Brandon L. Garrett, Convicting the Innocent (Cambridge,
Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 2011). The Innocence Project, founded by Barry Scheck
and Peter Neufeld at Cardozo Law School in 1992, has done signicant work on exonerations.
Gradually it evolved and involved many other people and institutions in identifying and freeing
the wrongfully convicted. See www.innocenceproject.org; see also Garrett’s article in this book.
14 15
should there not be more questioning of individual guilt and mitigat-
ing circumstances of alleged perpetrators belonging to marginalised
groups, instead of discrimination against them?
Besides the three main issues relevant for abolition or retention of
the death penalty, around which the rst three chapters of this book
are organised, there are many other issues. The economic eect of the
death penalty is one of them.
In various circumstances, this
may be astonishingly dierent.
I was present at a meeting
during which the top United
Nations ocial, speaking to
the leader of a developing
country that carried out fre-
quent executions after legal
proceedings that were considerably below international standards,
pleaded for abolition or at least a moratorium on executions. “I have
no money to feed them or build them prisons, the leader responded;
“a bullet is cheaper. But if you want them, he added, “you can take
them back with you to New York.
International norms are clear that if the death penalty exists, those
facing it should be aorded special protection and guarantees to
ensure a fair trial, above and beyond the guarantees aorded to defen-
dants in non-capital cases. This creates a paradox. The death penalty
is cheaper than other forms of punishment only if its execution does
not require complex legal proceedings or safeguards, such as the use
of forensics and reviews. However, in such cases the likelihood of
wrongful conviction is exacerbated. But if the number of safeguards
is increased, the death penalty becomes the most expensive form of
punishment, as the bulk of US research clearly indicates.
15
In fact, the cost of the death penalty is so much higher than the cost
of a life sentence without parole that abolitionists, especially in the
United States, use this argument in their campaigns.
16
Even when the
15 For a summary of these studies, see Rudolph J. Gerber and John M. Johnson, The Top 10 Death
Penalty Myths (Westport, Connecticut, Praeger, 2007), pp. 165-171.
16 See Death Penalty Information Center, Smart on Crime: Reconsidering the Death Penalty in a Time
of Economic Crisis (Washington, DC, 2009).
Most justice systems, in deciding guilt, accept the ethical principle
in dubio pro reo (when in doubt, [decide] for the accused). By way of
analogy, if there is no proof that the death penalty deters crime, why
would we continue to apply it? It may be out of ignorance, or deter-
rence may be a g leaf covering other motives: the desire for talionic
revenge,
13
or to protect dominant social groups and their interests; in
most retentionist states the death penalty disproportionately aects
socially marginalised groups—migrants, racial and ethnic minorities,
the poor and people with mental disabilities—some of them victims
of compounded discrimination.
Chapter 3 raises concern over the disproportionate eects of the death
penalty on marginalised groups in Africa, the Caribbean, India and
the United States. Marginalised groups are overrepresented among
the wrongfully convicted to a disturbing extent.
14
People with a
mental disability or without a competent defence lawyer are more
vulnerable to pressure to make a false confession, and jurors may be
more prone to suspect a defendant who is dierent from them. Also,
in too many legal systems, nancial resources, or the lack thereof,
determine the quality of legal representation.
From a moral perspective, the attitude and response to crimes
committed by members of marginalised groups should not be to dis-
criminate against them further, but precisely the opposite: to look for
mitigating circumstances, which may have been a consequence of the
discrimination they have been subjected to.
There needs to be some soul-searching and recognition of responsi-
bility on the part of society, when members of marginalised groups
are involved in crimes. To what extent have discrimination and unjust
treatment of members of racial or ethnic minorities contributed to
the commission of crime? How has a life of deprivation and lack of
opportunity for the poor, uneducated or mentally disabled contributed
to the commission of their crimes? From the perspective of justice,
13 Talion, or lex talionis in Latin, is a principle that perpetrators should receive as punishment the
same injuries that they inicted upon their victims. Its origins can be traced to early Babylo-
nian law, which subsequently inuenced Biblical and early Roman views on punishment. It is
also reected in later (including some current) justications of corporal punishment.
14 See Brandon L. Garrett, Convicting the Innocent (Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University
Press, 2011), p. 235.
“THE EVOLUTION OF
HUMAN RIGHTS HAS
REDUCED STATE SOVER
-
EIGNTY IN MANY AREAS;
THE DEATH PENALTY SHOULD
BE ONE OF THEM AS WELL.
Ivan Šimonovi´c
16 17
It is also questionable whether, in practice, the death penalty helps
provide closure, as it is so often argued. In most retentionist states
it is gradually being reduced in scope to exclude minors, pregnant
woman, people with mental disabilities and many others. For example,
in the United States, prosecutors seek the death penalty in only about
2 per cent of intentional homicide cases, and the death sentence is
imposed in only about half of those. Of those death sentences, about
two-thirds are reversed on appeal. In the end, just about one-third of
1 per cent are executed, and this after an average delay of 12 years.
18
Does the possibility of the death penalty psychologically prevent clo-
sure and healing—could these in fact come much sooner in cases that
result in a long prison term or a life sentence without the possibility
of parole? Does not the frustration of waiting in vain for a perpetrator
to be executed not actually hurt those seeking revenge more than if
there was no death penalty at all?
Are juries more reluctant to nd defendants guilty if there is a chance
that they might be executed? Does that lead to more acquittals and
thus hurt victims and their families even more when they see suspects
go free? Furthermore, does the death penalty aect other innocent
third parties more than other penalties? Do families of convicts suer
more because of the prolonged death threat to their loved ones?
19
May some of them not also be perceived as victims?
Although the analysis of the social, economic and psychological eects
of the death penalty clearly indicates its harmful eects, it can also be
attacked in a Kantian moral safe-haven, detached from any measurable
social eect and scientic evidence. In my view, the essence of the
moral opposition to the death penalty is the argument that killing is
simply wrong, whether we relate it doctrinally to a human right to life
and the right not be subjected to cruel or inhuman punishment, or not.
No one can blame victims and their families for wanting revenge,
including through the death penalty. In their pain and loss, they are
entitled to that desire. However, laws exist to prevent individuals from
18 Gerber and Johnson, The Top 10 Death Penalty Myths, pp. 196-197 and 222.
19 Psychiatrists warn that many family members, especially those who were the primary support
of a capital defendant, experience depression and symptoms associated with post-traumatic
stress disorder.
majority of public opinion polls indicate support for the death pen-
alty, when confronted with nancial analysis that indicates that a life
sentence without parole could produce savings that could instead go
towards compensation of victims and their families, public opinion
often tends to sway in favour of the latter option.
On the other end of the scale from the pragmatic approach are the
moral and value-based arguments regarding the death penalty. Chap-
ter 4 addresses the relationship between the death penalty and values
through an article reecting a victim’s perspective, two articles that
are potentially controversial, as is so often the case when values are
concerned—one dealing with major religious doctrine and the other
with politics, as well as two articles assessing the death penalty from
the perspective of international human rights obligations
Despite the lack of evidence of deterrence, retentionist’ arguments
can be articulated and are indeed perceived by some as moral ones.
Essentially, the reasoning is based on a “just retribution” argument—
changing the perspective from utilitarian to Kantian. If crime deserves
adequate punishment for moral reasons, it makes social consequences
and the deterrent eect (or lack thereof) less relevant. Furthermore,
even if capital punishment has negative social consequences, it should
be retained because it is proportionate to some crimes—vivat iustitia,
pereat mundus (justice should live even if the world were to die).
When discussing the death penalty from the perspective of values,
it is critical to bring the victims’ perspectives into the debate. Their
position certainly carries important moral and political leverage.
However, those perspectives at times seem to be quite dierent. Some
family members of murder victims are among the strongest support-
ers of the death penalty, well organized and inuential. But others are
equally strongly convinced that murder cannot be countered with
murder. They do not want the lives of their loved ones to be avenged
with more violence, and instead of focusing on retribution, they try
to set themselves free from their trauma through forgiveness, healing
and restoration.
17
17 In the United States they have formed an association called Murder Victims’ Families for Rec-
onciliation. Membership requirements are that a close family member has been murdered and
that they oppose the death penalty. Some of their stories have been collected in Rachel King,
Don’t Kill in Our Names (Rutgers University Press, 2003).
18 19
21st century, the right to take another person’s life is no longer a part
of the social contract between citizens and the state. The time when
Rousseau reluctantly accepted such a sacrice as a part of the social con-
tract, necessary to keep peace in society, has long gone. Locke believed
that political power includes the right to pass laws that carry the death
penalty. Not anymore. The evolution of human rights has reduced state
sovereignty in many areas; the death penalty should be one of them.
But what about public opinion and democracy and the “popular sov-
ereignty” argument in many countries, where the majority is in favour
of the death penalty?
22
Even when that is the case, it does not preclude
intellectual and political leaders’ responsibility to push for abolition. Is
it not precisely the role of leadership to inuence society to become
more moral? Instead of “killing for votes” and death-penalty populism,
is it not their duty to share with their people relevant information, that
they may not be aware of, and help change mind-sets and attitudes?
23
Chapter 5 highlights the importance of leadership in moving away
from the death penalty. To stand for abolition or even for moratorium is
often not popular. To change the tide requires courageous and commit-
ted leadership and a successful information campaign. Contributions
in this chapter are provided by international leaders and heads of state
and government from dierent cultures, continents and backgrounds,
each of whom contributed to moving away from the death penalty
nationally and internationally. The chapter also includes an article on
the relevance of public messaging and information sharing for inu-
encing popular attitudes towards the death penalty and its abolition.
Every book, including this one, should have a conclusion or a for-
ward-looking ending. Chapter 6 of the book includes a contribution
by the secretary-general of Amnesty International dealing with statis-
tics and trends in moving away from the death penalty.
22 Perhaps a little exaggerated, but with a point: “The people who know the least about how
the system of death sentencing functions appear to be the ones who support it most”—Craig
Haney, Death by Design: Capital Punishment as a Social Psychological System (New York, Oxford
University Press, 2005), p. 219. The lack of information-sharing on the death penalty is espe-
cially drastic in Japan, a retentionist country with strong public support for the death penalty,
which provides no ocial information on how many people are on death row, how and when
sentenced people are selected for execution or what the costs are for the death penalty com-
pared with the alternative punishment (see the contributions by Hoyle and Hood and Mai Sato
to this volume as well as Sato’s book The Death Penalty in Japan, Will the Public Tolerate Abolition?
(Wiesbaden, Springer, 2014).
23 See Sato, The Death Penalty in Japan.
pursuing vengeance and their own vision of justice. If they do anyway
(if, for example, a victim kills a perpetrator) then they become per-
petrators and pay the price, both legally and morally. Although we
may feel empathy with such a victim seeking revenge, Nietzsche’s
warning—that when ghting monsters you must take care not to
become one yourself—should be remembered. Killing by the state is
wrong as well, potentially even worse than killing by an individual.
Individuals can sometimes kill in self-defence; states have such a range
of options for protecting people from a threatening individual that
killing is disproportionate to the danger that person represents. An
individual might kill out of passion or be criminally insane. The state,
when administering the death penalty, always kills after reection,
fully aware and accepting of the consequences.
An individual who kills, whether brought to justice or not, at least
pays for the violation of a fundamental moral rule through his or her
guilty conscience. When a state kills, it kills through its ocials, with-
out a guilty conscience; executioners are just doing their job.
20
There
is a tendency, especially in the developed retentionist countries, to
carry out the death penalty in an increasingly organized, technical and
bureaucratic manner, favouring teamwork and a piecemeal approach,
without thorough reection, emotion or individual responsibility.
21
Is it acceptable that killing takes place without anyone being morally
responsible for it? Is a state that kills a dangerous state? Can its right
to kill be misused against enemies of the state or enemies of those in
power? Is such a state, in essence, more prone to also violate other
human rights? If a state can kill, can it also torture when it is deemed
necessary—also without guilt on the part of the decision-makers,
through professional torturers doing their job? Can it send its citizens
to kill and be killed in war, not in self-defence but for some other
important “national interest”?
The death penalty, and the prerogative of the state to impose and execute
it, is related to our approach to contemporary state sovereignty. In the
20 In If This Is a Man (Collier Books, 1993), writing about Auschwitz, Primo Levi expressed
profound amazement: “How can one hit a man without anger?” In a similar moral sense should
not we ask ourselves how one can kill without guilt?
21 See Linda Ross Meyer, “The meaning of death, last words, last meals”, in Who Deserves to Die?
Constructing the Executable Subject, Austin Sarat and Karl Shoemaker, eds. (Amherst, University of
Massachusetts Press, 2011).
20 21
The use of the death penalty should no longer be perceived
as an entitlement of a sovereign state, because it violates
human rights. No national interest can justify human rights
violations such as the death penalty or torture. International
recognition and protection of human rights limit state powers
in this regard.
As long as the death penalty exists, it can be misused, for exam-
ple to target particular social groups and political opponents.
This book oers solid scientic evidence that supports abolition of
the death penalty. Although it is an advocacy book, mostly written
and edited by committed abolitionists, it clearly distinguishes between
facts and values. I encourage you to choose your stand on this issue
based on solid information.
I believe that one day, people will look back and wonder how it
was possible that the death penalty ever existed—just like, in most
societies today, it is already hard to understand how public executions
could ever have taken place. But when will it become universally
accepted that the death penalty violates the most fundamental human
right, the right to life? When will the day come when all states are
abolitionist—when there is no death penalty anywhere, anymore?
If we were to extrapolate a curve based on current trends—reduction
of the number of crimes punishable by death, moratoria on its exe-
cution, and full abolition—one could perhaps predict the number of
years it may take. But of course, in society, where human action can
change trends, such predictions are highly unreliable.
This is the main reason for publishing this book: it is a part of global
action to encourage global abolition of the death penalty. State power
has to have its limits, limits that uphold human rights.
Ivan Šimonovi´c
Assistant Secretary-General for Human Rights
New York, 31 August 2015
Let me contribute to the tracing of the way forward in moving away
from the death penalty by summarizing the arguments against it and
encouraging political and social leaders to act decisively towards
its abolition.
In my view, the death penalty is morally, socially and politically
wrong. Morally, killing is wrong. Killing on behalf of a state is wrong
as well. Some may believe that the death penalty is a just and moral
punishment for the most serious of crimes; victims and their families
are morally entitled to long for revenge. However, the social, political
and economic costs of such retribution are, in my opinion, too high:
Despite the greatest judicial eorts, wrongful convictions are
not avoidable. Capital punishment is simply too nal and
irrevocable, and makes it impossible to correct such mistakes.
The consequences for human error are too grave.
There is no conclusive empirical evidence that the death
penalty deters crime.
The death penalty is cheap only if it is carried out quickly.
Putting in place the necessary safeguards to prevent wrongful
convictions often makes legal proceedings lengthy and much
more costly than the longest prison sentence.
Long delays on death row make the death penalty a cruel
punishment, unacceptable from a human rights perspective.
Long delays in carrying out executions also postpone closure
and psychological healing for victims and their families, in a
way that (for example) the perpetrator’s return to prison to
begin a life sentence without parole does not.
Not all victims’ families support the death penalty, and even
among those who do, and who desire revenge or closure
through it, the great majority are left frustrated because only
a small minority of perpetrators are executed.
The death penalty is not imposed in a just and equal way.
Those sacriced on the altar of retributive justice are almost
always those who are vulnerable because of poverty, minority
status or mental disability.
22
“If a great country cannot ensure
that it won’t kill an innocent citizen,
it shouldn’t kill at all.
— Kirk Bloodsworth
23
CHAPTER 1
WRONGFUL CONVICTIONS
Chapter includes articles by an exoneree, an academic, a former prosecutor and an
activist for global abolition of the death penalty. Each of them oers a dierent
perspective. Their ndings converge on this point: there are a signicant number
of wrongful convictions, including in capital punishment cases, and executing the
innocent is simply not acceptable.
Kirk Bloodsworth was the rst person in the United States to be exonerated—
have his conviction reversed—through DNA testing. He was a young man, a
former marine from a humble background, without any criminal record, when
he became the victim of faulty eyewitness identication. After almost nine years
(two of them on death row) trying to prove his innocence, he was nally released.
Nowadays, he is a strong advocate for the abolition of the death penalty and for
the rights of the wrongfully convicted.
Brandon Garrett, an academic who does legal research on wrongful convictions,
their causes and ways to prevent them, analyses DNA-based exonerations in
the United States with particular attention to death penalty cases. He documents
how revelations about innocent people being sent to death row have permanently
altered the death penalty debate in the United States. In his view, jurisdictions in
other countries should similarly take note of the possibility of wrongful convictions.
Gil Garcetti is a convert. He served as a district attorney in Los Angeles County,
California, for many years and sometimes sought the death penalty for those he
prosecuted. However, the death penalty’s disproportionate eect on minorities and
the history of wrongful convictions led him to become an abolitionist. He had a
major role in the Proposition 34 campaign in California, which almost succeeded
in replacing the death penalty with life imprisonment without parole (it attracted
48 per cent of the vote).
Saul Lehrfreund discusses retentionist countries across the Caribbean, Africa and
Asia in which law and practice do not provide the protections in capital punish-
ment cases that are required by international human rights law. He concludes that
miscarriages of justice and executions of the innocent may occur in every system
and that this is a major reason that an increasing number of countries have moved
away from the death penalty.
Activists lie on the street to mark the World Day against the Death Penalty. / © EPA/Wael Hamzeh
24 25
WITHOUT DNA EVIDENCE,
I’D STILL BE BEHIND BARS
Kirk Noble Bloodsworth
1
I am the rst person in the United States to be exonerated from a
capital conviction through DNA testing. When I was exonerated in
1993, I had spent 8 years, 11 months, and 19 days (including two years
on death row) for a crime I did not commit. I am living proof that
America’s system of capital punishment is broken beyond repair.
In early 1984, before my life changed forever, I was just a humble
waterman living in Cambridge, Maryland. I was barely 23 years old,
newly married, and had just served four years in the US Marine
Corps. I had never been arrested in my life. This all changed on
August 9, 1984, when the police knocked on my door at 3 o’clock
in the morning and arrested me for the murder of Dawn Hamilton.
In a matter of days, I became the most hated man in Maryland.
How was I, a former US Marine with no criminal record and no
connection to the scene of the crime, convicted and sentenced to
death for a murder I didn’t commit?
On July 25, 1984, 9-year-old Dawn Hamilton was tragically raped
and murdered in Baltimore County. She was playing outside with a
friend in the morning when she came across two little boys shing
at a pond. A man nearby approached Dawn and oered to help
her nd her friend in their game of hide-and-seek. That was the
last time Dawn was seen alive. Her body was found in the park
that afternoon, and the evidence of the brutal crime horried the
ocials at the scene.
Because of the notoriety of the crime, the police were understandably
eager to nd Dawn’s killer and ease the community’s fear. When the
police department found the two little boys who had seen the suspect,
the ocers drafted a composite sketch of the man they were looking for.
1 Kirk Noble Bloodsworth, victim of wrongful conviction.
The witnesses described the suspect as 6 feet 5 inches tall, with a slim
build and dirty blond hair.
At the time of the investigation, I was 6 feet tall, with a thick waist,
ery red hair and long, noticeable sideburns.
Despite the fact that I did not t the description, an anonymous
caller suggested my name to the Cambridge Police Department. In
a poorly conducted police line-up, I was identied as the last man to
be seen with the victim.
Eyewitness misidentication is widely recognized as a leading cause
of wrongful convictions in the United States. Since 1989, DNA evi-
dence has been used to exonerate over 200 individuals, and about 75
per cent of these cases involved inaccurate eyewitness identication.
Other faulty police procedures played a role in my wrongful conviction.
I went to the police station voluntarily. Knowing that I was inno-
cent of this crime, I wanted to be as cooperative as possible. When I
entered the interview room, a pair of girl’s panties and a rock were
lying on the table. I was never told why. I later found out that the
items were part of an experiment that the police devised because they
believed that the killer would have a strong reaction to these items
related to the crime. I had no reaction. But after I left the station, I
talked to my friends about what the police had done. During the
trial, the police used these statements against me, claiming that I knew
something that only the killer would know. I only knew because they
had shown the items to me that day.
There was no physical evidence against me. I was convicted primar-
ily on the testimony of ve eyewitnesses who were later shown to
be terribly mistaken. With all the fear and anger in the community
surrounding Dawn’s murder, it took the jury less than three hours to
convict. I was sentenced to die in Maryland’s gas chamber. When my
death sentence was announced, the courtroom erupted in applause.
I, an innocent man, was sent to one of the worst prisons in the United
States at the time, the Maryland State Penitentiary. There was not a
26 27
day that passed that I didn’t try to tell someone I was innocent of
this crime. But, as a guard at the penitentiary told me during my rst
week, “Everyone in the pen is innocent, man, don’t you know?” No
one believed me.
Life at the Maryland State Penitentiary can only be described as hell on
Earth. I still have nightmares about it. Imagine living in a cell where you
can only take three steps from the back wall to the front door. I could
touch the side walls with my outstretched arms. My cell was directly
under the gas chamber where I was sentenced to die at the hands of the
state. The guards thought it was funny to remind me of that fact. They
would describe the entire procedure in detail and laugh at my fate.
Fortunately, I only had to spend two years dreading this death. A
second trial reduced my punishment to back-to-back life sentences.
I spent many of my
years in the peniten-
tiary in the infamous
South Wing, where
men were driven mad
by the prison brawls, lth, and other horric experiences. Prisoners
kept cotton balls in their ears at night so cockroaches wouldn’t lay
eggs in their heads. Prisoners would scream all through the night. The
conditions proved even worse for me, as I was jeered by the other
prisoners as a child rapist and killer. I had to lift weights every day
and adopt a rough demeanour in order to fend o constant threats.
While I fought to stay safe at the penitentiary, I spent most of my time
ghting to prove my innocence to anyone who would listen. I signed
every letter I sent “Kirk Bloodsworth A.I.M., An Innocent Man.
While writing countless letters to advocates, I resolved to advocate
for myself through my own research. I spent long days in the prison
library, reading every book I could get my hands on. The key to my
freedom came in the form of a book titled The Blooding by Joseph
Wambaugh. This book chronicled the rst time a process called DNA
testing was used to solve a series of homicides in England. I had an
epiphany right there: “If it can convict you, it can free you.
At the time of my rst trial, DNA testing was not a well-understood
concept in criminal law. But when I came across this book in 1992,
DNA testing in criminal cases was breaking ground. My attorney, Bob
Morin, submitted a request for the evidence in my case to be tested
in a lab. The prosecutor in the case almost brought my innocence
claim to a halt when she sent a letter with a devastating message: The
biological material in my case had been inadvertently destroyed.
But by the grace of God, the judge from my second trial had decided
to store some of the physical evidence in his chambers. I cannot say
for sure why he decided to do that, but I have a hunch that he knew
there was more truth to be told.
One day in 1993, the truth came out. I received a phone call from
my typically mild-mannered attorney. He couldn’t contain his excite-
ment. The sperm stain lifted from the victim’s underpants did not
match my DNA. The DNA told the truth; I was not guilty of this
crime. The appeals process in capital cases can be complicated and
hard to manoeuvre. I was fortunate to have supportive family, advo-
cates and an attorney who believed in my innocence.
Had evidence for DNA testing not been available, I would still be
in prison today. In the vast majority of criminal cases in the United
States, DNA or other biological evidence is not available—like in the
cases of Troy Davis and Carlos DeLuna, who were executed despite
grave doubts about their guilt. It is dicult to overturn wrongful
convictions without evidence to test. Unfortunately, it is more than
likely that there are people sitting on death row right now who are
in this tragic bind.
It is hard to know just how I sustained hope through this ordeal.
One story in particular comes to mind. Three months before the
results came back that would prove my innocence, I lost my mother.
She died of a heart attack on January 20, 1993. I was escorted to
the funeral home in shackles and handcus and was only given ve
minutes with my mother. This was the woman who had taught me
that if I don’t stand up for something, I would fall for anything.
She always believed in my innocence, but she didn’t live to see
me vindicated.
“IF WE KILL ONE INNOCENT
MAN, IT’S ONE TOO MANY.
Kirk Noble Bloodsworth
28 29
Finally, on June 28, 1993, I walked out of the Maryland State Peni-
tentiary a free man.
Even today, many exonerees nd it hard to shake the stigma after
they are released from prison. At the time of my DNA exoneration,
the technology was still new and the public wasn’t sure if I could
be trusted. When I returned to Cambridge, Maryland, I had trouble
getting a job and I was harassed by my neighbours.
It didn’t help that the prosecutor, Ann Brobst, would not admit the
state’s mistake. Even when I was released based on clear scientic
evidence, Brodst stated, “If we had the DNA evidence in 1984, Mr.
Bloodsworth would not have been prosecuted, but we are not pre-
pared to say he is innocent.
Unfortunately, it would take 10 years for Dawn’s true killer to be iden-
tied. I received a phone call from Brobst in September 2003 when
the state of Maryland nally found a match in the DNA database.
The murderer was identied as Kimberley Shay Runer. Not only
was his name given in a tip at the time of the original investigation,
but Runer was a suspect in rapes in the Fells Point neighbourhood
of Baltimore. He was serving time for attempted rape when the DNA
match was concluded years later.
As fate would have it, Runer had been sleeping in the cell below
me in the Maryland Penitentiary all these years. We had lifted weights
together. I gave him library books. He never said a word in all that time.
When I was exonerated, the state of Maryland paid me $300,000 for
lost income during the time I was wrongfully imprisoned. But I lost
so much more than money in those eight years that I will never get
back. While I grieve this loss, I am no longer angry, and for the past
decade of my life, I have simply wanted to do something to ensure
that no-one else suers what I did. After all, if it can happen to me, it
can happen to anyone.
This principle guides my work today. During my years of freedom, I
have fought for wrongfully convicted people all over the United States
and lobbied for reforms to the American criminal justice system, such
as the Innocence Protection Act of 2003, which includes the Kirk
Bloodsworth Post-Conviction DNA Testing program, providing fed-
eral funds to states for DNA testing for prisoners who claim their
innocence. I have become one of many exonerees who, with the
help of great advocacy organizations like Witness to Innocence, travel
around the country to share our cautionary tales.
When I tell young students my story, they always say the same thing:
I can’t believe this could happen in America.
While people are concerned by the rate of wrongful conviction in
the United States, sometimes it takes a personal story to put a real face
to the issue. Now, I respectfully submit my story to you. This story is
why I believe that the time is overdue for the United States to follow
the lead of our partners in the international community and abolish
the death penalty once and for all.
Make no mistake about it. I am not here because the system worked. I
am here because a series of miracles led to my exoneration. Not every
person wrongfully convicted of a capital crime is as blessed. If we kill
one innocent man, it’s one too many.
I certainly understand the anger and desire for justice in capital cases.
When I speak at death penalty events, I sometimes carry with me the
picture of the victim Dawn Hamilton. Her death was so horric that
it still moves me to tears. But the great US Supreme Court Justice
Thurgood Marshall one said, “The measure of a country’s greatness
is its ability to retain compassion in time of crisis. Even in the midst
of fear and anger, a great country must ensure that its criminal justice
system is eective and accurate. If a great country cannot ensure that
it won’t kill an innocent citizen, it shouldn’t kill at all.
For these reasons, I strongly believe that abolishing the death penalty
is a necessary step for the integrity of the criminal justice system in
the United States and other nations.
30 31
DNA EVIDENCE CASTS LIGHT
ON FLAWS IN SYSTEM
Brandon L. Garrett
1
In no country other than the United States has there been such a large
group of people whose innocence has been clearly proven by DNA
tests years after their conviction. This group of innocent people, called
DNA exonerees, provides a unique opportunity to learn about what
can go wrong in even the most serious criminal cases. Exoneration is
an ocial decision to reverse a conviction based on new evidence of
innocence. The most haunting feature of many wrongful convictions
is that they can come to light by sheer fortuity. We may never know
how many other innocent people have been convicted and punished,
even for serious crimes like murder.
Accuracy may be of particular concern for very serious but di-
cult-to-solve crimes like murder, in which the death penalty may
be charged. If the culprit is not caught in the act, police may need
to rely on eyewitnesses, forensics or confessions—evidence that they
can get wrong, due to missteps and unsound practices early in crim-
inal investigations. Once key evidence is contaminated during an
investigation, it may be very dicult for subsequent trial, appeals,
and post-conviction courts to detect, much less correct, the errors.
What I found disturbing when reading a large set of criminal trials
of DNA exonerees is that a case against an innocent person may not
seem weak at the time; it may seem uncannily strong. Where very
few cases can be tested using DNA, it is crucial to prevent wrongful
convictions before it is too late.
Over 140 death row inmates have been exonerated since the 1970s
in the United States.
2
I focused on a small group of those cases when
1 Brandon L. Garrett is a professor ar the University of Virginia School of Law.
2 As of this writing, the Death Penalty Information Center had a count of 144 death-row
inmates who have been exonerated <www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/innocence-list-those-freed-
death-row>. A 2008 study modelled a false conviction rate by examining exonerations in cap-
ital cases in published work and in a work in progress. Samuel R. Gross and Barbara O’Brien,
“Frequency and predictors of false conviction: Why we know so little, and new data on capital
cases”,
Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, vol. 5 (2008), pp. 927 .
I examined what happened in the rst 250 DNA exonerations in
my 2011 book Convicting the Innocent: Where Criminal Prosecutions Go
Wrong.
3
There have now been more than 300 such exonerations in
the United States. Of the rst 300 cases, 192 were convicted of rape,
68 of rape and murder, 32 of murder, and 8 of other crimes; 18 had
been sentenced to death.
4
Of those 18, 16 had been convicted of rape and murder and 2 of
murder alone. The evidence in those cases relied heavily on confessions,
which we now know to have been false, and a range of awed forensic
evidence. Eight involved detailed false confessions allegedly including
inside information that only the murderer could have known. With the
benet of DNA tests, we now know those people were innocent, but
they may have seemed quite guilty at the time. Absent a complete video
recording of the interrogations, jurors readily believed law enforcement
ocials’ accounts of the confessions. Three of these confessions were
made by mentally disabled people who could be expected to have been
highly vulnerable to police coercion and suggestion.
5
Ten of the cases involved testimony by informants, including seven
jailhouse informants, three witnesses who testied in cooperation
with prosecutors, and two codefendants who alleged they were
accomplices but who were also innocent and themselves wrongly
convicted. These informants also claimed to have overheard, in jail
or elsewhere, details that only the killer could have known. Perhaps
the most chilling of those cases is that of Ron Williamson and Dennis
Fritz, in which the witness testifying for the state at trial, and describ-
ing the victim having a last dance with Williamson, was later shown
by DNA testing to himself have been the killer.
Eight cases involved identications by eyewitnesses, sometimes mul-
tiple eyewitnesses, who were all mistaken about what they had seen.
3 Data from that research are available online at <www.law.virginia.edu/html/librarysite/garrett_
innocent.htm>. A multimedia online resource about these data and ways to prevent wrongful
convictions is available at <www.innocenceproject.org/Content/Getting_it_Right.php>.
4 My book examined 17 such DNA exonerations in capital cases; in 2012, Damon Thibodeaux
became the 300th DNA exoneree and the 18th death row DNA exoneree in the United States.
Douglas A. Blackmon, “Louisiana death-row inmate Damon Thibodeaux exonerated with
DNA evidence”,
Washington Post, 28 September 2012.
5 The US Supreme Court noted the existence of one such case, that of Earl Washington Jr., in its
decision in
Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 320 n. 5 (2002).
32 33
Fourteen cases involved forensic evidence, including a number with
unreliable and unvalidated forensics. Ten of the cases involved hair
comparisons, two involved bre comparisons and nine involved
blood typing. Two involved bite mark comparisons; perhaps most
well known is the case of Ray Krone, who was convicted based on
little other than a awed bite-mark comparison.
The death penalty cases were not so dierent from many other DNA
exoneree cases that similarly involved murders, and in which false
confessions and informant testimony and awed forensic evidence
played a central role. Of the rst 250 DNA exonerees, 40 had falsely
confessed. I examined each of those cases in detail and found that in
all but two cases, the innocent person was said to have confessed in
detail. Those false confessions were all seemingly powerful because
they were contaminated. While many of the interrogations were
partially recorded, none was recorded in its entirety. The confessions
were concentrated in the murder cases. Of the 40 false confessions
that I studied, 25 involved rape and murder, 3 murder only, and 12
rape only.
EXONERATION: AN UPHILL BATTLE
Once evidence is contaminated early in a criminal investigation,
post-trial procedures—like appeals and the post-appeal habeas corpus
remedies that we have in the United States—may not be of much
help. It is a myth that appellate judges will correct factual errors: An
appellate court “knows no more than the jury and the trial judge” and
has a more limited role, partially because the appellate judge is “obliged
to accept the jury’s verdict” and focuses on more limited questions of
law rather than the reliability of facts.
6
An appellate judge, who was
not present at the original trial, is highly reluctant to second-guess the
jury’s decision to convict. No more than 1 or 2 per cent of cases are
ever reversed. Of course, the vast majority of criminal cases involve plea
bargains, in which the right to an appeal or post-conviction review is
usually waived. Even when an appeal can be brought, rules setting strict
time limits have traditionally prevented a convict from raising new evi-
dence of innocence (although some of those rules have been relaxed,
6 Jerome Frank and Barbara Frank, Not Guilty (Garden City, NY, Doubleday, 1957).
particularly by state statutes that permit post-conviction DNA testing),
and claims of innocence remain very dicult to make.
Once the appeal is over, an indigent inmate lacks the constitutional right
to a state-provided attorney. Every jurisdiction in the United States oers
some type of review after the appeal is complete, usually called post-con-
viction or habeas review. This additional level of review may permit, in
theory, litigation of claims that could not have been raised during the
initial appeal. However, non-death-row inmates typically do not have
lawyers to help them navigate the incredibly complex procedural barri-
ers that limit the chances of success during such reviews.
The death-row DNA exonerees typically followed a long road from
trial to exoneration. Four of them had two trials; two had three trials.
Each time they were convicted again, until they nally obtained DNA
testing and were exonerated. The picture was not much dierent for the
full group of DNA exonerees, including those who were not sentenced
to death, except that among the non-death-row prisoners, even fewer
received any relief prior to obtaining DNA testing. Non-death-row
exonerees often did not obtain lawyers after their appeal and could not
get any help ling habeas petitions. They rarely challenged the faulty
evidence that caused their wrongful convictions, and when they did try,
they failed. The gure that follows illustrates the degree to which the
rst 250 DNA exonerees (those who had judges write decisions in their
cases) tried to challenge the evidence presented at their trials during
appeal or post-conviction review, and how few obtained conviction
reversals before they were successfully exonerated using DNA testing.
Post-conviction challenges to evidence by the
first 250 DNA exonerees
We now know that these people were innocent, but they did not have
any luck raising claims of innocence either: Every DNA exoneree who
tried to raise such a claim failed. These appeals and post-conviction
challenges took time; the road to exoneration took an average of 15
years. Of the 18 death-row DNA exonerees, 8 earned reversals on
appeal or post-conviction. This high reversal rate is consistent with
other studies of post-conviction litigation by death row inmates,
although these cases were mostly litigated before the passage of the
34 35
Antiterrorism and Eective Death Penalty Act, which now restricts
the availability of federal habeas review.
7
What is still more troubling, though, is that others were convicted
again at multiple trials, until ultimately DNA evidence set them free.
Rolando Cruz and Alejandro Hernandez each had two convictions
reversed and three criminal trials before they were exonerated. Kirk
Bloodsworth, Ray Krone, Curtis McCarty and Dennis Williams each
had two trials before they were exonerated by post-conviction DNA
testing. Innocent people can be wrongly convicted not only once but
several times, including in capital cases.
Bloodsworth was the rst person exonerated from death row in the
United States based on post-conviction DNA testing. He had been
sentenced to death for the Maryland rape and murder of a 9-year-old
girl in 1984. Five eyewitnesses had incorrectly placed him near the
crime scene. Maryland recently abolished the death penalty, in part in
response to Bloodsworth’s case.
Compare that case to the nationally and internationally well-known
Troy Davis case, a death penalty case that similarly involved a group
of eyewitnesses who had each identied Davis following eyewitness
identication procedures. Although the US Supreme Court, in a rare
move, granted a habeas petition led directly with the Court and
asked a judge to look into the new evidence of Davis’s innocence, the
Georgia Board of Pardons denied clemency, and Davis was executed
in September 2011. We will never know for sure if he was inno-
cent—there was no DNA evidence to test, or any other real forensic
evidence in the case.
8
Other prisoners have fared better, but not to the point of full exon-
eration: They have pled guilty in exchange for having their sentence
7 For a discussion of the reversal rate in capital DNA exonerations, see Brandon L. Garrett,
“Judging innocence”, Columbia Law Review, vol. 108 (2008), pp. 55 ., 99-100 (reporting a
58 per cent reversal rate, or 7 out of 12 capital DNA exonerees with written decisions). Since
that article was written, of the four additional capital DNA exonerees, Curtis McCarty received
reversals, Kennedy Brewer did not, and Michael Blair and Damon Thibodeaux did not have
reported decisions.
8 Brandon L. Garrett, “Eyes on an execution”,
Slate, September 20, 2011. For an example of an
execution that received very little attention at the time, but regarding which grave doubts have
since been raised, see James Liebman and others, “The Wrong Carlos: Anatomy of a Wrongful
Execution” (Columbia U. Press: New York, NY 2014).
reduced to time served or have received partial clemency after errors
came to light in their cases. This has occurred in high-prole cases
like those of the West Memphis Three in Arkansas, the Norfolk
Four in Virginia and Edward Lee Elmore in South Carolina.
9
There
are many more exonerations that do not involve DNA testing; very
few death penalty cases—or murder cases generally—have testable
DNA evidence.
DEBATE AND REFORM
Exonerations in capital cases have had a broad impact on the public
and policymakers and have contributed to a “new death penalty
debate.
10
Revelations that innocent people were sent to death row
have permanently altered the debate, regardless of whether one
believes that the death penalty is justied in some circumstances.
For example, in Baze v. Rees, US Supreme Court Justice Stevens
announced his opposition to the death penalty, citing evidence from
DNA exonerations:
Given the real risk of error in this class of cases, the irrevo-
cable nature of the consequences is of decisive importance to
me. Whether or not any innocent defendants have actually
been executed, abundant evidence accumulated in recent
years has resulted in the exoneration of an unacceptable
number of defendants found guilty of capital oenses.
11
Justice John Paul Stevens, writing for the US Supreme Court in
Atkins v. Virginia, noted that “a disturbing number of inmates on
death row have been exonerated.
12
In contrast, Justice Antonin
Scalia has argued that known exonerations represent an “insignicant
9 See “Kaine’s full statement on ‘Norfolk Four’ case”, Washington Post, 6 August 2009, available
from http://voices.washingtonpost.com/virginiapolitics/2009/08/kaines_full_statement_on_
norfo.html?sidST2009080602217; Tom Wells and Richard A. Leo,
The Wrong Guys: Murder,
False Confessions, and the Norfolk Four (New York, W. W. Norton, 2008); Raymond Bonner,
Anatomy of Injustice: A Murder Case Gone Wrong (New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 2012).
10 James Liebman, “The new death penalty debate”, Columbia Human Rights Law Review, vol.
33 (2002), pp. 527 .; Colin Starger, “Death and harmless error: A rhetorical response to judg-
ing innocence”, Columbia Law Review Sidebar, vol. 108 (February 2008), pp. 1 .
11
Baze v. Rees, 553 U.S. 35, 85-86 (2008) (Stevens, J. dissenting).
12
Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 320 n.25 (2002).
36 37
minimum.
13
Federal district judge Jed Rako struck down the federal
death penalty, arguing: “We now know, in a way almost unthinkable
even a decade ago, that our system of criminal justice, for all its pro-
tections, is suciently fallible that innocent people are convicted of
capital crimes with some frequency. His ruling was later reversed
by the Second Circuit Court of Appeals.
14
Statewide moratoriums
and abolition of the death penalty have occurred in part citing the
examples of death row exonerations; the best known was the Illinois
moratorium and Commission on Capital Punishment, for which
there was intensive study of the cases of 13 men exonerated from
the Illinois death row.
15
Hearing from a death row exoneree how a
wrongful execution nearly happened can have a powerful eect on
legislators and the public. As noted, the death penalty was abolished
in Maryland; death row survivor Kirk Bloodsworth had lobbied for
the repeal in Maryland and has done so across the country. The direc-
tor of Maryland Citizens Against State Executions commented, “No
single individual has changed as many minds as Kirk.
16
Looking far beyond death penalty cases, DNA testing suggests addi-
tional questions about the more mundane criminal cases. A federal
inquiry conducted in the mid-1990s, when police rst began to send
samples for DNA testing, found that 25percent of these prime sus-
pects were cleared by DNA before a trial was held.
17
Where the vast
majority of criminal cases lack any DNA evidence to test, still more
questions are raised concerning accuracy.
13 Kansas v. Marsh, 548 U.S. 163, 194-195 (2006) (Scalia, J. concurring). For a discussion, see
Samuel R. Gross, “Souter passant, Scalia rampant: Combat in the marsh”, Michigan Law Review
First Impressions, vol. 105 (2006), pp. 67 .
14
U.S. v. Quinones, 196 F.Supp.2d 416, 420 (S.D.N.Y. 2002) rev’d U.S. v. Quinones, 313 F.3d 49
(2nd Cir. 2002).
15 Governor’s Commission on Capital Punishment,
Report of the Governor’s Commission on Capi-
tal Punishment (Springeld, Illinois, 2002), p. 4.
16 Scott Shane, “A death penalty ght comes home”,
New York Times, 5 February 2013.
17 Edward Connors and others,
Convicted by Juries, Exonerated by Science: Case Studies in the Use
of DNA Evidence to Establish Innocence after Trial (Washington, DC, US Department of Justice,
1996), pp. xxviii-xxix, 20.
“OVER 140 DEATH ROW INMATES HAVE
BEEN EXONERATED SINCE THE 1970S IN
THE UNITED STATES”
Brandon L. Garrett
More states and local police departments are now recording interro-
gations and have adopted best practices for eyewitness lineups. A few
have also improved quality control and standards for forensics. Those
reforms are inexpensive, and they benet law enforcement; they help
to identify the guilty and clear the innocent. However, they are all
being implemented at the local and state levels.
Additional reforms could improve the quality of post-convic-
tion review. One state, North Carolina, has created an Innocence
Inquiry Commission, to focus on judicial review of claims of inno-
cence. Unlike post-conviction and habeas courts, which are sharply
restricted by complex procedural barriers to relief, this Commission
just investigates whether a person is innocent and should be exoner-
ated by a three-judge panel. Other courts have made improvements
on the front end by insisting that juries be carefully informed of the
limitations of evidence, such as eyewitness testimony. Much more can
be done, however, both to improve judicial gatekeeping to prevent
wrongful convictions in the rst place and to review convictions after
the fact.
CONCLUSION
In the United States, because some jurisdictions happened to save
crime scene evidence that could be tested years later, there has been
No challenge Verdict reversed Challenge unsuccessful
Eyewitness testimony
56% challenged
Forensic testimony
31% challenged
Informant testimony
34% challenged
Confessions
59% challenged
120
100
80
60
40
20
0
38 39
a remarkable series of DNA exonerations, including in death penalty
cases. Jurisdictions in the United States are slowly learning from these
cases, and some have adopted reforms to prevent future wrongful
convictions. Jurisdictions outside the United States should similarly
take note. Eyewitness memory, confessions, informants and traditional
forensic comparisons are not very dierent around the world. The
same causes and practices may result in the same types of errors.
Much more remains to be done to prevent wrongful convictions, in
capital cases as well as other types of criminal cases. Getting it right
will take a sustained commitment.
IN THE UNITED STATES,
GROWING DOUBTS ABOUT
THE DEATH PENALTY
Gil Garcetti
1
The death penalty in the United States is applied through the state
systems of justice and, on far fewer occasions, through the federal
system. Under current federal law, each state has the authority to
impose a death penalty for murders involving actions or situations
that are usually referred to as “special circumstances. Likewise, any
state is free to ban the death penalty. As of this writing, 18 states have
banned it, and three more—Washington, Oregon and Colorado—
have recently imposed moratoriums. One could also convincingly
argue that the nation’s largest state, California, eectively has a mora-
torium, given that the last execution there was in 2006.
In the 29 states that do impose the death penalty, the decision on
whether to seek it is made by the county prosecutor (each state is
divided into counties). California has 57 counties, and each has an
elected prosecutor with the title of district attorney. Each of these
district attorneys has dierent criteria for deciding whether to seek
the death penalty in death-penalty-eligible cases. In Los Angeles,
the death penalty is sought in less than 15 per cent of all eligible
cases. In other California counties, this ratio is reversed. Without
doubt there are cases for which, if they were tried in two counties
in California, one county would seek the death penalty and the
other would not.
Los Angeles County, where I have the greatest experience and famil-
iarity, is the largest county in California and by population larger
than 43 states. Because of its size, courthouses are spread throughout
the county. Though the death-penalty decision-making process is
centralized, whether a jury returns a verdict of death depends to a
great extent on where in the county the case is tried. This has always
troubled me. Why should one defendant benet or suer simply
1 Gil Garcetti was Los Angeles County District Attorney from 1992 to 2000.
40 41
because he or she is tried in an area of the county that is less likely or
more likely to return a verdict of death? This concern holds for the
entire state: Why should defendants benet or suer simply because
of their county’s policy regarding the death penalty or the propensity
of jurors in the county to favour or oppose it?
I spent 32 years in the Los Angeles County District Attorney’s oce,
including eight years as the elected District Attorney and four in
the second-highest position, Chief Deputy District Attorney. In those
capacities I oversaw the nal decision-making process regarding the
death penalty. In my eight years as District Attorney, I supported and
implemented California’s death penalty law. I left oce at the end
of 2000. About 10 years later, I reversed my position on the death
penalty. I became convinced that it serves no useful criminal justice
or societal purpose, including as a deterrent to murder; that given
the number of recently exonerated death row inmates throughout
the United States, there were undoubtedly people on California’s
death row who should not be there; that the obscene amount of
taxpayers’ money used to support the death penalty would be much
more eectively used to keep teachers, school counsellors, and law
enforcement personnel on the job; and that the current system, under
which death-penalty cases often last for decades, was not fair to the
families and loved ones of murder victims.
In 2011 I made my views public. My ultimate goal is to see the death
penalty repealed, in California as well as the entire United States, and
replaced with life in prison without the possibility of parole. Each
state has a slightly dierent means of achieving this goal. Some, like
California and Oregon, require a voter initiative,
2
while others may
repeal through the state legislature. No matter the method, repeal
is a dicult task, because the death penalty in the United States is
a highly emotional issue, deeply political, and misunderstood by a
majority of Americans.
2 In a voter initiative, proponents of a measure circulate a petition which, if it garners enough
signatures, enables the measure to be placed on a ballot in the next election, to be voted on
directly by citizens. California and 17 other states provide for state laws to be passed in this way.
THE CALIFORNIA MORATORIUM
The hard facts behind the death penalty process have begun to come
to light in the United States, giving some of our political leaders,
including vocal supporters of the death penalty, a reason to pause
and think critically about the system. Many have publicly supported
a moratorium in order to allow time for a meaningful conversation
on the issue. California has since 2006 had a de facto moratorium
on executions due to ongoing legal challenges to the state’s lethal
injection protocol. This has created an environment that has allowed
us to move closer to achieving our goal of replacing the death penalty
with life in prison without the possibility of parole.
California’s de facto moratorium, as well as the moratoriums imposed
by the governors of the states of Oregon, Washington and Colorado,
have undoubtedly created an environment in which full repeal is
more plausible. The positive eect of moratoriums can be seen most
clearly in New Jersey, where a moratorium on executions was put in
place in 2004 due to the lack of a proper lethal injection procedure.
In the following years, questions about the eectiveness of the death
penalty as a deterrent, cost feasibility, and, critically, the risk of sen-
tencing innocents to death led New Jersey to repeal its death penalty
in 2007. The de facto moratorium in California has similarly created
an environment of scrutiny.
To fully understand the de facto moratorium in California, it is help-
ful to go back a few decades. After several years without a death
penalty, California voters reinstated it in 1978 in an initiative process.
Not many years after reinstatement, both supporters and opponents
of the death penalty became very unhappy with the how it was
being administered. In 2004, the California State Senate established
the California Commission on the Fair Administration of Justice,
a bipartisan blue-ribbon panel tasked with speeding up the death
penalty process, investigating the causes of wrongful convictions and
executions in the state, and recommending reforms. The resulting
report made substantive recommendations for change. Even though
highly respected individuals on both sides of the argument urged
the legislature to adopt major changes in the administration of the
death penalty, no meaningful change was adopted by the legislature.
42 43
In good part because of this failure to act, the then chief justice of
the California Supreme Court and other death penalty supporters
declared that there would never be the political will to change the
death penalty law and that the system was broken and unxable.
In 2005, in the court case Morales v. Cullen, a death row inmate chal-
lenged California’s lethal injection procedure in federal court as cruel
and unusual punishment prohibited by the Eighth Amendment to
the US Constitution. Governor Arnold Schwarzenegger responded
by agreeing to overhaul the state’s lethal injection procedure. In 2006,
in Pacic News Service v. Cullen, an inmate challenged the use of a
paralytic drug during lethal injection, arguing that it violates the First
Amendment rights of the press and the public by preventing witnesses
from seeing what actually occurs during an execution. As a result of
these legal cases, and because of a national shortage of lethal injection
drugs, all of California’s scheduled executions have been placed on
indenite hold. The last execution in California occurred in 2006.
In 2007, a state court ordered the California Department of Cor-
rections and Rehabilitation (CDCR), the agency legally responsible
for carrying out executions, to adopt a new lethal injection protocol
while allowing for public comment and participation. A challenge to
the CDCR’s new protocol was advanced in 2010 based on state law
in Sims v. California Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation. In that
case, the plainti alleged that the CDCR violated the Administrative
Procedures Act in both the process of adopting the new regulations
and their substance. In May 2013, the plainti won the case, and the
court found the state’s lethal injection protocol was invalid. Since
then, California has had no lethal injection protocol. If and when the
state issues a new protocol, it must follow the strict guidelines of the
Administrative Procedures Act and start the process of approval over
again. More legal challenges to any new protocol are a certainty.
In addition to the legal challenges, the CDCR’s supply of sodium
thiopental, the lethal injection drug required under the regulations,
has expired. The drug is no longer legally available in the United
States and may not be imported under federal law. Thus, there is no
legal source of the drug. Pentobarbital, another lethal injection drug
used by some states, is also in short supply as the European manufac-
turer has cut o sales to US prisons.
REPLACING THE DEATH PENALTY WITH
LIFE IN PRISON
In California, replacing the death penalty with life in prison with-
out the possibility of parole can only be accomplished through a
ballot initiative, since that is how the death penalty law was enacted.
In 1978, 70 percent of California voters passed the Briggs initiative,
establishing the death penalty and specifying the criteria for eligi-
bility. Given the current status of the death penalty in California
and the general movement away from it across the nation, the goal
of bringing a repeal initiative to the voters, while it may be viewed
by some as audacious, is, at least in California, within reach.
California sentences more people to death than any other state. As
of this writing, it has nearly 750 prisoners on death row. California
led the country with 24 death sentences in 2013, 13 of them coming
from just two southern counties. While more than 800 people have
been sentenced to death in California since 1978, only 13 executions
have been performed. Of the people sentenced to death in California
in the last 30 years, only 1 percent have been executed. Most death
row inmates die of natural causes.
On a national level, the United States continues to move further away
from the death penalty. Death sentences and executions are down in
most states, and reported public support for the death penalty has
declined signicantly since the mid-1980s. California is not immune
from this trend. An April 2011 poll by David Binder Research found
that 63 per cent of California voters, across all parties and counties,
support the governor converting all current death sentences to life in
prison without possibility of parole. More Californians are realizing
that the death penalty does not achieve swift and certain justice for
“SOMEONE WHO’S VICTIM IS WHITE IS THREE
TIMES MORE LIKELY TO BE SENTENCED
TO DEATH THAN SOMEONE WHOSE VICTIM
IS AFRICAN AMERICAN.
Gil Garcetti
44 45
victims’ families, it is imposed discriminately at a huge cost to the
state, and, most importantly, it risks executing innocent people.
The complicated and often decades-long appeals process that death
row inmates are constitutionally entitled to in California and other
states does not achieve swift justice for victims’ families. Most appeals
provide many opportunities for reversal and do not give families any
kind of closure. Furthermore, the lengthy appeals process and spe-
cial incarceration of death row inmates comes at a huge cost to the
state. The death penalty costs 10 times as much as life in prison. If
California replaced the death penalty with life in prison without the
possibility of parole, the state would save $1 billion in just ve years.
In the midst of a severe ongoing budget crisis, a legitimate question
is whether we should be investing taxpayer money in a broken death
penalty that serves no worthy criminal-justice or societal purpose—
or in education, mental health and law enforcement.
The death penalty in the United States has also been shown to fall
disproportionately on people of colour and people of limited means.
For example, data from 2011 show that someone whose victim is
white is three times more likely to be sentenced to death than some-
one whose victim is African American, and four times more likely
than someone whose victim is Latino. While only 27.6 per cent of
murder victims are white, 80 per cent of prisoners executed in Cali-
fornia have been convicted of killing whites. The location at which a
murder occurs also aects the likelihood of the oender receiving the
death penalty. In California, someone convicted in Alameda County,
for example, is eight times more likely to be sentenced to death than
someone convicted in Santa Clara County. As discussed earlier, even
within the single (though large and diverse) County of Los Angeles,
the death penalty is applied unequally in dierent locations. These
stark disparities are evidence that the death penalty is being imposed
discriminately, a reality that undermines a basic goal of our criminal
justice system—fair and equal treatment under the law.
Finally, the death penalty comes with the unacceptable and ever-pres-
ent risk of executing innocents. Between 1973 and 2011, 138 people
were exonerated and released from death rows across the United
States. Nationally, one person is exonerated for every 10 that are
executed. The factors that commonly lead to wrongful convictions
are rampant and varied: eyewitness error, false confessions, false testi-
mony by an informant, prosecutorial misconduct and poor forensic
evidence. The risk of wrongful conviction and execution can never
be removed from a death penalty system.
In November 2012, California voters had the opportunity to replace
the death penalty with life in prison without the possibility of parole
through a voter initiative known as Proposition 34. While that prop-
osition lost, the trend in public opinion had clearly changed. In 1978,
Californians had voted overwhelmingly (70 per cent to 30 per cent)
to reinstate the death penalty. But in 2012, 48 per cent of Californians
voted in favour of repeal while 52 per cent voted against it (5,974,000
to 6,460,000). If about 250,000 voters had had been convinced to
change their votes, there would be no death penalty in California
today. The initiative failed in good part because the campaign did not
reach enough voters with information. The reality of the Califor-
nia political system is that winning a ballot initiative, especially on a
controversial issue like the death penalty, requires millions of dollars
for voter education; unfortunately, the repeal campaign did not have
sucient resources.
Since Prop 34’s defeat in 2012, California’s death penalty repeal advo-
cates are continuing to educate the public about the high costs of the
death penalty; reshaping the California Coalition behind Proposition
34 into an ongoing advocacy campaign to promote public safety pol-
icies that reect our shared values of safety, accountability, fairness and
equality; and strengthening alliances with law enforcement, victims
and labour as well as traditional supporters in the faith and civil rights
communities. The ultimate goal, replacing the death penalty with life
in prison without the possibility of parole, will best serve our prior-
ities: to protect law-abiding citizens and punish those who commit
society’s most heinous crimes.
FEDERAL DEATH PENALTY CASES
The vast majority of death penalty cases are handled in the state
courts. According to the Federal Death Penalty Resource Project,
federal prosecutors tried 190 death penalty cases, involving 281
46 47
defendants, between 1988 and 2013. As of this writing there have
been three federal executions; 54 federal court defendants have been
sentenced to death and their appeals or writs are pending.
The movement of states toward repeal is both instructive and hopeful.
Imagine the impact worldwide when California, a state with a popu-
lation of over 37 million (greater than that of most countries), repeals
the death penalty and replaces it with life imprisonment without the
possibility of parole.
Or better yet, imagine the impact worldwide if the President of the
United States declared a moratorium on the death penalty. Is this out
of the question? Does the President have too many other pressing
issues on his agenda? Does his previously stated position on the death
penalty rule out the possibility that he would call for a moratorium
in federal cases? Consider what President Obama said in May 2014:
“In the application of the death penalty in this country, we have
seen signicant problems — racial bias, uneven application of the
death penalty, you know, situations in which there were individuals
on death row who later on were discovered to have been innocent
because of exculpatory evidence. And all these, I think, do raise sig-
nicant questions about how the death penalty is being applied.
3
That is our opening to seek a dialogue with the President about
declaring a moratorium on the death penalty while his administra-
tion studies and engages in dialogue with citizens on both sides of the
issue—a dialogue that we should be condent will lead not just to a
moratorium on the death penalty but to its replacement with life in
prison without the possibility of parole.
AFTERWORD: HISTORIC RULING
IN CALIFORNIA
On 17 July 2014, as the rst edition of this publication was being
produced, a historic federal district court decision was issued in the
case of Ernest Dewayne Jones v. Kevin Chappell, Warden of the California
3 Peter Baker, “Obama orders policy review on executions”, New York Times, 2 May 2014,
available from www.nytimes.com/2014/05/03/us/awed-oklahoma-execution-deeply-trou-
bling-obama-says.html?_r=0.
State Prison at San Quentin. Federal Judge Cormac Carney concluded
that California’s death penalty system is dysfunctional and results in
an “inordinate and unpredictable period of delay preceding their
actual execution. He went on to say that “as for the random few for
whom execution does become a reality, they will have languished for
so long on Death Row that their execution will serve no retributive
or deterrent purpose and will be arbitrary. ... Allowing this system
to continue to threaten Mr. Jones with the slight possibility of death,
almost a generation after he was rst sentenced, violates the Eighth
Amendment’s prohibition against cruel and unusual punishment.
Mr. Jones has been on California’s death row since April 1995.
The Jones decision can be appealed to the Federal Court of Appeals
by the California Attorney General. If the appeal is heard and the
decision of the district court is armed, the decision would then
apply to the entire state—California’s death penalty law would no
longer exist. The California Attorney General could either accept the
appeals court’s decision or appeal it to the United States Supreme
Court. The court of appeal obviously could also reverse the district
court’s decision. Mr. Jones would then be in the position of appealing
that decision to the United States Supreme Court.
This case is historic because it appears to be the rst time in the
nation that a federal court judge has concluded that a specic state’s
death penalty law is unconstitutional because of the state’s dysfunc-
tional death penalty system. While this decision applies to this single
case alone, judges and prosecutors in California can now expect
the same arguments to be made in any pending death penalty case.
Though judges are not required to follow a ruling by a single court,
this especially well-written, exhaustive and well-documented deci-
sion is likely to persuade many judges to follow its lead and declare
California’s state death penalty law unconstitutional.
48 49
WRONGFUL CONVICTIONS AND
MISCARRIAGES OF JUSTICE IN
DEATH PENALTY TRIALS IN THE
CARIBBEAN, AFRICA AND ASIA
Saul Lehrfreund
1
International attitudes to the death penalty have evolved with the
knowledge that every criminal justice system, however sophisti-
cated, is susceptible to error and miscarriage of justice.
2
International
human rights law, recognising that susceptibility, mandates that fair
trial guarantees must be implemented in all death penalty cases.
The understanding is that those facing the death penalty should be
aorded special protection and guarantees to ensure a fair trial above
and beyond those aorded in non-capital cases.
The reality is that the pre-
vailing law and practice in far
too many retentionist coun-
tries across the Caribbean,
Africa and Asia do not pro-
vide the level of protection
required in capital cases. Unless and until states can meet universally
accepted standards, the death penalty should not be enforced. Too many
countries retain the death penalty without assuming responsibility for
the proper administration of criminal justice; many states fail to provide
special procedural protections in capital cases.
UNIVERSAL STANDARDS APPLICABLE
TO CAPITAL CASES
The potential for wrongful conviction and execution is precisely why
international norms require such exacting standards and a heightened
1 Saul Lehrfreund, MBE, is co-executive director of The Death Penalty Project.
2 For a global snapshot of cases and research ndings on wrongful convictions, see The Death
Penalty Project,
The Inevitability of Error: The Administration of Justice in Death Penalty Cases
(London, 2014), available from www.deathpenaltyproject.org/news/1795/1795/.
“…THE RISK THAT
INNOCENT PEOPLE WILL BE
EXECUTED CAN NEVER BE
ELIMINATED…”
Saul Lehrfreund
level of due process in capital cases. The key question is: Are there sig-
nicant gaps between the minimum conditions required in all capital
cases and the law and practice in retentionist countries? If so, the only
option is that the death penalty should no longer be enforced.
Two key documents laying out international standards in this
regard are the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights
(ICCPR)
3
and the Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights
of Those Facing the Death Penalty.
4
International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights
Although Article 6(1) of the ICCPR establishes that capital punish-
ment is an exception to the right to life as long as it is not arbitrarily
imposed, Article 6 requires a number of safeguards in its implementa-
tion: It may only be imposed for the most serious crimes, it cannot be
pronounced unless rigorous procedural rules are followed, and it may
not be imposed on pregnant women or for crimes committed before
the age of 18. Article 6(2) of the ICCPR provides the following:
In countries which have not abolished the death penalty,
sentence of death may be imposed only for the most serious
crimes in accordance with the law in force at the time of the
commission of the oence and not contrary to the present
Covenant.... This penalty can only be carried out pur-
suant to a nal judgment rendered by a competent court.
Article 6(6) places the death penalty in its real context and assumes
its eventual elimination: “Nothing in this article shall be invoked to
delay or to prevent the abolition of capital punishment by any State
Party to the present Covenant.
Retention of the death penalty is permitted by international law
(albeit in extremely limited circumstances as discussed above), and
3 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, available from www.ohchr.org/EN/Profes-
sionalInterest/Pages/CCPR.aspx.
4
Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights of Those Facing the Death Penalty, available
from www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/DeathPenalty.aspx.
50 51
its use does not by itself constitute cruel, inhuman or unusual pun-
ishment or torture. However, it may become an arbitrary violation
of the right to life if it is imposed in circumstances that breach other
rights under the ICCPR—including the right to a fair trial and the
prohibition on torture, on which this paper will focus.
Article 14 of the ICCPR sets out the minimum requirements for a fair
trial, which must be respected in all capital cases. The United Nations
Human Rights Committee has consistently held that if Article 14 of the
ICCPR is violated during a capital trial, then Article 6 (right to life) is also
breached. In Carlton Reid v. Jamaica,
5
the Human Rights Committee held:
The imposition of a sentence of death upon the conclusion
of a trial in which the provisions of the Covenant have not
been respected constitutes ... a violation of Article 6 of the
Covenant. ... The provision that a sentence of death may
be imposed only in accordance with the law and not contrary
to the provisions of the present Covenant implies that “the
procedural guarantees therein prescribed must be observed,
including the right to a fair hearing by an independent tribu-
nal, the presumption of innocence, the minimum guarantees
for the defence, and the right to review by a higher tribunal.”
6
Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the
Rights of Those Facing the Death Penalty
The restrictions on capital punishment set out in Article 6 of the
ICCPR are reected and further developed in the Safeguards
Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights of Those Facing the Death
Penalty (hereinafter the Safeguards), which “constitute an enumer-
ation of minimum standards to be applied in countries that still
impose capital punishment.
7
5 Carlton Reid v. Jamaica, paragraph 11.5, Communication No. 250/1987, United Nations Doc.
CCPR/C/39/D/250/1987 (1987), United Nations Human Rights Committee.
6
Human Rights Committee, General Comment 6, Article 6 (Sixteenth session, 1982), Compilation of
General Comments and General Recommendations Adopted by Human Rights Treaty Bodies, U.N.
Doc. HRI/GEN/1/Rev.1 at 6 (1994), available from http://www1.umn.edu/humanrts/gen-
comm/hrcom6.htm.
7
Capital Punishment and Implementation of the Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights of
Those Facing the Death Penalty, Report of the Secretary-General, UN Doc. E/2010/10, p. 33.
The Safeguards were adopted in 1984 by United Nations Economic
and Social Council Resolution 1984/50. In 1989, they were further
developed by the Council, which recommended, among other things,
that there should be a maximum age beyond which a person could
not be sentenced to death or executed and that people suering from
mental retardation should be added to the list of those who should
be protected from capital punishment. Council Resolution 1996/15
called upon Member States in which the death penalty had not been
abolished “to eectively apply the safeguards guaranteeing the rights
of those facing the death penalty. The signicance of the Safeguards
was subsequently rearmed by the Commission on Human Rights in
2005 and the General Assembly in Resolutions 62/149 and 63/168.
All states are bound by the international standards set out in the Safe-
guards, which should be considered as the general law applicable to
the death penalty.
The fth safeguard states:
Capital punishment may only be carried out pursuant to a
nal judgment rendered by a competent court after legal pro-
cess which gives all possible safeguards to ensure a fair trial, at
least equal to those contained in Article 14 of the ICCPR,
including the right of anyone suspected of or charged with
a crime for which capital punishment may be imposed to
adequate legal assistance at all stages of the proceedings.
The United Nations Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary,
or Arbitrary Executions has stated that fair trial guarantees in death
penalty cases “must be implemented in all cases without exception or
discrimination.
8
The Special Rapporteur has reiterated that “proceed-
ings leading to the imposition of capital punishment must conform
to the highest standards of independence, competence, objectivity
and impartiality of judges and juries, in accordance with the pertinent
international legal instruments.
9
International norms clearly call for
those facing the death penalty to be aorded special protection and
8 Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions: Report of the Special Rapporteur, UN Document
E/CN.4/2001/9, 11 January 2001, paragraph 86.
9
Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions: Report of the Special Rapporteur, UN Document
E/CN.4/1997/60, 24 December 1996, paragraph 81.
52 53
guarantees to ensure a fair trial, above and beyond those aorded in
non-capital cases (sometimes referred to as “super due process”).
THE ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE IN
CAPITAL CASES
Numerous cases in countries that still impose the death penalty in the
Caribbean, Africa and Asia have failed to live up to these standards.
Some of them are discussed below. In the United Kingdom, which
has abolished the death penalty, several egregious wrongful convic-
tions in murder cases helped dissipate support for its reintroduction.
The Caribbean
There are many instances of miscarriage of justice and unfair trials in
capital cases in Caribbean countries. Wrongful convictions and unfair
trials are all too common, and the ratio of successful appeals to the
Courts of Appeal and the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council
reveals that the proper administration of justice is called into question
in far too many capital cases.
There are serious concerns that the common law as applied in the
19th century is not an adequate instrument for control of poorly
paid, lightly disciplined police forces who are under pressure to secure
results in the face of rising crime rates and criminal violence. The law
as it stands does not provide an adequate basis for the exclusion of
unreliable confessions, identications and other aspects of a defec-
tive investigation. People who face the death penalty are typically
tried and convicted upon confession evidence that is later challenged,
given at a time when legal aid is not available. The right of access to
a lawyer while in custody remains, on the whole, theoretical rather
than practical, and trial and appeal lawyers are too frequently ill-
equipped and/or insuciently experienced to ensure a fair trial and
often lack sucient resources to obtain the expert assistance (medical
or otherwise) needed to adequately prepare the defence.
10
10 See for example the Community Legal Services Act Cap. 112A of the Laws of Barbados and
decision of the Court of Appeal in Civil Appeal No. 20 of 1997 in Hinds v. Attorney General
of Barbados (30 September 1999). On legal aid fees, see also the Poor Persons Defence Act of
Jamaica.
The vast majority of prisoners in the Caribbean cannot aord to pay
for legal representation and are therefore provided with an attor-
ney through an inadequate legal aid system. The accused are often
assigned a very junior member of the bar to prepare the defence,
usually without any expert help, medical or otherwise.
In R v. Bethel,
11
the appellant’s conviction for murder and his death
sentence were quashed and a retrial ordered as his trial lawyer had
failed to take proper instructions before the trial. The Court of
Appeal of Trinidad and Tobago emphasised that whatever the time
spent taking instructions, in a murder case involving the death pen-
alty, the gravity of the charge required counsel to pursue with his
client a “full and searching inquiry into the facts.
The domestic courts in the Caribbean have on a number of other
occasions considered the eectiveness of legal representation and the
conduct of counsel in a capital case. For example, Ann-Marie Boodram
had been sentenced to a mandatory death penalty in Trinidad for the
murder of her husband. Her appeal to the Court of Appeal was rejected,
and she further appealed to the Judicial Committee of the Privy Coun-
cil (hereinafter the Privy Council), who considered whether her trial
lawyer’s gross incompetence had resulted in a miscarriage of justice. In
delivering the judgment of the Board, Lord Steyn held:
In the present case [her trial lawyer’s] multiple failures,
and in particular his extraordinary failure when he became
aware on 17th February, 1998 that he was engaged on
a retrial to enquire into what happened at the rst trial,
revealed either gross incompetence or a cynical dereliction
of the most elementary professional duties. ... it is the
worst case of the failure of counsel to carry out his duties
in a criminal case that their Lordships have come across.
The breaches are of such a fundamental nature that
the conclusion must be that the defendant was deprived
of due process. ... The conclusion must be in this excep-
tional case the defendant did not have a fair trial.
12
11 R v. Bethel, Unreported, 23 March 2000, Court of Appeal of Trinidad and Tobago, Republic of
Trinidad and Tobago.
12
Boodram v. the State, paragraph 40, 1 Criminal Appeal Reports 12 (2002), Judicial Committee
of the Privy Council, Republic of Trinidad and Tobago.
54 55
Another death penalty case from Trinidad (Dookran and another v. the
State)
13
concerned the investigation and collection of the evidence by
the police and the conduct of the trial itself. It revealed that the law
and practice as it stands does not guarantee the level of protection
required by international norms in the investigation, prosecution and
trial of a capital case.
In 1997, Chitrah Dookran and her mother, Malharri Dookran, were
convicted of the murder of Chanardai Dookran-Bissoon, who was
Chitrah’s sister and Malharri’s daughter. A third defendant, Devon
Cunningham (the alleged hit man), was acquitted whilst Chitrah and
Malharri were sentenced to death. Both were unrepresented when
taken into police custody, and the case centred on incriminating
statements they allegedly gave to the police. Chitrah claimed her
statement was involuntary and preceded by threats and promises by a
police ocer whom the prosecution never called as a witness, but the
trial judge still admitted her statement into evidence. The Court of
Appeal held that Chitrah’s statement should not have been admitted
into evidence before the jury, but nevertheless held that there had
been no miscarriage of justice. The Privy Council disagreed and held
that the approach of the Court of Appeal was fundamentally awed as
they could not be satised that a reasonable jury would have inevita-
bly convicted her had the statement not been admitted into evidence.
This was a clear miscarriage of justice, and Chitrah’s conviction was
quashed and she was released from death row.
Malharri, who was elderly and of low intelligence and who had a
history of being battered by her husband, contended at trial that she
was kept in custody without food for over 14 hours before her state-
ment was taken. She alleged that the investigating police ocer made
her take o her glasses and threatened to bang her head against a
wall before she eventually put her cross (X) on the statement that the
police ocer had written out for her. The trial judge admitted Mal-
harri’s statement into evidence in spite of the allegations of physical
abuse and coercion by the police and evidence indicating Malharri
was especially vulnerable due to her low intelligence and history of
domestic abuse.
13 Dookran and another v. the State, UKPC 15 (2007), Judicial Committee of the Privy Council,
Republic of Trinidad and Tobago.
Having already quashed Chitrah’s conviction and death sentence,
the Privy Council held that they could not “avoid a residual feel-
ing of unease about whether justice has been done in Malharri’s
case.
14
The appeal was allowed, and Malharri was also released from
death row.
In many capital cases from the Caribbean, individuals who are
sentenced to death have subsequently been found to be suering
from mental illness and/or an intellectual disability that aected the
safety and lawfulness of their convictions and death sentences. This
is especially so in countries with inadequate mental health services.
The reality is that the death penalty is regularly imposed on people
with signicant mental disorders, contrary to recognised norms and
procedural requirements. There are many examples of defendants
being wrongly sentenced to death by virtue of the fact that inade-
quate or no medical evidence was produced at trial.
In 2012, on the strength of fresh psychiatric evidence, the appeal of
Shorn Samuel,
15
a prisoner under sentence of death in Saint Vincent
and the Grenadines, was allowed by the Eastern Caribbean Court of
Appeal. The Court found that new medical evidence demonstrated
that Mr. Samuel was suering from a severe mental disorder at the
time of the murder, which substantially diminished his responsibility
for the oence. Mr. Samuel’s conviction for murder was therefore
quashed, and a conviction of manslaughter was substituted by reason
of diminished responsibility. The death sentence was reduced to
life imprisonment.
In 2012, the appeal of Sheldon Issac,
16
a prisoner under sentence of
death in Saint Kitts and Nevis, was determined by the Eastern Carib-
bean Court of Appeal. The last hanging in Saint Kitts and Nevis had
taken place in 2008, and Mr. Isaac and his three co-defendants were
at real risk of execution. The Privy Council granted all four defen-
dants stays of execution pending the determination of their appeals.
Psychiatric and psychological evidence was presented to the Privy
14 Ibid., paragraph 36
15
Shorn Samuel v. the Queen, Criminal Appeal No. 22 of 2008 (2012), Eastern Caribbean Court
of Appeal, Saint Vincent and the Grenadines.
16
Sheldon Issac v. Director of Public Prosecutions, Criminal Appeal No. 19 of 2008 (2012), Eastern
Caribbean Court of Appeal, Saint Kitts and Nevis.
56 57
Council demonstrating that Mr. Isaac was severely brain-damaged
and should never have stood trial. The Privy Council remitted the
case to the Eastern Caribbean Court of Appeal for review, and the
Court of Appeal accepted the evidence that he was severely men-
tally disordered and concluded that he was unt to stand trial. The
Court rejected a retrial as inappropriate and unnecessary. The system
of criminal justice in Saint Kitts and Nevis clearly failed in this capital
case: The investigating authorities, the prison service, the lawyers and
the trial judge all failed to recognize that Mr. Isaac was so severely
mentally disordered that he was unt to stand trial. As a result, he
was tried, convicted, sentenced to death and very nearly executed,
contrary to international standards and norms.
In 2005, the UN Commission on Human Rights urged all states
that maintain the death penalty “not to impose the death penalty on
a person suering from any mental or intellectual disabilities or to
execute such a person.
17
The reality, though, is that a large propor-
tion of prisoners under sentence of death have never been properly
examined by a psychiatrist or psychologist, resulting in many prison-
ers who are mentally disordered or impaired facing the death penalty
in the Caribbean and beyond.
Africa
I am not aware of any academic research into innocence and miscarriages
of justice in capital cases in Africa, but there are concerns that many of
the features identied in Caribbean death penalty cases also prevail in
African retentionist countries. A few of these are described below.
Malawi’s criminal justice system, like that of many Commonwealth
Caribbean countries, is based on English common law. An obvious dif-
ference is that capital murder trials are held in the High Court before a
single judge who determines guilt and imposes a sentence, not before
a jury. Although Malawi’s Criminal Procedure Code provides for the
right of trial by jury, jury trials in homicide cases were discontinued in
2009 by executive at, a decision justied at least in part by their cost.
17 Oce of the High Commissioner of Human Rights, Human Rights Resolution 2005/59,
“The question of the death penalty”, paragraph 7(c), available from http://ap.ohchr.org/docu-
ments/alldocs.aspx?doc_id=11140.
Article 42 of the Malawi Constitution provides that indigent defendants
facing criminal charges are entitled to free legal aid “where the interests
of justice so require. In practice, however, legal aid is provided only in
homicide cases as there are so few lawyers to serve the entire country.
Malawi has struggled for years with a tremendous backlog of
homicide cases causing severe prison overcrowding throughout
the country . . . . Bail is rarely granted in such cases, and homi-
cide trials are frequently suspended, meaning many accused
persons spend several years awaiting trial. These “remand”
prisoners typically will not speak to a lawyer until the day of
trial, when a Legal-Aid advocate will interview them briey.
The defence rarely calls witnesses or conduct any investigation;
in most cases counsel simply cross-examines the prosecution’s
witnesses based on a thin le containing witness statements
and a post-mortem examination. . . . Under Section 11 of the
Supreme Court of Appeals Act, each individual convicted of
homicide has the right to appeal to the Malawi Supreme Court.
In practice, however, the right to appeal is often frustrated
by the lack of an eective case-management system and the
failure of Legal-Aid attorneys to track cases on appeal. Case
les often go missing. . . . As of January 2012, no appeals had
been led for 11 of the prisoners sentenced to death from 2005
to 2009. In several of these cases, the courts appear to have lost
all court records relating to the conviction, including the trial
transcript and exhibits.
18
Clearly, the requisite fair trial standards cannot be applied to every
death-penalty case in countries that lack the resources to ensure due
process. Thus, there is a great risk of innocent people being sentenced
to death. The law, as applied in countries such as Malawi, does not
protect against mistakes leading to the wrong person being convicted
and sentenced to death.
In Uganda, Edmary Mpagi spent over 18 years on death row, accused
of killing a man who was later found to be alive. In 1982, he was
18 Sandra Babcock and Ellen Wight McLaughlin, “Reconciling human rights and the application
of the death penalty in Malawi: the unfullled promise of Kafantayeni v. Attorney General”,
in
Capital Punishment: New Perspectives, Peter Hodgkinson, ed. (Farnham, United Kingdom,
Ashgate Publishing, 2013), p. 193
58 59
convicted, together with his cousin, of murder and sentenced to death,
after what has been called “fabricated evidence, coerced testimony
and a generally slipshod trial.
19
Mpagi met with his state-appointed
lawyer only twice before the trial, and no translator was provided
even though neither he nor his cousin had any working knowledge
of English.
20
Prison conditions were reportedly cruel, degrading and
inhumane. Mpagi’s cousin died in prison in 1985 after the prison
authorities refused to provide him with medical attention, stating that
they could not waste time or money on a condemned prisoner who
was due to be executed.
21
In 1989, the Attorney General established
that Mpagi was innocent and wrongly convicted; however, it was not
until 2000, 11 years later, that Mpagi received a presidential pardon
and was released.
In Sierra Leone, “MK” was the longest serving woman on death
row. She was arrested in 2003 and charged with the murder of her
stepdaughter, convicted in 2005, and received the death penalty,
which was mandatory at the time in Sierra Leone. MK’s case high-
lights many of the serious human rights concerns that can occur in
capital cases. From her arrest until shortly before trial, she received
no legal advice or assistance. MK, who is illiterate, thumb-printed a
confession which was later used against her at trial. The state did not
provide MK with a lawyer until the commencement of the trial. This
lawyer met with MK three times before the trial, each meeting lasting
no longer than 15 minutes.
Following her trial, MK again did not have access to a lawyer,
and she did not have the knowledge or resources to le an appeal
against her conviction within the stipulated 21-day time limit.
MK led an appeal to the Court of Appeal 10 months after her
conviction with the assistance of a state-provided Prison Welfare
Ocer. The Court of Appeal rejected the appeal, holding that the
time period for ling appeals cannot be extended even for those
facing the death penalty.
19 Foundation for Human Rights Initiative, Towards the Abolition of the Death Penalty in Uganda,
the Civil Society Coalition on the Abolition of the Death Penalty in Uganda (2008).
20 Mpagi Edward Edmary, “Mpagi Edward Edmary”,
Our Friends in Prison, available from www.
ourfriendsinprison.weebly.com/lifestory-of-mpagi-edward-edmary.html.
21 Ibid.
In 2010, MK received legal assistance from AdvocAid, a Sierra Leo-
nean non-governmental organisation, and her case was re-listed in
the Court of Appeal. In March 2011, after she spent six years on death
row, MK’s conviction was overturned in a landmark decision by the
Court of Appeal, and she was released immediately. The Court found
that the procedural irregularities—lack of legal advice and assistance,
lack of resources to le an appeal—were fundamental, and therefore
rendered MK’s trial a nullity.
Asia
An authoritative recent United Nations report
22
stated: “In many
countries in Asia, specically in death penalty cases, the right to a fair
trial was impeded by laws which denied due process. Even in countries
where due process safeguards exist in principle, they were not applied
in practice. The Anti-Death Penalty Asia Network has reported that
courts continue to rely on “confessions” extracted through
torture as evidence in criminal trials—despite the interna-
tional ban on torture and on the use of such confessions.
Laws impose mandatory death sentences for crimes such
as drug tracking, and place the burden of proof on the
accused, depriving them of the right to be presumed inno-
cent until and unless proven guilty according to law. Access
to a lawyer before, during and after trial is often denied,
and in some countries the independence of the judiciary
is not assured. Some states have established special courts
which sentence people to death after hasty proceedings.
23
There have been 11 executions in Taiwan since 2013, in spite of
growing public disquiet about the death penalty with the knowl-
edge that there is a real danger the state could execute someone in
error following an unfair trial.
24
In January 2011, Taiwan’s Ministry of
22 Moratorium on the Use of the Death Penalty, Report of the Secretary-General (3 August 2012),
UN Doc. A/67/22, paragraph 34.
23 Anti-Death Penalty Asia Network,
When Justice Fails, Thousands Executed in Asia After Unfair
Trials (Amnesty International ASA 01/023/2011), p. 6.
24 For more information on the death penalty in Taiwan, see The Death Penalty Project,
The
Death Penalty in Taiwan: A Report on Taiwan’s Legal Obligations under the International Cove-
nant on Civil and Political Rights (London, 2014), available from www.deathpenaltyproject.org/
news/1750/dpp-launches-report-on-the-death-penalty-in-taiwan/.
60 61
Justice admitted that Chiang Kuo-ching had been executed in error
in 1997, for the rape and murder of a ve-year-old girl committed 15
years previously. After a campaign by Chiang’s parents, the Military
Supreme Court Prosecutor’s Oce led an extraordinary appeal with
the Military Supreme Court to reopen the case in 2010. The author-
ities acknowledged that Chiang’s confession was the result of torture
by military investigators, including being subjected to a 37-hour
interrogation, exposed to strong lights, threatened with an electric
prod and deprived of sleep while being forced to undergo strenuous
physical activities.
25
The authorities accepted that the trial court had
ignored Chiang’s allegations of torture and his pleas of innocence and
that his conviction had been rushed through by the military court.
26
In September 2011, a military court formally acquitted Chiang, and
in October 2011, Taiwan’s Ministry of Defence agreed to pay US$3.4
million in compensation to Chiang’s relatives. President Ma Ying-
Jeou publicly apologised to Chiang’s mother and conceded that the
authorities had “acted wrongly” in the case.
27
In many retentionist countries in Asia, prisoners facing the death
penalty have little or no access to a lawyer following arrest and when
preparing for trial or appeal.
Many of those sentenced to death in Afghanistan do not
have proper legal representation at the time of their trial.
In fact, defence lawyers in Afghanistan are normally not
even present in the trial court but must submit a written
rebuttal of the charges against their client to the court.
In Indonesia even though the Criminal Procedure Code
guarantees the right to be assisted by a lawyer, in practice
there are documented cases of defendants who do not have
access to a lawyer. In China, the authorities may block
or make it very dicult for defence lawyers to meet with
their clients, gather evidence and access case documents.
25 Taiwan Alliance to End the Death Penalty, “Doubts raised over soldier’s execution” (30 January
2011), available from www.taedp.org.tw/en/story/1875.
26 Amnesty International,
Death Sentences and Executions 2013, p. 5. See also Amnesty Interna-
tional, China: Against the Law: Crackdown on China’s Human Rights Lawyers Deepens (2011),
available from www.amnesty.org/en/library/info/ASA17/018/2011/en.
27 The National, “Taiwan ‘child rapist’ cleared 14 years after his execution” (2 February 2011),
available from www.thenational.ae/news/world/asia-pacic/taiwan-child-rapist-cleared-14-
years-after-his-execution.
Lawyers defending clients involved in politically sensitive
cases have been subjected to intimidation and excluded
from proceedings. Others have had charges led against
them for advising their clients to withdraw forced confes-
sions or for trying to introduce evidence that challenges
the prosecution’s case.
28
In Japan, there are no legal provisions requiring the eective assis-
tance of defence counsel. Indeed, Japanese courts tend not to nd
problems even when defence counsel’s assistance is clearly ineec-
tive and inappropriate.
29
In some cases, death sentences have been
imposed and nalised despite insucient assistance from a defence
lawyer, but there have been no cases in which a death sentence has
been overturned because of the ineective assistance of counsel.
A minimum fair trial guarantee that needs to be respected in all capital
cases is the right of appeal. In the Caribbean, the availability of an
automatic appeal has saved many innocent lives, as the appellate courts
have on numerous occasions overturned capital convictions. However,
in a number of Asian countries there is no mandatory right of appeal,
thus increasing the risk that wrongful convictions will not be remedied.
China now provides for more than one appeal, but there are concerns
that the review process before the Supreme People’s Court does not
meet the minimum requirements of Article 14 of the ICCPR because
the present procedures are insucient to meet developing human
rights standards. All appeals must be governed by the principles and
safeguards of Article 14, and in order to ensure an eective right of
appeal, the convicted person should be granted eective access to
the review process with adequate legal representation in an open,
public hearing.
In Japan, appeal to a higher court against a death sentence is not
automatic despite repeated recommendations by the UN Committee
28 Anti-Death Penalty Asia Network, When Justice Fails, p. 24.
29 The Death Penalty Project,
The Death Penalty in Japan: A Report on Japan’s Legal Obligations
under the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and an Assessment of Public
Attitudes to Capital Punishment (2013), pp. 7-8, available from www.deathpenaltyproject.org/
legal-resources/research-publications/the-death-penalty-in-japan/.
62 63
against Torture and the UN Human Rights Committee.
30
The gov-
ernment of Japan insists that a mandatory appeal system is unnecessary
because most defendants do exercise their right to appeal. But the
numbers are troubling. Of the rst 15 death sentences imposed by lay
judge panels in Japan, three (20 per cent) were nalised after defen-
dants withdrew their appeals. Moreover, people sentenced to death in
Japan who withdraw their appeals tend to be executed more quickly
than non-volunteers (people who withdraw their appeals seldom le
requests for retrial or pardon either).
In South Korea and parts of Pakistan, there is no mandatory require-
ment for appeal to a higher court in death penalty cases, and in North
Korea there is no possibility of appeal at all.
31
Japan also fails to conform to universally agreed standards for spe-
cial protection and fair-trial guarantees beyond those oered in
non-capital cases.
32
Capital punishment is not treated as a dierent
form of punishment in Japan despite claims to the contrary. As a
result, there are few special procedural protections accorded to sus-
pects and defendants in potential capital cases.
33
Since Japan’s lay
judge system started in 2009, the courts have become more restric-
tive about what evidence can be introduced at trial. The change
is largely motivated by the desire to minimise the burden felt by
citizens who serve as lay judges, and the courts have become more
likely to demand that expert testimony be presented in extremely
abbreviated forms. As a result, a defendant’s psychological condi-
tion and developmental problems are seldom considered by the lay
judge tribunals as carefully as they should be.
34
Furthermore, Japan
does not require unanimity (of all judges and lay judges on a panel)
or even a super-majority (agreement by six or more of the nine
30 Paragraph 20, CAT/C/JPN/CO/1, 3 August 2007; paragraph 17, CCPR/C/JPN/CO/5, 30
October 2008.
31 Anti-Death Penalty Asia Network,
When Justice Fails, p. 31.
32 International Federation for Human Rights,
The Death Penalty in Japan: The Law of Silence
(2008), available from www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/hrc/docs/ngos/FIDHJapan94.pdf;
Amnesty International,
Death Sentences and Executions 2012, available from www.amnesty.
org/en/library/asset/ACT50/001/2013/en/bbfea0d6-39b2-4e5f-a1ad-885a8eb5c607/
act500012013en.pdf. See also Taiwan Alliance to End the Death Penalty, “Doubts raised over
soldier’s execution”.
33 David T. Johnson, “Capital punishment without capital trials in Japan’s lay judge system”,
Asia
Pacic Journal, vol. 8, issue 52 (27 December 2010), pp. 1-38, available from www.japanfocus.
org/-David_T_-Johnson/3461.
34 The Death Penalty Project,
The Death Penalty in Japan, pp. 21-22.
people on a panel) before the death penalty can be imposed. A bare
“mixed majority”—ve votes, with at least one from a professional
judge—is enough to condemn a person to death. “It is dicult to
square Japan’s mixed majority rule with the claim often made by
Japanese ocials that the country is extremely ‘cautious’ (shincho)
about capital punishment.
35
The combination of the lack of eective judicial control over the use
of lengthy pretrial detention, the failure to require jury unanimity for
a death sentence, the lack of eective mandatory appeals and the need
for a fair and functioning process of executive mercy places Japan
in breach of its international obligations with regard to the death
penalty. Japan is one of the wealthiest nations in Asia, with a sophisti-
cated and well-resourced legal system, but is yet another example of
a country that fails to implement capital punishment in accordance
with universally accepted safeguards. Miscarriages of justice will inev-
itably occur, and when the death penalty is imposed, it results in an
irreversible injustice.
35 Ibid p. 22. See also David T. Johnson, “Progress and problems in Japanese capital punishment”,
in Confronting Capital Punishment in Asia: Human Rights, Politics, Public Opinion, and Practic-
es, Roger Hood and Surya Deva, eds. (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013), p. 176.
64 65
The United Kingdom
Many lessons can be learned from the United Kingdom, where the death
penalty was in eect abolished in 1965.
36
Between 1966 and 1993, there
were 13 attempts in Parliament to reintroduce the death penalty for cer-
tain categories of murder. These attempts ended after a shocking series
of miscarriages of justice in cases concerning particularly heinous crimes.
The most notable were those of the Birmingham Six and the Guildford
Four, all wrongfully convicted of murder through terrorist bombings,
and Stefan Kisko, a man of limited intelligence, wrongfully convicted of
a child sex murder. “All would certainly have attracted the death penalty
had it been available. This persuaded many who had previously supported
the reintroduction of capital punishment to change their minds.
37
The last execution in the United Kingdom was carried out in 1964,
but it was not until 1999 that the United Kingdom ratied Protocol
No. 6 to the European Convention on Human Rights and Protocol
No. 2 of the ICCPR, thus marking by international treaty its nal
rejection of capital punishment.
There have been no campaigns since then, in the press, by
pressure groups, or in parliament to seek to reinstate the
death penalty. Even the families of the victims of the most
appalling types of crime, like the abduction and sexual
murder of children, have expressed themselves generally as
satised by a sentence of life imprisonment, with a guaran-
teed lengthy period of custody.
38
This rejection of capital punishment has been further strengthened
by a series of cases where the courts have posthumously reviewed
the murder convictions of individuals who were executed. In 1998,
36 In 1965, the death penalty for murder was suspended for a period of ve years (to expire on
31 July 1970) unless both houses of Parliament determined that it should not expire by ar-
mative resolutions. In reality this was the end of capital punishment for murder in the United
Kingdom, and in 1969, the House of Commons endorsed the 1965 Act.
37 Roger Hood, “Abolition of capital punishment in the United Kingdom”, paper presented at
the workshop Global Survey on Death Penalty Reform, Beijing, 25-26 August 2007, p. 13. See
also Roger Hood and Carolyn Hoyle,
The Death Penalty: A World-wide Perspective, 4th ed.
(Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 42-47.
38 Ibid, p. 14.
the Court of Appeal found that the conviction of Mahmoud Hussein
Mattan, who was hanged in Cardi Prison on 8 September 1952,
should be quashed. In delivering judgement, Lord Justice Rose stated
that the case had wide signicance and demonstrated that “capital
punishment was not perhaps an appropriate culmination for a crimi-
nal justice system which was human and therefore fallible.
39
CONCLUSION
A precondition, under international law, for imposing the ultimate
penalty is that the investigation, prosecution and trial have been
conducted with impeccable fairness and propriety. All too often,
capital trials fall short of these standards. But even when procedural
guarantees are improved and the protection of law is provided to all
individuals, wrongful convictions and miscarriages of justice will still
occur. The likelihood of wrongful convictions can be decreased, but
the risk that innocent people will be executed can never be elimi-
nated altogether as there is no perfect justice system.
39 R v. Mattan, All England Ocial Transcripts 676 (1998), Court of Appeal, United Kingdom.
66
“The empirical research conducted over the past few
decades demonstrates that no matter what politicians
argue or the public believe, neither deterrence nor
public opinion should be seen as barriers to abolition.
—Carolyn Hoyle and Roger Hood
67
CHAPTER 2
MYTH OF DETERRENCE
Chapter focuses on deterrence and the death penalty. Three academics, based
on results of their own as well as those of other researchers during the last
fty years assessing the deterring eects of the death penalty.
Drawing on studies in diverse countries including Australia, Canada,
Trinidad and Tobago, the United States, as well as a number of Asian
and European countries, well-known academics Carolyn Hoyle and Roger
Hood demonstrate that there is no clear evidence that the death penalty has
a deterrent eect on crime. Popular support for the death penalty depends
heavily on belief in its deterring power; the best way to counter this belief is
through better information. Leaders should not hide behind public opinion
statistics but should lead the move away from the death penalty. In a
number of countries, since the death penalty has been abolished, more and
more citizens have come to regard it as cruel and obsolete.
Jerey Fagan, a Columbia Law School Professor, warns that deterrence
remains deeply embedded in the social and political culture in States that
execute. Moving away from the death penalty should be based on informa-
tion: ve decades of research have shown that scientic evidence supporting
the belief in deterrence is unreliable. Using examples regarding the death
penalty for drug oences and terrorism, he demonstrates how, and why,
assumptions of its deterring eects are wrong. States that execute in the
face of uncertainty about its deterrent eects are implicated in taking lives
without a measurable return beyond vengeance or retribution.
The feet of a man convicted of murder are seen during a hanging. © Credit: EPA/Raed Qutena
68 69
DETERRENCE AND
PUBLIC OPINION
Carolyn Hoyle and Roger Hood
1
DECLINING USE OF THE DEATH PENALTY
At the end of 2013, the number of countries that were “actively
retentionist” (had carried out at least one judicial execution within
the past 10 years and had not subsequently declared a permanent
moratorium on executions) had fallen to just 39, 20 percent of the
world’s countries. Only seven of these countries have executed 10
or more citizens every year for the past decade (2003 to 2012), and
not all of them because they believe that it is a necessary deterrent to
crime: China, Iran, Iraq, North Korea (probably), Saudi Arabia, Yemen
and the United States.
The use of capital punishment in retentionist countries has also been
declining. Whereas 37 countries carried out a judicial execution in
1998, only 21 did so in 2012. With very few exceptions, such as Iran,
Iraq, and Saudi Arabia, the number of executions per year appears to
be falling almost everywhere.
Singapore, which in the mid-1990s had the world’s highest execution
rate per head of population—carrying out 74 executions in 1994—
has reduced the number drastically, executing only a few people in the
last ve years. Malaysia, which executed between 13 and 15 people
a year between 1970 and 2000, has carried out very few executions
since the turn of the millennium, despite retaining a mandatory death
penalty for certain oences. Thailand and Indonesia now also carry
out only sporadic or occasional executions.
Pakistan, which executed at least 135 people in 2007 and 36 in 2008,
has since adopted a policy not to carry out executions (although one
did occur under military jurisdiction in November 2012). India had
no executions between 2004 and November 2012; since then, two
1 Carolyn Hoyle and Roger Hood are the authors of The Death Penalty: A Worldwide Perspective.
This paper draws on their research for the book’s fth edition (Oxford University Press, 2014).
people convicted of murders committed during terrorist attacks have
been executed.
These examples don’t demonstrate that executions are coming to an
end in these countries, but they do suggest a commitment to pro-
gressive restriction—to using the ultimate penalty only in the most
egregious cases.
On the other hand, there has been considerable resistance to the
political movement to force change ever since the Second Optional
Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights
was adopted by the United Nations General Assembly in 1989.
Attempts since 1994 by abolitionist nations at the United Nations
General Assembly to press for a resolution calling for a worldwide
moratorium on the imposition of death sentences and executions
were still being resisted by 41 countries (on the grounds that there
is no international consensus that the death penalty is a violation
of human rights) when the resolution was debated at the General
Assembly in December 2012. This is signicantly fewer than the 66
countries that opposed such a resolution in 2005. Indeed, opposition
has weakened at each subsequent vote since 2007, though powerful
countries such as Japan, China, India and the United States have con-
sistently voted against the resolution.
RESISTANCE TO CHANGE
Across abolitionist jurisdictions, and within supranational and national
bodies that oppose the death penalty, abolition is now established as a
matter of principle, with the doctrine of inalienable human rights—
specically the right to life and the right not to be subjected to cruel,
inhuman and degrading punishment—drawn on to provide the absolute
justication for abolition. However, governments in many retentionist
countries argue that total prohibition is not yet established as a human
rights norm. They cling to their sovereign right to determine their own
laws and criminal justice practices, often drawing on public support for
the death penalty, and in particular belief in its deterrent eect.
In the past decade, various countries—including some that are abo-
litionist de facto, such as South Korea, Jordan and Algeria—have
70 71
rejected bills to abolish the death penalty, with the public faith in
its deterrent eect cited as a reason for caution. Deterrence is the
main argument, or at least a powerful secondary argument alongside
retribution, of many governments that support capital punishment,
such as those of China, Japan, Indonesia, Singapore and a number
of countries in the Middle East and Africa. In Iraq, the authorities
in 2010 at its United Nations Universal Periodic Review stated that
“because of the exceptional circumstances in Iraq and the prevalence
of terrorist crimes targeting the right to life, the death penalty had
been maintained as a means of deterrence and to provide justice to
the families of victims.
2
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT AND
THE HOMICIDE RATE
Because it would be morally repugnant to conduct random exper-
iments in the use of capital punishment, it remains dicult, if not
impossible, to nd empirical data on the deterrent eects of the
threat of capital punishment that would utterly persuade a com-
mitted proponent of the death penalty to change his or her mind.
Indeed, as far as some crimes punishable by death in several coun-
tries are concerned—such as importing or trading in illegal drugs,
economic crimes, or politically motivated violence—there simply is
no reliable evidence of the deterrent eects of executions. Nor have
any empirical studies investigated the impact of capital punishment
when used on a more extensive scale as an exemplary punishment
in law-and-order campaigns, such as have occurred in China and
Iran. Consequently, almost all the studies available for review are con-
cerned with the deterrent eect of capital punishment on the murder
rate in the United States.
3
That said, the evidence should lead any dispassionate analyst to conclude
that it is not prudent to accept the hypothesis that capital punishment,
as practiced in the United States, deters murder to a marginally greater
2 Report of the Working Group on the Universal Periodic Review, Iraq (2010), UN Doc. A/
HRC/14/14.
3 For a review of deterrence studies in the United States, Singapore and Hong Kong, see Ethan
Cohen-Cole, Jerey Fagan and Daniel Nagin, “Model uncertainty and the deterrent eect of
capital punishment”, American Law and Economics Review, vol. 7, no. 2 (2008), pp. 335-369;
Franklin Zimring, Jerey Fagan and David T. Johnson, “Executions, deterrence and homicide: A
tale of two cities”, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, vol. 7 (2010), pp. 1-29, at p. 24.
extent than does the supposedly lesser punishment of life imprisonment.
A 2012 report by the Committee on Deterrence and the Death Penalty
of the National Research Council in the United States, which reviewed
evidence published over 34 years, oered the same conclusion:
Research to date on the eect of capital punishment on
homicide is not informative about whether capital punish-
ment decreases, increases, or has no eect on homicide rates.
Therefore the Committee recommends that these studies not
be used to inform deliberations requiring judgments about
the eect of the death penalty on homicide and ... should
not inuence policy judgments about capital punishment.
4
One rather unsophisticated way of considering deterrence is to
analyse homicide rates before and after the death penalty is abol-
ished. This at least can show whether countries that abolish capital
punishment inevitably experience more murders, as those who
support the deterrent argument claim. In Australia, where the last
executions occurred in the mid-1960s, the reported murder rate
has, a few uctuations aside, fallen. Prior to the abolition of the
death penalty in Canada, the reported homicide rate had been
rising, yet in 2003, 27 years after abolition, the rate had fallen to
1.73 per 100,000 population, 43 percent lower than it was in 1975
(3.02 per 100,000), the year before abolition.
5
The sharp decline
following abolition was a potent argument used by the Canadian
prime minister in 1987 when opposing the reintroduction of capital
punishment.
6
The rate has continued to fall. In 2012 it was 1.56 per
100,000 population, its lowest level since 1966.
Although not designed to study the relationship between abolition
of the death penalty and homicide rates, a 2011 study by the United
Nations Oce on Drugs and Crime of global trends in homicide
showed that although the homicide rate rose initially after abolition
4 Daniel S. Nagin and John V. Pepper, eds., Deterrence and the Death Penalty (Washington, DC,
National Academies Press, 2012), p. 3.
5 Susan Munroe, “Abolition of capital punishment in Canada: Canadian murder rate stays low
without capital punishment”, About.com (updated 31 October 2010), available from http://
canadaonline.about.com/od/crime/a/abolitioncappun.htm.
6 Speech in the Canadian House of Commons, 22 June 1987, by the Right Honourable Brian
Mulroney, Prime Minister of Canada, Commons Debates, p. 7477.
72 73
of the death penalty in Eastern European countries, it declined
quite sharply after the mid-1990s, and this decline has not been
reversed. Thus, the homicide rate in ve countries of Central and
Eastern Europe (the Czech Republic, Hungary, Moldova, Poland
and Romania, all of which abolished the death penalty in the 1990s)
declined by 61 percent from 4.5 to 1.6 per 100,000 between 2000
and 2008, declining especially in respect to male victims. The study
concluded that “virtually all countries [in Europe] where there has
been a strengthening of the rule of law [and no death penalty] have
also experienced a decline in the homicide rate.
7
In Trinidad and Tobago, which has a very high homicide rate, aca-
demics have not been able to establish any relationship between
trends in the execution and murder rates.
8
Taiwan’s informal mor-
atorium on executions, which lasted from 2006 to 2010, provided
an opportunity to examine whether the withdrawal of the threat of
execution led to an increase in violent crimes reported to the police.
Analysis by the Taiwan Alliance to End the Death Penalty showed
that in fact the violent crime rate per 100,000 of the population fell
during these four years from 62.9 in 2005 (when there were three
executions) to 53.6 the following year and 29.3 in 2009.
9
In 2009, Richard Berk, a distinguished statistician, concluded that
over the past 20 years no progress had been made towards deter-
mining whether or not executions had a deterrent impact and
that no further progress would be made in the next 20 years.
10
Given the data available for analysis and the statistical and econo-
metric techniques that can be employed, as well as the methods
employed for selecting and controlling for all other factors that
might be associated with the murder rate and execution rate over
7 United Nations Oce on Drugs and Crime, 2011 Global Study on Homicide: Trends, Contexts,
Data (Vienna, 2011), p. 33.
8 David F. Greenberg and Biko Agozino, “Executions, imprisonment and crime in Trinidad and
Tobago”, British Journal of Criminology, vol. 52 (2012), pp. 113-140 and 117-118; Roger
Hood and Florence Seemungal, A Rare and Arbitrary Fate: Convictions for Murder, the Man-
datory Death Penalty and the Reality of Homicide in Trinidad and Tobago, report prepared for
the Death Penalty Project (Oxford: University of Oxford Centre for Criminology, 2006), pp.
15-22.
9 A Blow to Human Rights: Taiwan Resumes Executions: The Death Penalty in Taiwan, 2010
(Taipei: Taiwan Alliance to End the Death Penalty, 2011), p. 15.
10 Richard Berk, “Can’t tell: Comments on ‘Does the death penalty save lives?’”, Criminology and
Public Policy, vol. 8, no. 4 (2009), pp. 845-851.
time and across jurisdictions, contradictory ndings and interpreta-
tions seem to be inevitable.
11
Articles in the Journal of Quantitative
Criminology, published in 2013, came to similar conclusions, making
clear that the recent literature on deterrence in the United States
was “inconclusive as a whole, and in many cases uninformative”,
12
primarily because of methodological problems. As another article
in the journal concluded: “It is thus immaterial whether the stud-
ies purport to nd evidence in favour or against deterrence. They
simply do not rise to level of credible evidence on deterrence as a
behavioural mechanism.
13
Although there must have been instances in which people refrained
from murder out of fear of execution, this in itself is an insucient
basis on which to conclude that the existence of the death penalty
and the (often remote) threat of execution will lead to a lower
rate of murder than would be the case without it. The issue is not
whether the death penalty deters some (if only a few) people where
the threat of a lesser punishment would not, but whether, when
all the circumstances surrounding its use are taken into account,
it is associated with a marginally lower rate of the death-penalty-
eligible kinds of murder than the next most severe penalty,
life imprisonment.
The reason one must weigh all its eects is that capital punishment
has several drawbacks to counter its supposedly obvious advantages.
For example, oenders threatened with death could have an added
incentive to kill witnesses to their crimes. Furthermore, it may be
much less easy to convict people when the punishment may be death
than when it is less draconian. In other words, severity of punish-
ment may run counter to the more eective certainty of punishment.
Evidence to support this comes from England, Wales and Canada,
11 See Ethan Cohen-Cole, Jerey Fagan and Daniel Nagin, “Model uncertainty and the deterrent
eect of capital punishment”, American Law and Economics Review, vol. 7, no. 2 (2008), pp.
335-369. These authors used a model-averaging method across dierent studies and concluded,
“not that there is no deterrent eect present, but rather that inferences on its magnitude are so
imprecise as to make representation of strong claims impossible” (p. 364).
12 Aaron Chaln, Amelia M. Haviland and Steven Raphael, “What do panel studies tell us about
a deterrent eect of capital punishment? A critique of the literature”, Journal of Quantitative
Criminology, vol. 29 (2013), pp. 5-43, at pp. 5 and 8.
13 Kerwin Ko Charles and Steven N. Durlauf, “Pitfalls in the use of time series methods to study
deterrence and capital punishment”, Journal of Quantitative Criminology, vol. 29 (2013), pp.
45-66, at pp. 45-46 and 65.
74 75
where since abolition of the death penalty it has proven easier to
obtain convictions for murder rather than the less serious oence of
manslaughter. In fact, the proportion convicted of murder among all
those convicted of a homicide in England and Wales increased from
28 percent in 1965 (the year that capital punishment was abolished)
to 63 percent in 2005/2006.
14
The same has been true in Canada,
where the conviction rate for rst-degree (capital) murder, rather than
second-degree murder or a lesser charge, has doubled from under 10
percent when execution would result, to about 20 percent “now
they [juries] are not compelled to make life-and-death decisions.
15
PUBLIC OPINION WORLDWIDE
Support in the United States for executions is decreasing. Accord-
ing to Gallup polls, public support fell from 80 per cent in 1994 to
60 per cent in October 2013. In November 2012, California held a
plebiscite to decide whether the death penalty should be abolished
and replaced by life imprisonment without parole. It was defeated by
a margin of only 6 percentage points (53 percent to 47 percent).
The risk of innocent people being executed; the cost of obtaining a
conviction for capital murder, holding a prisoner on death row and
providing a lengthy appeals process;
16
and the rising use of the pri-
mary alternative—life in prison without the prospect of parole—are
all factors in the declining level of public support. The proportion of
supporters of capital punishment who say that they favour it because
of its deterrent eect has dropped remarkably in recent years.
A number of public opinion polls in the United States have shown
the same trend, but what of other retentionist nations? This section
14 Kevin Smith, ed., Kathryn Coleman, Simon Eder and Philip Hall, “Table 1.02: Oences initially
recorded as homicide by outcome, 1999/00 to 2009/10”, in Homicide, Firearm Oences and
Intimate Violence 2009-10, Home Oce Statistical Bulletin 01/11 (2011).
15 Mark Warren, The Death Penalty in Canada: Facts, Figures and Milestones (London, Amnesty
International, 2005).
16 A recent study of the cost of the death penalty inColoradoshowed that capital proceedings re-
quiresix timesmore days in court and take considerably longer to resolve than life-without-pa-
role cases. Justin Marceau and Hollis Whitson, “The cost of Colorado’s death penalty”,
Univer-
sity of Denver Criminal Law Review, vol. 3 (2013), pp. 145 . And a report of the California
Commission on the Fair Administration of Justicefound that the additional cost of conning
an inmate to death row—as compared to a maximum-security prison for a life-without-parole
sentence—is $90,000 per year per inmate. California Commission on the Fair Administration
of Justice,
Report and Recommendations on the Administration of the Death Penalty in California
(2008), available from www.ccfaj.org/documents/reports/dp/ocial/FINAL%20REPORT%20
DEATH%20PENALTY.pdf.
will look at surveys from Asia and the Caribbean, where governments
have claimed that public opinion would be hostile to abolition.
Japan
Statements from the judiciary and the executive in Japan justify retention
of capital punishment on the grounds that a democratic government
cannot ignore strong public support for it without endangering public
condence in, and support for, the law. In this, they draw on an o-
cial government survey on the death penalty that has been conducted
since 1956, approximately every ve years. In the most recent survey,
conducted in 2009, 86 percent of respondents favoured retention. In
2010 the minister of justice said that this high level of support should
be respected as an expression of “the voice of the people.
17
There is a great deal of secrecy around the death penalty in Japan.
Until 2007 the Japanese government did not announce the names of
prisoners and the crimes they had committed after executions. And as
a powerful Amnesty International report pointed out, death-sentenced
prisoners and their family members are not informed of execution
dates. The inmate is only informed of the execution a few hours before
it takes place.
18
What is more, there is still no ocial information on how and when
prisoners under sentence of death are selected for execution, how
they are treated on death row, or what the cost of the death penalty
is compared to life imprisonment. At the time of writing, Japan had
157 people on death row in solitary connement
19
—which is proba-
bly double the number at the turn of the millennium, as the number
of death sentences has risen. This kind of information is only available
informally through those who are involved in the execution process,
and through somewhat speculative secondary sources. The govern-
ment does not ensure the publication of accurate information on the
process or outcomes. This has led scholars to state that “the secrecy
17 Yomiuri newspaper, 2010, cited in Mai Sato, The Death Penalty in Japan: Will the Public Tolerate
Abolition? (Wiesbaden, Springer, 2014), p. 25.
18 Amnesty International,
“Will This Day Be My Last?” The Death Penalty in Japan (July 2006),
AI Index: ASA 22/006/2006.
19 Death Penalty Worldwide (updated 12 November 2013), available from www.deathpenaltyworld-
wide.org/country-search-post.cfm?country=Japan.
76 77
that surrounds capital punishment in Japan is taken to extremes not
seen in other nations” and that the public only has very abstract ideas
about the punishment.
20
This inevitably poses the question: on what
grounds does the public support the death penalty?
A recent study by Mai Sato argued that, although the Japanese asser-
tion that retaining capital punishment is a democratic obligation
may be theoretically coherent, it requires reliable evidence that the
public feel so strongly in favour of retaining the death penalty that
to abolish it would undermine the legitimacy of the criminal justice
system.
21
In other words, the Japanese government’s case is defensible
only if the surveys on which it relies accurately capture public atti-
tudes on the subject. Sato tested this through three rigorous surveys
of public opinion and found that the government’s interpretation of
its survey—and its contention that it reliably reected the views of
the public as a whole—was seriously awed. Her ndings suggest that
opposition to abolition is neither as strong nor as unalterable as the
government claims. With more information and greater transparency
about how the death penalty system works in practice, and reliable
evidence on whether the execution rate has any deterrent eect on
the murder rate, a more accurate sense of the Japanese public’s sup-
port for the death penalty would emerge. This suggests that retention
of the death penalty in Japan is not so central to popular trust in the
criminal justice system that abolition would result in the erosion of
political and judicial legitimacy.
Malaysia
In Malaysia, death is the mandatory penalty for murder, tracking
in certain amounts of narcotics, and discharging a rearm during the
commission of various crimes, even if no one is hurt. There is a grow-
ing debate on whether the mandatory death penalty should be replaced
by a discretionary system where it is used only in exceptional circum-
stances, or abolished altogether. In a recent public opinion survey of
1,535 Malaysian citizens on this issue,
22
a large majority said they were
20 David Johnson, “When the state kills in secret: capital punishment in Japan” Punishment and
Society, vol. 8, issue 3 (2006), pp. 251-285, at p. 251.
21 Mai Sato, The Death Penalty in Japan: Will the Public Tolerate Abolition? (Wiesbaden, Springer,
2014).
22 Roger Hood,
The Death Penalty in Malaysia (London, The Death Penalty Project, 2013).
in favour of the death penalty (either mandatory or discretionary): 91
percent for murder, 74-80 percent for drug tracking (depending
on the drug concerned), and 83 percent for rearms oences. Con-
cerning themandatorydeath penalty, 56 percent said they were in
favour of it for murder, but only 25-44 percent supported it for drug
tracking and 45 percent for rearms oences.
When asked what sentences they themselves would impose on a
series of hypothetical cases, all of which were subject to a mandatory
death sentence, respondents gave markedly dierent answers than
they had given to the more theoretical questions. For none of four
hypothetical drug tracking cases did more than 30 percent choose
the death penalty. Only 8 percent chose death for all the cases they
judged. Only 1.2 percent thought that the death penalty was the
appropriate punishment for all 12 hypothetical cases of murder, drug
tracking and rearms oences, showing decisively that the vast
majority favoured discretionary use of the death penalty.
These ndings suggest that there would be little public opposition
to abolition of the mandatory death penalty. Public support for the
death penalty for drug tracking and rearms oences, as well as for
murder, was not nearly as strong as had been assumed, so may not be
a denite barrier to complete abolition.
Trinidad
Another study recently surveyed 1,000 residents of Trinidad,
focusing on support for and use of the mandatory death penalty
for murder under current Trinidadian law.
23
It found that a large
majority of Trinidadians are in favour of the death penalty, but only
a minority (close to a quarter) favour it being mandatory for all
murders. Trinidadians also favoured discretionary use of the death
penalty in cases involving violent robbery or drug or gang killing,
preferring to take into account mitigating factors such as age and
previous good character. When faced with three murder scenarios,
only 1 in 5 survey respondents thought that the death penalty was
the appropriate punishment for all three crimes. The majority of
23 Roger Hood and Florence Seemungal, Public Opinion Survey on the Mandatory Death Penalty
in Trinidad (London: The Death Penalty Project, 2011).
78 79
those who favoured the death penalty in one of these scenarios
gave justice as the reason; only 1.3 per cent based their decision
primarily on deterrence.
The high level of support for the death penalty was contingent on it
being enforced with no possibility that an innocent person could be
executed. If this were proven to have happened, only 35 percent of
those interviewed said they would continue to support capital pun-
ishment—as was the case in Malaysia, where support fell to just 33
percent with the risk of an innocent person being executed.
China
The consensus among the
authorities in China is that
the public will not yet tol-
erate abolition. Thus, it is
argued that the attempts
now being made to reform
the death penalty, through
due process safeguards and progressive restriction of its application,
must proceed slowly and carefully, for fear of a public backlash and
collapse of condence in the government and the criminal justice
system. It is true that some judicial decisions not to impose the
death penalty are met with a urry of online criticism. But a recent
analysis
24
argued that the scholarly debate on the death penalty in
China often ignores contemporary survey evidence when claiming
that the strength of the Chinese public’s support for capital punish-
ment is a barrier to abolition, and that even liberal intellectuals who
favour reducing the use of the death penalty have tended to blame
popular support for harsh penalties for the slow pace of capital pun-
ishment reform.
The 2007-2009 survey referred to in that article demonstrated a
low level of interest and knowledge; a relatively high proportion of
24 Børge Bakken, “Capital punishment reform, public opinion, and penal elitism in the People’s
Republic of China”, in Confronting Capital Punishment in Asia: Human Rights, Politics,
and Public Opinion, R. Hood and S. Deva, eds. (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013),
pp. 187-204.
“…THERE MUST BE LIMITS
TO THE POWER THAT THE
STATE CAN BE PERMITTED
TO EXERCISE…”
Carolyn Hoyle and Roger Hood
respondents had no rm opinion on the subject of the death penal-
ty.
25
When asked whether they favoured or opposed the death penalty,
58 percent of almost 4,500 respondents in three provinces were de-
nitely in favour, not a very high proportion when compared with
the experience of European countries when they abolished capital
punishment. While only 14 percent said they opposed capital pun-
ishment, as many as 28 percent said they were unsure. When asked
whether China should speed up the process of abolishing the death
penalty, only 53 percent were opposed to doing so; 33 percent were
unsure. This hardly indicates the kind of fervent support for capital
punishment that would make abolition politically impossible.
Almost three-quarters of survey respondents said they were either
“not very interested” or “not interested at all” in the subject; only
1.3 percent said they had “a lot of knowledge, and less than a third
said they had “some knowledge” of the death penalty law and its
administration. Many were concerned about wrongful convictions,
and only a quarter said that they would support the death penalty if it
were proven that innocent people had been executed. Almost 70 per
cent thought that the death penalty was not equitably administered,
being more likely to be imposed on poor and powerless people than
on rich people, ocials or relatives of ocials.
When respondents were asked whether they would support the
death penalty if various alternatives were available, a substantially
lower proportion denitely opposed abolition. If the death penalty
were replaced by life imprisonment with the possibility of parole,
only 38 per cent said they would still favour the death penalty. If
the alternative maximum sentence was the harsh penalty of life with
no possibility of parole and an obligation to make restitution, less
than a quarter said they would oppose abolition, and half denitely
favoured it.
26
Meanwhile, a survey of a sample of 455 criminal jus-
tice professionals (including judges, prosecutors, police and legislative
and judicial administrative sta) in Wuhan found that 91 per cent
25 Dietrich Oberwittler and Shenghui Qi, Public Opinion on the Death Penalty in China: Results
from a General Population Survey Conducted in Three Provinces in 2007/09 (Freiburg, Max
Planck Institute, 2009).
26 Dietrich Oberwittler and Shenghui Qi, Public Opinion on the Death Penalty in China: Results
from a General Population Survey Conducted in Three Provinces in 2007-08, Research Survey on
the Death Penalty in China, 2007-9 (London, Great Britain-China Centre, 2009), p. 29.
80 81
favoured the death penalty, though for the more serious crimes, rather
than for nonviolent oences.
27
It seems likely that it is the intellectual, legal and administrative elites
that are slowing the pace of reform in China, not the masses, and it is
the legal practitioners and political leaders who need to embrace the
human rights objections to capital punishment.
DETERRENCE AND PUBLIC OPINION:
NO BARRIERS TO ABOLITION
The empirical research conducted over the past few decades demon-
strates that no matter what politicians argue or the public believe,
neither deterrence nor public opinion should be seen as barriers to
abolition. At the seminars and meetings that we have attended in
China, people who work within the criminal justice system often say
that the public will not tolerate abolition while the crime rate is high,
for fear it will lead to further rises in serious crimes, especially drug
tracking and corruption. The evidence on deterrence discussed
above suggests that this is not likely to be the case. Furthermore,
the public opinion studies we have reviewed for the forthcoming
fth edition of The Death Penalty suggest that there is no immutable
relationship between rising levels of homicide and increased support
for the death penalty. Much will depend on the extent to which cit-
izens believe in the general deterrent power of executions, their faith
in alternative punishments, and the ability of the political system to
tackle the roots of the problem through social reforms and a criminal
justice approach that increases the certainty, rather than the severity,
of punishment. In none of the countries that we have studied do the
data suggest that there would be disastrous consequences for public
order and respect for the law if the death penalty were abolished and
replaced by a (humane) sentence of life imprisonment.
The experience of nearly all abolitionist countries is that opinions
change and support for capital punishment withers as it comes to be
seen as a thing of the past. Analysis of support for the death penalty
27 R. Hood, “Introduction”, in Research Survey on the Death Penalty in China, 2007-9, available
from www.gbcc.org.uk/les/documents/dp2introduction.pdf.
across 17 countries
28
came to two interesting conclusions. First, it
found that “residence in a retentionist nation signicantly increases
the odds of an individual supporting the death penalty. This suggests
that people on the whole support what has been the norm in their
culture. Second, each year of abolition lowered the odds that an indi-
vidual would support the death penalty by 46 percent.
29
Clearly, as
the example of Europe shows, when the death penalty has been abol-
ished, more and more citizens come in time to regard it as a cruel and
outdated punishment. Abolition can lead to previously unimagined
changes in opinion by creating a dierent climate for the discourse on
the limits of state punishment. France provides an obvious example
of this. François Mitterrand stood for election in 1981 on a manifesto
that included abolition of the death penalty despite 63 percent of
the general public being in favour of it. He was elected president,
and after abolition he was re-elected. This showed that the public
was ready to accept leadership on this issue; subsequently, France has
become one of the leading nations to protest against capital punish-
ment around the world.
Opinions about capital punishment also dier in dierent sectors of
the population—which may be related to their social status, their
political or religious beliefs and how well they are informed about
the issue, including what the eects of abolition might be. Ultimately,
public opinion on the death penalty—essentially an expression of
supercial sentiment by the electorate, who may or (as is more usual)
may not be aware of all the facts and arguments relating to the issue—
should not be allowed to determine an issue which many, indeed now
the majority of countries, believe must be dealt with on the basis of a
principled interpretation of human rights.
CONCLUSION
Those governments that still favour capital punishment in principle
or believe that it is necessary pay insucient attention to human
rights protections, such as due process safeguards to reduce the
risk of executing those who are innocent or otherwise wrongly
28 Steven Stack, “Public opinion on the death penalty: analysis of individual-level data from 17
nations”, International Criminal Justice Review, vol. 14 (2004), pp. 69–98.
29 Ibid., pp. 87–88.
82 83
convicted. They may be presented with convincing evidence of
the abuses, discrimination, mistakes and inhumanity that inevitably
accompany capital punishment in practice—as have been revealed
by social scientists, legal theorists and human rights lawyers—but
they don’t tend to recognize the importance of such knowledge,
because their concern is with upholding state power and main-
taining social control, rather than with the rights of all citizens to
be protected from the state as far as their life, liberty and just and
humane treatment are concerned. They argue that the death penalty
is a general deterrent, not because the academic studies show this to
be the case, but because, despite the evidence to the contrary, they
believe it can be deduced from human nature.
But ultimately a human rights perspective must reject the utilitarian
justication that nothing less severe can act as a sucient deterrent
to those who contemplate committing capital crimes. This is not
only because the social science evidence does not support the case
for deterrence but also because those who care about human rights
would reject the deterrence rationale even if it could be proven.
Those retentionist countries that rely on the deterrent justication
should face the fact that if capital punishment were used to try to
obtain its maximum possible deterrent eect, it would have to be
enforced mandatorily, or at least with a high degree of probability,
on a substantial scale across most categories of homicide, and swiftly.
This would increase the probability of innocent or wrongfully con-
victed people, and people whose crimes had sucient mitigating
circumstances, being executed. As mentioned above, too-vigorous
enforcement may also backre, resulting in fewer convictions for
murder and thus a decline in the certainty of punishment on which
the deterrent theory relies.
One wonders, therefore, whether those states that do retain the death
penalty for some limited class of murders and murderers, imposed in
a somewhat haphazard and arbitrary way on only a few of those who
are death-eligible, can really claim that such a policy is justied by its
deterrent eects. Looked at this way, the balance of evidence clearly
favours the abolitionist position.
Furthermore, abolitionists who have embraced the view that all cit-
izens have a right to life argue that the issue cannot be left to public
opinion, not only because that opinion may not be fully informed as
to the consequences of capital punishment, but also because the appeal
to human rights is based on the protection of all citizens from cruel
and inhumane punishment, whatever crimes they may have commit-
ted. Some countries have attempted to stigmatise opposition to the
death penalty as a form of cultural imperialism, an attack on national
sovereignty and an attempt to turn a domestic criminal justice issue
into a human rights issue. This implies that if it is one it cannot also
be the other. In our opinion this is a false antithesis. Whatever system
of criminal justice a country may choose, there must be limits to the
power that the state can be permitted to exercise over people accused
and convicted of crimes, however serious: limits dened by universal
human rights principles that apply to all citizens of the world.
84 85
DETERRENCE AND THE DEATH
PENALTY IN INTERNATIONAL
PERSPECTIVE
Jerey Fagan
1
Many states that retain the death penalty do so with the belief that
executions deter the targeted crime. While some states execute
solely on the basis of retribution or a belief in a moral imperative
based on the harm of the crime, many others cling to the theory
that executions prevent further crimes by deterring other people
from committing them. Whether the death penalty is reserved for
murder or also applied to drug crimes or terrorism, belief in its
deterrent power remains deeply embedded in the social and polit-
ical culture in states that execute. Leaders in those states, as well as
large segments of their populations, endorse this view. But rarely
do those states or their citizens reect on the evidence that sup-
ports those beliefs or the theory that underpins them. Were they to
explore the deep body of empirical evidence and the core elements
of the theory itself, their belief in deterrence might well be shaken.
THE MEANING OF DETERRENCE
The core ambition of deterrence is to make threats credible to
the point where they inuence behavioural choices. In the case of
capital punishment, retentionist states wish to signal to those con-
templating murder, or any other death-penalty-eligible oense, that
there is a substantial risk of dying at the hands of the state if they
commit the crime and are caught and convicted. The premise is that
a would-be oender, knowing about the threat of execution, would
forego the act because the cost (death) is unacceptably high and
well in excess of any benets from the crime. It assumes a rational
actor whose risk-reward calculus would lead to the avoidance of a
capital crime and whose perceptions of risk are well calibrated to
1 Jerey Fagan is the Isidor and Seville Sulzbacher Professor of law at Columbia Law School, pro-
fessor of epidemiology at the Mailman School of Public Health, Columbia University, and senior
research scholar at Yale Law School.
the likelihood of execution. It also assumes that risks are substantial
and observable.
This proposition leaves many practical and empirical questions unan-
swered. How would we know about murders or other death-eligible
crimes that are contemplated but abandoned because of the threat of
the death penalty? How many murders have been averted, and how
many would have to be averted to show a deterrent eect? Is execu-
tion the reason for the abandonment of a capital crime? What about
other punishment threats, like death in prison through an irreversible
life sentence? What ratio of executions to capital crimes would pres-
ent evidence of deterrence? How many executions are needed to
signal a credible deterrent?
These questions are not simply policy matters, for they also give
weight to moral arguments about execution. Proponents of capital
punishment suggest that evidence of deterrence morally justies
execution.
2
States that fail to execute knowing that lives may be
saved through deterrence violate their moral requirements to pro-
tect people from serious harms including death. If there is a life-life
trade-o from execution, even if one life is saved for another taken
by execution, then by this argument, states are moral agents that are
required to impose capital punishment to save the lives of innocents,
regardless of any other consideration of the culpability of the accused;
the risks of wrongful execution of the innocent in this framework are
viewed as part of a “risk-risk” trade-o.
3
Much turns, then, on the evidence of deterrence. Not only are
there practical consequences of deterrence and execution, but state
legitimacy is also implicated by its obligation to protect and save
lives. Deterrence is a central justication for capital punishment in
many retentionist countries, and their use of execution is linked
to their state legitimacy.
4
Whatever moral reservations a state or its
agents may have about execution would, under this argument, be
2 Cass Sunstein and Adrian Vermeule, Is capital punishment morally justied? Acts, omissions and
life-life tradeos. 58 Stanford Law Review 703 (2005).
3 Cass Sunstein and Adrian Vermeule, “Is capital punishment morally justied?, at p. 705. The risks of
wrongful execution of the innocent in this framework are viewed as part of a “risk-risk” tradeo.
4 Roger Hood and Carolyn Hoyle, The Death Penalty in Worldwide Perspective (Oxford, UK, Oxford
University Press, 2014).
86 87
neutralized by the evidence of lives saved. The strength of this evi-
dence, then, carries weight beyond the practical and policy matter
of capital punishment. In this view, the moral legitimacy of the state
depends in part on its willingness to full its obligation to save lives.
Countries like Japan argue that popular support for capital punish-
ment, including cultural belief in its deterrent value, is reciprocally
tied to the legitimacy of the government itself.
5
But what if the evidence for deterrence is weak, speculative and incon-
clusive? Then this logic would be turned on its head. States that execute
in the face of uncertainty about execution’s deterrent eects are impli-
cated in taking lives without a measurable return beyond vengeance
or retribution. Those states then lose the moral grounding of life-life
trade-os, and in fact, create risks that reverse the statistical and moral
justication for taking lives. The deaths of people who are innocent, or
lacking in the requisite culpability for execution, become moral casu-
alties of execution. The costs to state legitimacy are potentially severe,
with the risk of spill-over eects such as deteriorating respect for the
law.
6
Much rides, then, on the evidence for deterrence.
THE EVIDENCE ON THE DEATH PENALTY’S
VALUE AS A DETERRENT
Whether the oense is murder, a drug-related crime or terrorism,
the scientic evidence for deterrence is unreliable, inconclusive and,
in many instances, simply wrong. This has been the conclusion across
a wide range of studies over ve decades. While there are no exper-
iments on execution, nor can there be for obvious moral and ethical
reasons, some studies have examined the eects of moratoria on cap-
ital punishment. Other studies have compared places that practice
capital punishment with carefully matched places that have abolished
or suspended executions and found no dierences in murder rates or
other capital-eligible crimes, regardless of the number of executions
in the retentionist places.
5 See for example Mai Sato, The Death Penalty in Japan: Will the Public Tolerate Abolition? (Wiesbaden,
Germany, Springer, 2014); David T. Johnson and Franklin E. Zimring, “Development without
abolition: Japan in the 21st century”, chapter 3 in The Next Frontier: National Development, Political
Change, and the Death Penalty in Asia (New York, Oxford University Press, 2009).
6 Sharon Dolovich, “Legitimate punishment in liberal democracy”, Bualo Criminal Law Review,
vol. 7 (2004), pp. 307-442
A. Murder
From 1972 to 1976, there was a moratorium on capital punishment
in the United States, inspired in part by growing doubts about its
deterrent eect on murder.
7
Executions resumed following publi-
cation of research claiming that the death penalty did in fact deter
homicides—in fact, that each execution deterred as many as eight
homicides.
8
But that evidence was strongly contested, and a 1978
panel of the National Academy of Sciences found little evidence that
claims of deterrence were accurate.
9
Still, belief in deterrence was
politically and culturally popular, even if scientic evidence didn’t
support it.
10
The belief in deterrence persisted for over two decades,
despite the fact that murder rates rose dramatically in the 1980s just
as executions were increasing.
Two factors undermined those beliefs. First, while the murder rate
began declining sharply in the second half of the 1990s, at the same
time that executions rose sharply, the decline in the murder rate con-
tinued after executions declined sharply in 2000. Second, a large body
of statistical evidence emerged showing that the claims of deterrence
advanced in the early 2000’s were deeply awed. My own research
showed that the decline in murders starting in 1996 was no greater
in states that continued to sentence and execute murderers than in
states that did not.
11
This included states with a formal moratorium
and states with a de facto moratorium such as California, Illinois and
Pennsylvania, which had large numbers of condemned prisoners but
almost no executions. In those places, despite the absence of execu-
tions, murder rates declined sharply.
7 Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 315 (1972) (Marshall, concurring).
8 Issac Ehrlich, The deterrent eect of capital punishment: A question of life and death”, The Ameri-
can Economic Review, vol. 65, pp. 397-417 (1975).
9 For a summary, see Brian A. Forst, “Capital punishment and deterrence: Conicting evidence”,
Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, vol. 74, pp. 927-942 (1983). See, also, Lawrence R.
Klein, Brian Forst, & Victor Filatov, “The Deterrent Eect of Capital Punishment: An Assessment
of the Estimates”, pp. 336-60 in Alfred Blumstein, Jacqueline Cohen and Daniel Nagin (eds),
Deterrence and Incapacitation: Estimating the Eects of Criminal Sanctions on Crime Rates. Washington,
DC: National Academy of Sciences (1978)
10 Samuel R. Gross, Public opinion on the death penalty: It’s getting personal”, Cornell Law Re-
view, vol. 83 (1998): pp. 1448-1479
11 Jerey Fagan, Franklin E. Zimring, and Amanda Geller. “Capital punishment and capital murder:
Market share and the deterrent eects of the death penalty. Texas Law Review, vol. 84 pp. 1751 -
2134 (2005).
88 89
A recent intensive review of the evidence on deterrence by the US
National Academy of Sciences in 2012 concluded that there was no
reliable evidence of deterrence based on its failure to once we con-
sider its deterrent eects beyond the eects of the next most severe
punishment, life in prison without the possibility of parole; other
research commissioned by the panel reached much the same conclu-
sion.
12
These analyses noted that there was no credible evidence of
deterrence, owing to the failure to establish, if not the impossibility
of establishing, the necessary conditions for making suciently strong
causal conclusions.
The panel’s ndings conrmed what was evident from observable
trends in the United States that showed no plausible evidence of
executions’ deterrent eect. Murders rose from 1985-1996, as states
ramped up executions. Figure 1 shows that murders have been
declining across the United States in retentionist, moratorium and
12 Daniel S. Nagin and John V. Pepper, eds., Deterrence and the Death Penalty (Washington, DC,
National Academy of Sciences, 2012); Aaron Chaln, Amelia M. Haviland, and Steven Raphael,
“What do panel studies tell us about a deterrent eect of capital punishment? A critique of the
literature”, Journal of Quantitative Criminology, vol. 29 (2013), 5-43.
Sources: Death Penalty Information Center, various years. Federal Bureau of Investigation, U.S. Department of Justice,
Uniform Crime Reports, various years.
abolitionist states since 1999, when executions reached their peak.
Starting that year, murder rates, death sentences and executions have
all declined at the same time and at the same pace. The homicide rate
in the United States has declined since 1996; death sentences peaked
in 1998, and executions in 1999. The murder rate throughout the
decade starting in 2000 and into the current decade was unaected
by the changes in the risk of a death sentence or execution.
Further evidence of the absence of deterrent eects from execution
can be seen in recent abolition events in several US states—Con-
necticut, Illinois, Maryland, New Jersey, New Mexico and New York.
These states allow comparisons of murder rates before and after the
cessation of the threat of execution.
13
Over the several years following
abolition in New Jersey in 2007, Illinois in 2011, and New Mexico
in 2009, there appears to be no evidence of an increase in murders
following the abolition of capital punishment. In fact, homicides in
Chicago, Illinois, reached a 50-year low in 2014, long after the last
execution in the late 1990s.
14
Evidence from other countries shows similar trends. Following the
abolition of capital punishment in eastern Europe in the early 1990s,
homicide rates declined.
15
Studies in Trinidad and Tobago showed no
change in homicide rates despite increases in executions.
16
Homi-
cide rates in Taiwan declined during a sharp reduction in executions
from 2005-2009. A study comparing Singapore, where executions
for murder have been common, with Hong Kong, where executions
were banned, showed no dierence in the murder rates over nearly
three decades since the cessation of executions in Hong Kong.
17
13 Death Penalty Information Center, “Recent legislative activity”, www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/
recent-legislative-activity.
14 Jeremy Gorner, Chicago ends 2014 with fewer homicides, but shooting victims up 14 percent,
Chicago Tribune, June 3, 2-15, at http://www.chicagotribune.com/news/ct-chicago-crime-
year-end-met-20150101-story.html. Total homicides in Chicago were the lowest since 1965.
15 United Nations Oce of Drugs and Crime, 2011 Global Study on Homicide: Trends, Contexts and
Data (Vienna, Austria, UNODC, 2011), p. 33. Homicide declined by 61% from 2000 to 2008 in
the Czech Republic, Hungary, Moldova, Poland, and Romania.
16 David Greenberg and Biko Agozino, “Executions, imprisonment, and crime in Trinidad and
Tobago”, British Journal of Criminology, vol. 52, no. 113 (2012). See, generally, Hood and Hoyle,
The Death Penalty in Worldwide Perspective, p. 389.
17 Franklin E. Zimring, Jerey Fagan, and David T. Johnson, “Executions, deterrence, and homicide:
a tale of two cities”, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, vol. 7 (2010), 1-29.
90 91
B. Drug crimes
The death penalty for drug smuggling is authorized in 33 coun-
tries, including the Palestinian Authority.
18
All but four of these
(Cuba, South Sudan, Sudan and the United States) are in Asia or the
MiddleEast. Executions overall are rare in those four. The United
States authorizes capital punishment for drug crimes only if commit-
ted in federal jurisdiction or charged under federal law, and then only
for high-volume drug importation. In some countries, the death sen-
tence is mandatory for drug tracking over a specied amount, yet
executions for drug crimes are uncommon.
19
There are no reliable
cross-national data on the number of executions for drug oenses,
although some recent multiple executions have shed light on the
practice across the world.
20
States that authorize executions for drug oenses invoke two ratio-
nales: that drug oenses fall under the international-law principle of
the “most serious crimes”
21
and that executions deter, and thus are
essential to controlling, drug crime. The deterrence rationale is based
on arguments that drug crimes cause numerous deaths, some arguing
that there are more drug-related deaths than deaths from murder or
other intentional killing. Accurate assessment of both claims—the
seriousness of drug crimes and the deterrent eect of the death pen-
alty—is essential.
18 Patrick Gallahue, The Death Penalty for Drug Oences: A Global Overview (London, UK, Harm
Reduction International, 2011). See also Hood and Hoyle, The Death Penalty in Worldwide
Perspective, 160.
19 Hood and Hoyle, The Death Penalty: A Worldwide Perspective, appendix 1. The nations with this
provision are China, Indonesia, Iran, Iraq, Malaysia, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia, Singapore, VietNam,
Yemen, and Thailand. In Singapore, the parliament passed the Misuse of Drugs Amendment Act,
which allowed for a discretionary sentence of life imprisonment plus caning to be substituted for
the mandatory death penalty if the defendant could prove that the tracker was a paid courier
and not a reseller, and with substantial cooperation in the prosecution of the major tracker
(Hood and Hoyle, The Death Penalty, 161, note 60).
20 Indonesia executed six people for drug oenses in January 2015 and another eight people in
April 2015. See, for example, Sara Kaplan and Sarah Larimer, “‘Bali Nine’ leaders executed by
ring squad in Indonesia”, Washington Post, 29 April 2015, available from www.washingtonpost.
com/news/morning-mix/wp/2015/04/28/bali-nine-leaders-in-indonesia-could-face-death-by-
ring-squad-wednesday/. In 2011, Amnesty International reported that Iran had executed 448
people for drug oenses. See Amnesty International, Addicted to Death: Executions for Drug Oences
(London, Amnesty International, 2011). Under Iran’s Anti-Narcotics Law, death is a mandatory
sentence for anyone found in possession of more than 5kg of hashish or opium or more than
30g of heroin, codeine, methadone, or morphine.
21 See for example William A. Schabas, The Abolition of the Death Penalty in International Law, 3rd ed.
(Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 373.
Consider the case of the Indonesian government, which has claimed, in
justication of its recent escalation of executions of drug trackers, that
illegal drugs caused 40-50 deaths per day and that 2.6% of its popula-
tion, or nearly 4.5 million people, used drugs.
22
In contrast, the World
Health Organization estimated that 1.5 million people in Indonesia
used any drugs.
23
The government numbers in Indonesia are disputed,
however, by local experts, who argued that there were aws in the
research design and a lack of transparency in disclosing the evidence.
24
The methods themselves are questionable: imprecise wording of survey
questions that confuses use with addiction, setting arbitrary thresholds
for assigning a respondent to the status of addict, relying on imprecise
wording to determine which users died because of drugs or how their
deaths were related to drugs, and failing to consider that tracking
itself is often a cause of death owing to the legal status of drugs.
25
Evidence for or against these claims is crucial not only to assess the
soundness of a government’s rationale for executing drug oenders,
but also to determine if drug problems are responsive to execu-
tions, in the manner of sound empirical research on deterrence
and murder.
26
In the matter of drug tracking, the causal claims
remain global, and a one-size-ts-all explanation is applied to all
drugs and a range of putative causal mechanisms. Governments
claiming that executions are necessary to deter drug crimes rarely
if ever dene the precise causal mechanism through which drugs
cause deaths, leaving open any one factor or combination of factors:
drug overdose, infectious disease transmitted via drug paraphernalia,
murder resulting from drug selling, adverse psychological reactions
to banned substances. It has not been established which if any of
these pathways is sensitive to the threat of execution, rendering the
search for deterrence a moot point.
22 Claudia Stoicescu, “Indonesia uses faulty stats on drug ‘crisis’ to justify death penalty”, The
Conversation, 4 February 2015, available from http://theconversation.com/indonesia-uses-faulty-
stats-on-drug-crisis-to-justify-death-penalty-36512.
23 World Health Organization, “Country prole: Indonesia”, Atlas of Substance Abuse Disorders, avail-
able from www.who.int%2Fsubstance_abuse%2Fpublications%2Fatlas_report%2Fproles%2Fin-
donesia.pdf.
24 Melissa Davey, “Data used by Indonesia to justify drug laws is ‘questionable’, say experts”, The
Guardian, 4 June 2015, citing a letter from health experts in Indonesia challenging the accuracy
of the government’s claims; Stoicescu, “Indonesia uses faulty stats”.
25 See for example Jerey Fagan, “Interactions among drugs, alcohol, and violence”, 72 Health
Aairs, vol. 72 (1993), pp. 65-79.
26 John J. Donohue III, “Empirical evaluation of law: the dream and the nightmare”, American Law
and Economic Review, vol. 17, no. 1 (spring 2015), doi:10.1093/aler/ahv007
.
92 93
No empirical research supports the claim that the threat of execution,
or even of a lengthy prison term, deters drug use or drug tracking.
27
The types of evidence that are available to test the deterrent eects of
executions on murder are not available to test deterrence of dierent
forms of drug oenses. The types of empirical tests themselves are
likely to dier. There are many reasons for this, but perhaps the most
important is that there is no reliable way to count or even estimate
the number of people who are involved in drug tracking.
28
We also
lack reliable evidence on the number of people using drugs, which
would be an indirect estimate of drug availability, or the elasticity
in drug prices under dierent forms of sanction threats.
29
There are
other challenges to research in this area, including the diversity of
drugs that are tracked and the dierences from one place to another
in the resources devoted to drug enforcement. Comparisons there-
fore are complicated.
Analyses of market dynamics in response to punishment actions pro-
vide an alternative to the direct measure of criminal activity. Economic
theory suggests that market dynamics and parameters will be sensitive
to executions, incarceration and other forms of harsh punishment.
30
Under a theory of deterrence, drug trackers would exact higher
prices for drugs owing to greater risk and scarcity under threats of
harsh punishment. Also, production and importation are likely to be
lower in places where the risks of punishment from drug tracking are
greater. Producers and trackers are likely to oset the greater risks of
punishment by increasing prices in places that execute drug oenders.
Also, if executions for drug crimes are a deterrent, availability of drugs
will decline over time as executions for drug crimes increase.
To see if drug prices or availability are higher in such countries, we
can compare both availability and prices for heroin, cocaine or other
27 David Skarbek, “Prisonomics: lessons from America’s mass incarceration”, 34 Economic Aairs, vol.
34 (2014), 411; John F. Pfa, “The durability of prison populations”, University of Chicago Legal
Forum 73 (2010), 73-116.
28 Carol V. Petrie, John V. Pepper, and Charles F. Manski, eds., Informing America’s Policy on Illegal
Drugs: What We Don’t Know Keeps Hurting Us (Washington, DC, National Academies Press, 2001).
29 See Jonathan P. Caulkins and Peter Reuter, “How drug enforcement aects drug prices, Crime
and Justice: A Review of Research, vol. 39, pp. 213-71 (2012). See, also, Stoicescu, “Indonesia uses
faulty stats”; Davey, “Data used by Indonesia”. As the critiques of the Indonesian studies suggest,
drug crimes and drug tracking are particularly dicult to measure, owing not only to the
inconsistencies in denitions or metrics but also to the inability of states to agree on the mecha-
nisms to generate these data. See Petrie et al., Informing America’s Policy on Illegal Drugs.
30 Jonathan P. Caulkins and Peter Reuter, id..
banned substances such as ecstasy (MDMA) with prices in nearby
similar countries that do not execute people convicted of drug traf-
cking. While many countries authorize the use of the death penalty
for drug oenses, only a few actually carry out executions. These
include China, Iran, Malaysia, Saudi Arabia, Singapore, Viet Nam and,
more recently, Indonesia.
Evidence suggests that executions do not appear to have a deterrent
eect in these countries or the surrounding regions. Instead, there has
been a steady increase in drug seizures over the past decade, a sign of
increased availability and tracking, even in the face of executions
in the countries that are nearest to the producing areas and supply
routes. Data from the 2012 U.N. World Drug Report show that in
the regions where drug executions are most frequent, availability (as
indicated by drug seizures) has either remained stable or increased
compared to the previous reporting period.
31
For example, prices in
31 United Nations Oce on Drugs and Crime, World Drug Report, 2012, available at http://www.
unodc.org/unodc/data-and-analysis/WDR-2012.html
No data available for previous year
Islamic Rep. of
Iran
35.24
Turkey
12.7
China
5.4
West & Central Europe
5.8
Pakistan
10.3
United States of America
3.5
Russian Federation
2.6
Colombia
1.7
Uzbekistan
1.0
Ecuador
0.9
India
0.8
Australia
0.5
Mexico
0.4
Kazakhstan
0.3
0.3
Viet Nam
Malaysia
0.3
North Africa
0.2
Central America
0.2
East Africa
0.2
Kyrgyzstan
0.2
Sri Lanka
0.1
0.1
Thaliand
Canada
0.1
Myanmar
0.1
Lao People’s Dem. Rep.
0.08
Hong Kong, China
0.07
Belarus
0.04
Venezuela (Bolivarian
Republic of)
0.05
Caribbean
0.03
Singapore
0.05
Indonesia
0.03
Macau, China
0.01
* Seizures as reported (no adjustments made for purity)
Source: UNODC Annual Reports Questionnaires data supplemented by other sources
Note: The boundaries and names shown and the designations used on this map do not imply official endorsement or acceptance by the United Nations.
Dashed lines represent undetermined boundaries. Dotted line represents approximately the Line of Control in Jammu and Kashmir agreed upon by India and Pakistan. The final status of Jammu and Kashmir has not yet been agreed upon by the parties.
Final boundary between the Republic of Sudan and the Republic of South Sudan has not yet been determined.
Increase (>10%)
Stable (+/- 10%)
Decrease (>10%)
Seizures in 2010
Weight in tons
Trend 2009-2010
Heroin and morphine seizures reported
to UNODC (2006-2010)
Seizures of heroin and morphine, 2010 (countries and territories reporting seizures* of more than 10 kg)
No heroin and morphine seizures reported
to UNODC (2006-2010)
Tajikistan
1.0
West and Central Africa
0.2
Bangladesh
0.1
Taiwan province of China
0.07
Southeast Europe
(excl. Turkey)
0.68
Afghanistan
14.1
Turkmenistan
0.1
Israel
0.5
United Arab Emirates
0.2
Saudi Arabia
0.06
Syrian Arab Republic
0.05
Source: UNODC annual report questionnaires data supplemented by other sources.
Note: The boundaries and names shown and the designations used on this map do not imply ocial endorsement or
acceptance by the United Nations. Final boundary between the Republic of Sudan and the Republic of South Sudan
has not yet been determined.
MAP: Global seizures of heroin and morphine, 2010 (countries and territories
reporting seizures* of more than 100kg)
94 95
China, Malaysia, Thailand and VietNam have either remained stable
or increased as executions have been carried out.
Again, deterrence would predict that a strong risk of punishment,
including death, associated with drug tracking would result in
higher prices to compensate for those risks. In other words, a traf-
cker facing the risk of execution would be likely to charge more
for the commodity than a tracker whose risks are lower, in turn
lowering the amount of drugs imported and available for seizure.
Without a deterrent threat, drugs presumably would ood a market
and prices would be driven down. This is simple economic theory
that applies for many commodities, based on scarcity and the costs
of producing and distributing the banned product. Yet, current data
from the 2012 U.N. Report on Drugs and Crime suggest that even
in the face of the threat of execution, seizures remain high, suggesting
an uninterrupted ow of drugs.
32
Overall, the lessons of execution for drug oenses are lost on a person
who is involved in drug tracking. Research in the United States has
shown that even the prospect of the harshest punishments, including
death, have no deterrent eect. Drug oenders are strongly motivated
by both economic interests and the personal thrills of their lifestyle,
and the exaggerated value of these rewards colours their risk-reward
calculations.
33
They see the risk of detection and punishment as
remote and the rewards of drug oenses as well worth any price.
Were there a deterrent eect, drug prices would be higher in places
that more frequently execute drug oenders. There is no evidence
that this is the case. Drug prices appear to be disconnected from pun-
ishment risks, including the risks of execution. Moreover, imprisoned
or executed trackers are often quickly replaced in a market that is
deeply integrated at a macro level into both national and regional
economies.
34
32 United Nations Oce on Drugs and Crime, World Drug Report, 2012, pp. 27-32.
33 Patricia A. Adler, Wheeling and Dealing: An Ethnography of an Upper-Level Drug Dealing and Smug-
gling Community (New York, Columbia University Press, 1993); Volkan Topalli, Richard Wright,
and Robert Fornango, “Drug dealers, robbery and retaliation, vulnerability, deterrence and the
contagion of violence”, British Journal of Criminology, vol. 42 (2002), 337-351.
34 Thomas Fuller, “Prots of drug trade drive economic boom in Myanmar”, New York Times, 6 June
2015.
C. Terrorism
Assessing the likelihood that the death penalty would deter terrorism
presents additional empirical and theoretical challenges.
35
First, the
data on deterrence and terrorism present many of the same challenges
as the data on deterrence and drug crimes. Dening terrorism in a
way that facilitates reliable cross-national comparisons is the major
challenge, and it is multiplied by the diculty of obtaining precise esti-
mates at the national level.
36
For example, recent estimates of terrorist
activity in the U.S. since the September 11, 2001 domestic attacks
include incidents of deadly force, property destruction, and “material
support” for terrorist organizations operating internationally.
37
In the case of terrorism, execution can be a perverse incentive.
38
The
logic of deterrence rests on the assumption that criminals are rational
and act in their own self-interest, and that their goals are elastic and
sensitive to both cost and reward. For most people, death by execution
would be a fate worth avoiding. But many terrorists view execution
as a form of principle or martyrdom. For those who commit acts of
terrorism motivated by religious beliefs, execution oers martyrdom
and rewards in the afterlife. Thus, executions of terrorists could well
inspire rather than deter terrorist violence.
For terrorists and other criminals, a lifetime of incarceration and
deprivation can be a far harsher punishment than execution in the
spotlight of public and political attention. British philosopher John
Stuart Mill characterized a life sentence as a “living tomb”:
What comparison can there really be . . . between con-
signing a man to the short pang of a rapid death, and
immuring him in a living tomb, there to linger out what
35 Bruno S. Frey and Simon Luechinger, “How to ght terrorism: alternatives to deterrence”,
Defence and Peace Economics, vol. 14 (2003), pp. 237-249.
36 Gary LaFree, Nancy A. Morris, and Laura Dugan, “Cross-national patterns of terrorism compar-
ing trajectories for total, attributed and fatal attacks, 1970-2006”, British Journal of Criminology,
vol. 50 (2010), pp. 622-649.
37 Scott Shane, “Homegrown radicals more deadly than Jihadis in the U.S.”, New York Times. June
24, 2015, at http://securitydata.newamerica.net/extremists/deadly-attacks.html
38 For example, Laura Dugan and Erica Chenoweth, in “Moving beyond deterrence: the eective-
ness of raising the expected utility of abstaining from terrorism in Israel” (American Sociological
Review, vol. 77 [2012], pp. 597-624), argued that increasing the rewards for abstaining from ter-
rorism may discourage terrorist acts more than raising the likelihood and severity of punishment.
96 97
may be a long life in the hardest and most monotonous toil,
without any of its alleviation or rewards—disbarred from
all pleasant sights and sounds, and cut o from all earthly
hope…….?”
39
Decades later, a committee of the British Parliament concluded in
1930 that the relative physical and psychological pains of execu-
tion are far preferable to the slow decay of body and spirit of life
imprisonment:
“A further alternative is to lengthen the sentence
to the limit of life itself. . . . This is a death sentence
where the inevitable end is reached by the imper-
ceptible stages of institutional decay instead of by
one full stroke.
40
RETHINKING THE THEORY OF DETERRENCE
The logic of deterrence rests on the principle that persons people
committing these crimes have motivations that inuence their consid-
eration of the possibility of death as a consequence of their act. There is
strong and consistent social science evidence that persons contemplat-
ing murder tend to heavily undervalue the risks of punishment. They
regard punishment as a distant possibility, and not one to be taken seri-
ously.
41
In some instances, the rewards and gratication from murder
outweigh any risks of death, or even the certainty of death itself.
42
Even in places with frequent and well-publicized executions, there
is no scientic evidence that executions deter homicides marginally
more than do lengthy incarceration prison sentences.
43
39 John Stuart Mill, Collected Works, vol. 28 (London, Routledge, 1868), pp. 266-272.
40 Sir Alexander Paterson, Report of the Committee on Capital Punishment (1930), pp. 484-487.
41 See, for example, Kenneth Polk, When Men Kill: Scenarios of Masculine Violence (New York, Cam-
bridge University Press, 1994).
42 This can be observed both in the high number of people who commit suicide after killing
before being arrested by police, and also in the acts of terrorism that result in certain death by
the attacker. See, Scott Eliason, “Murder-suicide: a review of the recent literature”, Journal of the
American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online, vol. 37 (2009): 371-376.
43 Randi Hjalmarsson, “Does capital punishment have a ‘local’ deterrent eect on homicides?”
American Law and Economics Review, vol. 11 (2009), pp. 310-334.
A recent review of the empirical research on deterrence
44
, concluded
that three preconditions of decision-making by criminal oenders
are necessary for deterrence to be eective:
1. Knowledge—Do oenders know and understand the impli-
cations of the law? Do they know which actions are criminalized
and what will mitigate their culpability?
2. Rationality—If so, will they allow that understanding to
determine their conduct?
3. Perceived net cost—If so, are they likely to choose com-
pliance as the more benecial option? Is the punishment worth
avoiding? This in turn requires assessment of three concurrent
probabilities: (a) the probability of being caught and convicted,
(b) the likely severity of a sentence, and the marginal increases in
severity for each level of punishment, and (c) the delay in reaching
the nal stage of the most severe punishment.
The third precondition raises the most dicult challenges: assuming
rationality in both perception and weighing of risks associated spe-
cically with execution. In most instances, the risks are remote: Few
murderers are caught, even fewer sentenced to death, and still fewer
actually executed.
45
In the case of drug tracking, its apparent high
volume suggests that perceptions of risk are realistically low.
For both murderers and drug trackers, with detection and punish-
ment uncertain if not unlikely, and with the payos of drug tracking
well exceeding conventional returns, the net cost hurdle is likely to
defeat deterrence. Empirical research has shown that the calculus drug
oenders apply in their decision making renders deterrence simply
a component of their task to be managed and avoided. But it hardly
changes how net costs are evaluated.
There also are personal rewards that alter the rationality of decision
making. Economic necessity, emotional rewards and other non-rational
44 Paul Robinson and John Darley, “Does the criminal law deter?” Oxford Journal of Law, 24 (2004),
p. 173.
45 See, for example, Scott Phillips and Alena Simon, “Is the modern American death penalty a fatal
lottery? Texas as a conservative test”, Laws, vol. 3 (2014), pp. 85-105, doi:10.3390/laws3010085.
98 99
considerations make severe
penalties unlikely to deter
many acts of murder, drug
tracking or terrorism.
Several ethnographic stud-
ies of decision making by
drug trackers have shown the remoteness of detection and punish-
ment in their thinking. Both in the United States and elsewhere, even
with the death penalty for major drug crimes, there is no evidence that
severe punishments—either death or life in prison without parole—
have aected the price, availability or demand for drugs. Even when
there is a small probability of detection and punishment, these factors
are diminished in the calculus of deterrence among active oenders.
46
Risks tend to be underestimated and rewards inated by many crim-
inal oenders,
47
defeating the ability of deterrence to overcome the
“perceived net cost” hurdle of rational decision making.
IS THE DEATH PENALTY AN EFFECTIVE CRIME
CONTROL MEASURE?
Deterrence is an eective crime control measure for crimes such as tax
evasion, minor property crimes and vehicular oenses.
48
There also is
some evidence that rapid criminal justice responses to marital violence
can be an eective deterrent, but only for some types of oenders.
49
In
general, deterrent eects are weakest for the most serious crimes.
50
We
have no expectation that executions will deter homicides in the United
States, and limited evidence that they do so elsewhere.
46 For basic expressions of the principles of discounting and risk, see Daniel Kahneman and Amos
Tversky, “Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk”, Econometrica: Journal of the Econo-
metric Society, vol. 47, no. 2 (March 1979), pp. 263-291; Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman,
“Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty”, Journal of Risk and
Uncertainty, vol. 5 (1992), pp. 297-323. See, generally, Derek B. Cornish and Ronald V. Clarke,
eds., The Reasoning Criminal: Rational Choice Perspectives on Criminal Oending, 2nd ed. (New
Brunswick, New Jersey, Transaction Publishers, 2014).
47 See, for example, Taku Yokoyama and Taiki Takahashi, “Mathematical neurolaw of crime and
punishment: the qexponential punishment function, Applied Mathematics, vol. 4 (2013), pp. 1371-
1375, doi:10.4236/am.2013.410185; for a review, see Richard H. McAdams, Present Bias and
Criminal Law (John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics Working Paper No. 562, 2011).
48 Daniel Nagin, “Deterrence in the 21stcentury: a review of the evidence”, in Crime and Justice: An
Annual Review of Research, M. Tonry, ed. (Chicago, University of Chicago Press) (2014).
49 Christopher D. Maxwell, Joel H. Garner, and Jerey A. Fagan, “The preventive eects of arrest on
intimate partner violence: research, policy and theory”, Criminology & Public Policy, vol. 2 (2002),
pp. 51-80.
50 Nagin, “Deterrence in the 21stcentury”.
The conditions to establish deterrence for drug trackers would be
infeasible for most sovereign governments, for several reasons. First,
drug trackers are not easy to apprehend. In the countries that carry
out executions for drug oenses, the vast supply of drugs stands in
contrast to the few arrests that are made for drug tracking. Despite
the threat of execution, drugs remain available, large seizures occur
regularly, and few arrests are made. These arrests often are widely
publicized, partially establishing the conditions for deterrence, yet
there seem to be no measurable eects on the supply or price of
drugs in these countries.
Second, to increase the risks of apprehending and convicting drug
trackers, signicant investments in police and prosecution agencies
would be necessary above the current levels of investment, in turn
detracting from the enforcement of other crimes. Police eciency
would also have to improve markedly, the number of arrests for drug
oenses would have to increase signicantly, and corruption would
have to be eliminated. These reforms would strain legal institutions
and weaken other areas of public security. In addition, deterrence
requires eciency in conducting trials to reduce the time so that
drug oenses are temporally connected to arrests. Procedural rights
would be compromised under these conditions, challenging the
legitimacy of governments and courts. The central role of the drug
economy in some states also would pose a barrier to creating the
conditions necessary for deterrence, with institutional incentives o-
setting if not surpassing the demand for punishment and control of
drug tracking.
51
51 Fuller, “Prots of drug trade drive economic boom in Myanmar”.
“MANY TERRORISTS
VIEW EXECUTION AS A
FORM OF MARTYRDOM.
Jerey Fagan
100
“They took us to trial, and the evidence was the
Stephen King novels that I read, the music I listened
to and the clothes that I wore. They found us
guilty, and I was sentenced to death.
—Damien Echols
101
CHAPTER 3
DISCRIMINATION
This chapter contains articles by geographically diverse authors showing that,
all over the world, the death penalty disproportionately targets members of
marginalised groups. Discrimination can be based on various characteris-
tics—including racial, ethnic and cultural identity or mental disability—but
poverty almost always plays a role.
Damien Echols and Stephen Braga both describe the so-called West Memphis
Three murder case. He was one of the suspects and the only one sentenced to
death. Damien Echols writes about growing up in poverty and social isola-
tion, feeling dierent from other kids, and the comfort he received from the
books, music, and all-black clothes that others judged him for. At the age of
18, he was wrongfully convicted and sentenced to death. He describes the
horrors of death row and of life in the prison where he spent 18 years.
Stephen Braga, who was his lawyer during an advanced stage of the proceedings,
describes how, based on the West Memphis Three’s appearance and taste for
heavy-metal music, they were accused of being satanists, and how this, as well
as their inability to aord a better defence, led to a wrongful conviction. When
a documentary movie on the trial revealed its shortcomings, growing public
support for the West Memphis Three, including nancial donations, made it
possible to hire rst-rate lawyers on their behalf, and they won their freedom.
Stephen Bright, an academic, analyses the unequal application of the death
penalty in the United States. He nds that the likelihood of receiving the
death penalty relates not only to the crime committed but also to the social
and economic status of the accused. Almost all who are sentenced to death are
poor, and half are members of a racial minority; many did not have a proper
defence. Many have suered from a mental disability or were victims of
childhood abuse. Lawyers who were intoxicated or asleep during trial, were
absent during crucial testimony, did not know their client’s name, said nine
words during sentencing or missed the deadlines for appeals have contributed
to their clients’ convictions and ultimately their executions.
Usha Ramanathan, an activist, writes about poverty, women’s rights, ter-
rorism and the death penalty in her native India, where events such as the
2008 attack on Bombay and recent brutal crimes against women may have
Damien Echols, victim of wrongful conviction and death sentence, USA (West Memphis Three), exonerated after 18 years in prison, speaking at the United Nations Head-
quarters at OHCHR’s Global Panel “Moving away from the death penalty: Wrongful Convictions”, New York, 28 June 2013, © UN Photo/Evan Schneider
103102102
led to resurgence in support for the death penalty. She points to the dangers
that inamed public passions can pose to fair trials, as well as the way that
high-prole trials can further iname divisive emotions, and describes how
many women’s groups reject the notion that the death penalty should be
imposed in their name for the crime of rape.
Alice Mogwe, executive director of DITSHWANELO, the Botswana Centre
for Human Rights, examines the status of the death penalty in Botswana,
in the context of the African human rights architecture. The death penalty
remains on the books in Botswana and is mandatory for murder unless
there are extenuating circumstances. She examines the barriers faced by poor
people and members of ethnic and linguistic minorities in Botswana’s justice
system—including inadequate representation, lack of translation services in
this multilingual country and secrecy surrounding the clemency process—and
supports the call by the African Commission on Human and People’s Rights
for a moratorium on the death penalty.
Innocent Maja, a lawyer and a lecturer at the University of Zimbabwe, anal-
yses the extent to which Zimbabwe has implemented the United Nations
General Assembly resolution on the moratorium on the use of the death pen-
alty. Although there is no ocial moratorium, Zimbabwe has not carried out
an execution since 2004. The country’s 2013 Constitution severely limits the
circumstances in which a death penalty could be imposed, and there is currently
no death penalty law on the books that meets those criteria. But shortcomings
in the legal system—from the paucity of legal aid for indigent defendants to
appalling conditions for death-row prisoners—as well as the fact that Zimba-
bwe has paused and resumed executions before, call for a more nal and formal
end to the death penalty.
Arif Bulkan, an academic from Trinidad and Tobago, analyses the applica-
tion of the death penalty in the Commonwealth Caribbean. While the death
penalty has not been abolished there, its use has been limited by a series of
appeals-court rulings focusing on how it is carried out—for example, limiting
how long a prisoner can be kept on death row, making the pardons process more
accessible and transparent, enabling petitions to international treaty bodies, and
challenging mandatory sentencing. Despite these limits, severe problems in the
legal system—including failure to assess defendants’ mental and psychological
status, the poor quality of legal aid for indigent prisoners, and a low clearance
rate in murder investigations—combine to make the pattern of death sentences
that still do occur tragically arbitrary and useless as a deterrent.
THE TERRORS OF PRISON
FADE SLOWLY
Damien Echols
1
When I rst arrived on death row, the guards decided they were
going to welcome me to the neighbourhood. So they took me to
the part of the prison they call The Hole. It’s a very small, dark, lthy
place that’s in complete isolation. And for the next 18 days they beat
the hell out of me.They used to come in at about twelve or one
o’clock in the morning, and they would chain me to the bars of
the cell and beat me with nightsticks. They beat me so badly at one
point that I started to piss blood. I still wake up at night sometimes
dreaming that I’m pissing blood again.
They starved me. They tortured me.
Eventually word of what they were doing started to leak out into
the rest of the prison. Other prisoners started to hear about it. So
they went to a deacon from the Catholic Church, who used to
come to prison to bring Catholic inmates communion, and they
told him what was going on. And he went to the warden’s oce,
and he told the warden, “I know what you’re doing to this guy.
I know you’re killing him. And if it doesn’t stop, I’m going to
go public.
So that night they took me out of The Hole and put me back in a regular
prison cell. The other prisoners told me later that they had expected to
see me carried out in a body bag any day. And I think the only reason
they didn’t murder me is because they realized they were being watched.
When I was a kid my family was beyond dirt poor. When we nally
moved into a trailer park with running water and electricity, we
thought we were really moving up in the world. I used to take refuge
in books and music. Reading became a sanctuary for me. It allowed
me to escape the world I lived in for a little while.
1
Damien Echols spent 18 years on death row for a crime he did not commit.
104 105
I’d read Stephen King novels over and over and listen to bands like
Iron Maiden. I started dressing in black all the time because it was like
a security blanket for me. It made me feel a little safer in an unsafe and
scary world. I didn’t have many friends; in fact, my only real friend
was a skinny blonde kid with a mullet named Jason Baldwin, and
Jason was with me the night I was arrested.
Jason, my sister, my girlfriend
and I were sitting in the living
room watching movies when
the cops started hammering on
the door. And when I opened
the door, they were pointing
guns at me. They swarmed
into the house like ants. They
stampeded over everything and
pawed through every possession my family owned. They put Jason
and me in handcus, threw us into the backs of cop cars, and took
us to jail.
I spent all night in a cell about the size of a closet. I wasn’t allowed to
go to the bathroom, wasn’t given so much as a drink of water. Every so
often a cop would come in and ask me if I had anything to tell him, or
if I was ready to make my confession yet. This went on all night, until
the next day when we were given an arraignment hearing.
At this hearing the judge told me that I was being charged with
three counts of capital murder, accused of killing three children as
part of a satanic sacrice. He said someone had confessed, but he
refused to read the confession in the courtroom. Instead, I was put
in a broom closet somewhere in the back of the jail and given a
transcript of the confession.
I was only 18 years old, in complete shock and trauma, and suering
from sleep deprivation. My life had just been destroyed. But even so,
I could see that there was something wrong with that document. It
made no sense. It was like some sort of bizarre patchwork Franken-
stein thing that they had stitched together.
“NOTHING IN
THIS CONFESSION
MADE ANY SENSE
WHATSOEVER, BUT IT
DIDN’T MATTER TO
THEM.
Damien Echols
It turned out that they had picked up a mentally handicapped kid in
our neighbourhood and coerced him into making a confession, and
then he was led to implicate Jason and me. Nothing in this confession
made any sense whatsoever, but it didn’t matter to them. I was put in
a cell. I kept thinking,surely someone’s going step in and put a stop
to this. Surely, someone is going to rectify the situation. They can’t
put you on trial and prove you’ve done something you haven’t done.
It seemed to me that science would say that’s impossible.
But they did.
They took us to trial, and the evidence was the Stephen King novels
that I read, the music I listened to and the clothes that I wore. They
found us guilty, and I was sentenced to death—not once, not twice, but
three times. The judge read these death sentences in this really bored,
monotone voice, like it was just another day at the oce for him.
People asked me later, “What were you feeling when he was sentenc-
ing you to die?” It’s almost impossible to describe. If you’ve ever been
beaten, when you’re punched in the head, you don’t register pain. You
see a bright ash of light, hear a loud noise, and you’re completely
disoriented, youhaveno idea where you even are for a few minutes.
That’s what it was like when he was reading those death sentences; it
was like being repeatedly punched in the head.
They sent me to death row. I was in a cell for about a week before
I noticed a shadow on the wall. It was from a man who had already
been executed who was in the cell before I got there. He had stood
against the wall and traced around himself with a pencil really, really
lightly, and then lightly shaded it in. I didn’t even see it for about the
rst week—but after I saw it, I couldn’t un-see it. So for years I slept
on a dead man’s mattress,stared at a dead man’s shadow, and lived in
the cell with ghosts.
People led appeal after appeal on my behalf, all before the same
judge who sentenced me to death. He denied them all. Even when
new DNA evidence came in that excluded me and the other two
guys from the crime scene, the judge still said: “This is not enough.
106 107
Then we were allowed to appeal to the Arkansas Supreme Court, and
by that time public awareness and interest in the case had been build-
ing. There’d been documentaries, books, and countless newspaper
and magazine articles and TV shows. So the Arkansas Supreme Court
justices knew they were being watched. In the end, the only thing
they really cared about was winning the next election. So they ruled
that all of the new evidence would be heard, and the prosecutors
realized that meant there was going to be anothertrial.
So a deal was hammered out—an Alford Plea. What an Alford Plea
means is that I plead guilty, and I walk out of the courtroom, and I
can still publicly maintain my innocence, but I can’t sue the state.
People have asked me what I was thinking about the day that I went
into court knowing that I could very well go home that day. And the
truth is, I wasn’t thinking anything. By that time I was so tired and
beat down that all I wanted to do was rest. I was dying. My health was
deteriorating rapidly. I was losing my eyesight. I knew I wasn’t going
to make it much longer.
The prosecutor said that one of the factors in his making this deal
was the fact that the three of us together could have collectively sued
the state for $60 million. I knew they could have had me stabbed to
death for $50 any day of the week. It happens in prison all the time.
So I knew if I didn’t take that deal, one way or another I would never
live to see the outside of those prison walls. So I took it.
I’ve been out of prison now for almost two years. I lived in terror
every single day for the rst year or so, but it’s getting better. I’m still
scared sometimes,but I’m trying to ght my way through it. And I
know that I will eventually be free from fear and anxiety. I’ll do it, and
I’ll be free, because if there’s one thing that I learned from 18 years in
prison, it was how to ght.
DAMIEN ECHOLS AND THE WEST
MEMPHIS THREE CASE: A SEARCH
FOR MOTIVE RUN AMOK
Stephen L. Braga
1
On a beautiful spring afternoon in 1993, three young boys dis-
appeared from their neighbourhood in West Memphis, Arkansas,
around dinnertime. The next day their bodies were found, naked,
bound and in horric condition, submerged in a creek in the
woods. Fear and panic quickly swept through the community, along
with rumours about the murders, including that a satanic cult was
to blame.
Shortly thereafter, three local teenagers—Damien Echols, Jason Bald-
win and Jessie Misskelley—were charged with the murders. Echols’s
own lawyer called him the “weird” kid in town because of the way
he dressed and acted, which—along with his rst name—played
right into the sensational nature of the allegations. Agreements were
reached to lm the teenagers’ trials and surrounding circumstances
for a documentary, with defence lawyers, prosecutors and even the
victims’ families playing leading roles. Less than a year later, the three
teenagers were convicted in two separate trials. Baldwin and Misskel-
ley were sentenced to life in prison without the possibility of parole;
Echols was sentenced to death by lethal injection.
Questions arose almost immediately about the validity of the teen-
agers’ convictions. The evidence seemed thin, and the alleged motive
was almost impossible to believe. Public release of the documentary
Paradise Lost spread those questions worldwide. Journalists, research-
ers, supporters and new counsel for the three teenagers began to
re-examine every aspect of the case. What they found was deeply
disturbing at every level, but perhaps nothing was more troubling
than the facts surrounding the prosecution’s purported proof of the
alleged motive for the murders.
1 Stephen Braga is a professor at the University of Virginia School of Law and counsel for
Damien Echols, whose essay also appears in this volume.
108 109
As the United States Supreme Court has noted, “when identity is in
question, motive is key.
2
Identity was the issue in this case. There was
no question that the three young boys had been brutally murdered;
the only question was who did it. To convince the jury that the West
Memphis Three were the perpetrators of these crimes, the prosecu-
tors had to establish a motive for why they would kill three young
boys with whom they had no prior relationship.
The motive associated with the prosecution theory at trial was clearly
explained by prosecutor John Fogelman during his closing argument
to the jury:
That’s the only thing that matters, in relation to motive. The testi-
mony in this case was that these murders—when you take the crime
scene, the injuries to these kids, the testimony about the sucking of
blood—and do you remember there was testimony about that—in
the satanic areas that blood is a life force, there is a transference of
power from drinking of blood—when you take all of that together,
the evidence was that this murder had the trappings of an occult
murder. A satanic murder.
To establish this theory of motive, the prosecution used ques-
tionable science,awed forensic science and the testimony of a
prison informant, and played on the rampant fear and prejudice
in the community at the time. The jury bought it, hook, line
and sinker.
THE EXPERT TESTIMONY
The questionable science came in the form of testimony from Dale
Gris, a purported expert in satanic and occult behaviour. After the
trials, the institution from which Gris received his master’s and PhD
degrees (without ever attending a class or taking a test) was shut down
by the state of California. During his testimony, Gris conceded that
he had only previously worked on one criminal case involving an
alleged satanic motive, and that motive was not too hard to gure out
since a pentagram had been carved into the victim’s body.
2 House v. Bell, 547 U.S. 518, 540 (2006).
Given this background, it was hardly surprising that Gris’s tes-
timony about the West Memphis murders was a collection of
generalizations. According to Gris, the wearing of black clothing,
such as Damien favoured, was a sign of occult beliefs, as was listen-
ing to heavy metal bands like Led Zeppelin. The reading of books
about magic and horror, such as the Stephen King novels Damien
was fond of, was also a sign of an occult mindset, he said, as was
writing dark fantasy poetry. The fact that the murders happened on
the night of a full moon was yet another indicator of occult activity,
as was the location of the murders in a wooded area. In perhaps
the most outrageous aspect of his testimony, Gris responded to
the judge’s question about whether the fact that there were three
victims was relevant to his analysis by stating that it was because 666
was the number for the Devil and if that number was divided by
two the result was 333. Twenty years later, it is hard to do anything
but laugh at such ridiculous testimony, but at the time of Echols’s
trial it was deadly serious.
The only specics Gris relied on for his conclusions about the
murders were (1) forensic evidence that a knife was used to emascu-
late one victim and to create ritualistic patterned wounds on all three
victims, and (2) testimony by prison informant Michael Carson that
Jason Baldwin admitted details of the crime to him while they were
incarcerated together. Neither piece of evidence was accurate.
THE FLAWED FORENSICS
With great ourish during his closing argument, prosecutor John
Fogelman performed a demonstration with a large serrated knife and
a grapefruit in order to convince the jury that the knife had made the
allegedly serrated pattern wounds on the victims’ bodies. In his rebut-
tal closing argument, prosecutor Brent Davis added that the knife was
used in the genital mutilation of one of the victims. The knife had
been found in the lake behind Jason Baldwin’s home, which made it
all the more suspicious to the prosecutors and incriminating to the
jury. The prosecutors’ claims about the knife being used to inict the
victims’ injuries was based on the testimony of the state’s forensic
pathologist, Frank Peretti.
110 111
However, subsequent re-examination by several of the country’s lead-
ing forensic pathologists found Peretti’s testimony to be completely
wrong. Each of these experts, evaluating the evidence independently,
concluded that the injuries suered by the victims were caused by
post-mortem animal predation rather than by a knife. Thus, the inju-
ries with the alleged serrated-knife patterns and the emasculation of
one victim were caused by animals attacking the young boys’ bodies
in their watery grave, not by a knife used as part of a satanic ritual
killing. The unanimity of these experts is as striking as their ndings,
which leave no room for doubt that the forensic arguments used to
convict the West Memphis Three and to sentence Damien Echols to
death were wholly unfounded.
How could the state’s forensic pathologist have been so wrong? Per-
etti had failed the board examination for forensic pathologists twice,
yet Arkansas law permitted him to keep his state job. Arkansas law,
like that in many states, provided little funding for criminal defence
attorneys to hire their own experts in court-appointed criminal cases.
So the system enabled a weakly (if at all) qualied expert with the
imprimatur of a state title to impress the jury more than whatever the
defence could come up with on a limited budget.
Everyone recognizes that money can make a dierence in the eec-
tiveness of a criminal defence, but the West Memphis Three case
provides a particularly dramatic example of the human tragedy that
can result. At trial with limited resources, Damien Echols was unable
to eectively counter the state forensic pathologist’s evidence that
a knife had been used to commit the murders. After the trial, with
the nancing of numerous well-to-do supporters, Echols was able to
retain the world’s best forensic pathologists to testify, in unison, that
the state’s expert was completely wrong and that no knife had been
used in the crimes. The case for adequate defence funding in criminal
justice systems around the world could hardly be made more clear. It
can literally be a matter of life and death.
THE PRISON INFORMANT
In another of the trial’s dramatic moments, the prosecutors called
inmate Michael Carson to the stand to recount statements allegedly
made to him by Jason Baldwin about the murders while the two
men were briey incarcerated together. Carson said that Baldwin had
told him about sucking blood from a victim, which is what Gris
relied on for the blood-related element of his conclusion that the
crime had an occult aspect. Gris conceded on cross-examination
that if Michael Carson’s testimony was false, then there was no other
evidence in the case to connect Baldwin to the occult.
Although the jury accepted Carson’s testimony as credible, it too
turned out to be false on later re-examination. Prison informants
make notoriously unreliable witnesses, as Brandon Garrett’s landmark
book Convicting the Innocent makes clear.
3
Carson proved to be even
more unreliable than most. As Carson himself explained in the movie
West of Memphis,
4
he was a heavy drug user at the time of his testi-
mony, could not distinguish between reality and fantasy, and had no
idea what he was doing or why. To this day, Carson is not certain
whether Baldwin ever made the statements he testied about at trial,
and he has publicly apologized to Baldwin.
FEAR AND PREJUDICE
Like Salem, Massachusetts, during the witch hysteria of the late
1600s and New York City in the 1980s at the time of the Central
Park jogger’s brutal beating and rape (for which ve defendants were
wrongfully convicted), rural Arkansas was terried by the West Mem-
phis murders. Who could possibly have committed such unthinkably
heinous acts? Adding allegations of satanic activity with ritualistic
knife murders and the drinking of blood into the investigation of
these murders was like tossing a Molotov cocktail of prejudice into
the mix. Who could be impartial, dispassionate and analytical, who
would not be afraid in the face of such a panoply of evil? Due process
disappears when such fear and prejudice creep into the system to
warp people’s judgment.
Regrettably, fear and prejudice did not merely creep into the West
Memphis Three case—they were injected into the case by prosecutors
3 Brandon Garrett, Convicting the Innocent: Where Criminal Prosecutions Go Wrong (Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2011).
4 A my Berg (director),
West of Memphis (Sony Pictures Classics, 2012).
112 113
and law enforcement authorities. In West of Memphis, Steve Jones, an
Arkansas State Criminal Justice ocial who searched for and found
the victims’ bodies, recalled a pretrial conversation with prosecutor
Fogelman in which, in response to Jones’s inquiry, Fogelman told him
that the case was not satanic and was “just a murder. Unfortunately,
Jones told no one at the time about this.
During the subsequent trials, the
prosecutors used the satanic char-
acterization of the case whenever
and wherever they could. Such
appeals to jurors’ “passions and
prejudices” have long been out-
lawed precisely because of their
power to distract the jury from
an impartial evaluation of the evi-
dence and encourage an emotional
response to what they have heard. Yet those arguments were allowed
to be made in this case and proved damning.
Many other errors were committed during the trial. But on the basis
of the errors relating to motive alone, the defendants never had a
chance. In the juror’s minds, the weird kid with the bad attitude,
dressed in black, listening to violent metal music and reading coun-
terculture books, simply had to be the ringleader of these horrible
crimes—because it could not possibly have been a regular member
of the community. Or could it?
A FRESH LOOK AT MOTIVE
As part of the post-trial eorts to free the West Memphis Three,
the Echols defence team retained forensic proling expert John
Douglas, the former head of the FBI’s Behavioral Science Unit.
Douglas reviewed the crime without meeting any of the defen-
dants because he did not want personal relationships to play a
role in his analysis. Douglas could not have been more emphatic
in rejecting the prosecution’s theory that the crimes t a satan-
ic-murder pattern. As Douglas explained, in the early 1990s, the
FBI was ooded with claims of satanic crimes due to fears and
“TERRIBLE
TRAGEDIES
INVOLVING
SENSATIONAL
CRIMES TOO OFTEN
MAKE BAD LAW.
Stephen L. Braga
rumours running rampant at the time. According to Douglas, the
FBI examined all of them and found that none of them consti-
tuted satanic crimes. Rather, they were all attributable to more
traditional motives for criminal activity.
As Douglas saw it, the murders of which the West Memphis Three
were accused were also explainable by a far more typical motive and
were likely committed by someone who had a personal relationship
with one or more of the victims and whose actions were triggered
by some cause arising from that relationship. Yet in their rush to
judgment to solve this crime under the mistaken notion of a satanic
motive, the West Memphis police ignored a number of leads and sus-
pects which would have more naturally t into Douglas’s prole for
the killer or killers.
CONCLUSION
An old adage tells us that “hard cases make bad law. Terrible tragedies
involving sensational crimes too often make bad law as well. One
need look no further than this case, or that of the Central Park Five,
to see evidence of this, although there are many other examples as
well. When authorities use aggressive tactics to rush to judgment to
quell community fear in such notorious cases, and when those fearful
community members wind up serving as jurors reviewing evidence
of unspeakable horror, mistakes happen and wrongful convictions
result. Fortunately for the Central Park Five, New York had no death
penalty at the time of their wrongful convictions. Arkansas did have
the death penalty, and Damien Echols came within weeks of being
executed for a crime he did not commit.
The nality of the death penalty is its strongest point for those who
believe in it—and its weakest point for those who oppose it. After
watching a documentary on the Central Park Five, commentator
George Will summarized the conservative case against the death pen-
alty: “Its nality leaves no room for rectifying mistakes.
5
This is not
just a liberal Democratic issue. It is a social justice issue.
5 George Will, “‘Central Park Five’ tells of a gross miscarriage of justice”, Washington Post,
12 April 2013.
114 115
As an empirical matter, we must acknowledge that mistakes happen
in an imperfect criminal justice system run by fallible human beings.
Those mistakes include wrongful convictions imposing the death
penalty. For example, the work of the Innocence Project demon-
strates that 18 of the rst 300 prisoners exonerated after wrongful
convictions on the basis of scientically unimpeachable DNA evi-
dence had been on death row. Eighteen people might have been
executed even though they were demonstrably innocent. The case of
Damien Echols is yet another instance.
The best judicial system in the world cannot guarantee 100 percent
accuracy. The risk of inaccuracy creates the very real possibility that
an innocent man or woman might be executed. No civilized society,
operating under any modern notion of the rule of law, can condone
such a possibility. We likewise cannot ignore it. The only sensible and
just approach in the face of such facts is a worldwide moratorium on
the death penalty.
IMPOSITION OF THE DEATH
PENALTY UPON THE POOR,
RACIAL MINORITIES, THE
INTELLECTUALLY DISABLED
AND THE MENTALLY ILL
Stephen B. Bright
1
The death penalty is imposed in the United States upon the poorest,
most powerless, most marginalized people in the society. Virtually all
of the people selected for execution are poor, about half are members
of racial minorities, and the overwhelming majority were sentenced
to death for crimes against white victims. Many have a signicant
intellectual disability or suer from a severe mental illness. Many
others were the victims of brutal physical, sexual and psychological
abuse during childhood and lived on the margins of society before
their arrests. Some are innocent. They are subject to discretionary
decisions by law enforcement ocers, prosecutors, judges and jurors
that are often inuenced by racial prejudice. Because of their pov-
erty, they are often assigned lawyers who lack the skills, resources and
inclination to represent them capably in capital cases.
One does not need to look far for illustrative examples. As of this
writing, the state of Georgia plans to execute Warren Hill, an African
American man, despite the fact that he is intellectually disabled.
2
The United States Supreme Court has held that the Constitution
does not allow the execution of a person who is intellectually dis-
abled (once called “mentally retarded”),
3
but Georgia requires that a
person facing death prove intellectual disability beyond a reasonable
doubt. Although four experts testied at the hearing on the issue
that Hill was not intellectually disabled, they all later changed their
1 Stephen Bright is president and senior counsel of the Southern Center for Human Rights in
Atlanta, Georgia, and Harvey Karp visiting lecturer at Yale Law School.
2 It has been delayed in doing so while the state’s supreme court considered and rejected his
challenge to the secrecy of its lethal injection procedures.
Owens v. Hall, 758 S.E.2d 794
(Ga. 2014).
3
Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002) (using the term “mental retardation”).
116 117
opinions when they reviewed additional information about him. As
a result, all nine experts who have examined Hill have found that he
is intellectually disabled.
Nevertheless, the state and federal courts have held that they are pow-
erless to prevent a patently unconstitutional execution.
Before the Supreme Court held that the mentally retarded could not
be executed, a Florida court found that Freddie Lee Hall had been
“mentally retarded his entire life.
4
But after the Supreme Court’s
decision, the Florida courts held that he is not retarded and could be
executed because of an IQ score above 70.
5
However, the United States
Supreme Court held that Florida could not treat an IQ score above 70
as nal and conclusive and, instead, must consider other evidence of
intellectual disability. Other states have fashioned their own denitions
of intellectual disability. The Texas Court of Criminal Appeals held
that someone with the severe mental limitations of Lennie in John
Steinbeck’s Of Mice and Men (1973) would be exempt from the death
penalty, but not others who were diagnosed by psychologists as intel-
lectually disabled.
6
This denition allowed Texas to execute Marvin
Wilson in 2012, even though he had an IQ of 61, which is below the
rst percentile in human intelligence, sucked his thumb, and could not
tell the dierence between left and right.
7
Glenn Ford, a black man, was released in March 2014 after 30 years
on death row in Louisiana’s notorious Angola Prison for a crime he
did not commit.
8
As a result of his poverty, Ford was assigned two
lawyers to represent him at his capital trial. The lead attorney was
4 Hall v. Florida, 134 S.Ct. 1986, 1991 (2014).
5 Ibid.; Andrew Cohen, “Supreme Court case may stop states that still execute mentally disabled”,
The Atlantic, 28 February 2014, available from www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2014/02/
supreme-court-case-may-stop-states-that-still-execute-the-mentally-ill/283969/.
6
Ex parte Briseno, 135 S.W.3d 1, 6 (Tex. Crim. App. 2004).
7 Andrew Cohen, “Of mice and men: the execution of Marvin Wilson”, The Atlantic, 8 Aug
2012, available from www.theatlantic.com/national/archive/2012/08/of-mice-and-men-the-exe-
cution-of-marvin-wilson/260713/.
8 Andrew Cohen, “Freedom after 30 years on death row”, The Atlantic, 11 March 2014, available
from www.theatlantic.com/national/archive/2014/03/freedom-after-30-years-on-death-
row/284179/; Andrew Cohen, “Glenn Ford’s rst days of freedom after 30 years on death row”,
The Atlantic, 14 March 2014, available from www.theatlantic.com/national/archive/2014/03/
glenn-fords-rst-days-of-freedom-after-30-years-on-death-row/284396/; Andrew Cohen,
“The meaning of the exoneration of Glenn Ford”,
Brennan Center, 13 March 2014, www.
brennancenter.org/analysis/meaning-exoneration-glenn-ford.
an oil and gas lawyer who had never tried a case, criminal or civil,
before a jury. The second attorney had been out of law school for
only two years and worked at an insurance defence rm on slip-and-
fall cases. As often happens in capital cases, the prosecutors used their
peremptory strikes to keep blacks o the jury. Despite a very weak
case against him, Ford, virtually defenceless before an all-white jury,
was sentenced death.
Ford is just one of many people who were found guilty beyond a
reasonable doubt in capital and non-capital cases but were actually
not guilty at all. States have already executed innocent people—like
Carlos DeLuna and Cameron Todd Willingham in Texas
9
—and will
continue to do so as long as they have the death penalty.
Missouri executed John Middleton in July 2014, despite questions
about his guilt and his mental competence. United States Appeals Court
Judge Kermit Bye, dissenting from a decision vacating a stay granted
by a lower court, stated, “Missouri is positioned to execute a man who
may very well be incompetent. That fact simply cannot be denied or
overstated. But, for some reason, that fact has been ignored.
10
Florida
executed John Ferguson, a black man, who suered from schizophre-
nia, in 2013 even though he believed that he was the Prince of God
and that after execution, he would be resurrected and return to earth
in that capacity. The federal Court of Appeals in Atlanta treated this
as nothing more than an unusual religious belief:
While Ferguson’s thoughts about what happens after death
may seem extreme to many people, nearly every major
world religion—from Christianity to Zoroastrianism—
envisions some kind of continuation of life after death,
often including resurrection. Ferguson’s belief in his ultimate
corporeal resurrection may dier in degree, but it does
9 James S. Liebman, The Wrong Carlos: Anatomy of a Wrongful Execution (New York, Columbia
University Press, 2014); and “The wrong Carlos”, available from www3.law.columbia.edu/
hrlr/ltc/; David Grann, “Trial by re: did Texas execute an innocent man?”,
The New Yorker, 7
September 2009, available from www.newyorker.com/reporting/2009/09/07/090907fa_fact_
grann?printable=true.
10 Chris McDaniel, “After delays, Missouri carries out sixth execution this year”, St. Louis Public
Radio, 16 July 2014, available from http://news.stlpublicradio.org/post/after-delays-missou-
ri-carries-out-sixth-execution-year.
118 119
not necessarily dier in kind, from the beliefs of millions
of Americans.
11
The court warned against treating unusual religious beliefs as proof
of mental illness. But religious delusions and obsessions are frequent
manifestations of mental illness. This was just an eort by judges to
gloss over the fact that Florida and other states are executing people
who are out of touch with reality.
POVERTY AND POOR LAWYERING
Georgia plans to execute Robert Wayne Holsey, an African Amer-
ican, even though he was represented at his trial by a lawyer who
drank a quart of vodka every night of trial and was preparing to
be sued, criminally prosecuted, and disbarred for stealing client
funds.
12
Holsey’s other court-appointed lawyer had no experience in
defending capital cases and was given no direction by the alcoholic
lawyer in charge of the case except during trial, when she was told to
cross-examine an expert on DNA and give the closing argument at
the penalty phase.
13
The lawyers failed to present mitigating evidence
that might well have convinced the jury to impose life imprisonment
instead of death: Holsey was intellectually limited and as a child had
been “subjected to abuse so severe, so frequent, and so notorious that
his neighbours called his childhood home ‘the Torture Chamber.’”
14
Holsey was by no means the rst person sentenced to death at a
trial where he was represented by a drunken lawyer. Ronald Wayne
Frye, executed by North Carolina, was represented by a lawyer who
drank 12 shots of rum a day during the penalty phase of the trial.
15
And there are other cases of intoxicated lawyers, drug-addicted law-
yers, lawyers who referred to their clients with racial slurs in front
of the jury, lawyers who slept through testimony (three people were
11 Ferguson v. Secretary, 716 F.3d 1315, 1342 (11th Cir. 2013).
12 Marc Bookman, “This man is about to die because an alcoholic lawyer botched his case”,
Mother Jones, 22 April 2014, available from www.motherjones.com/politics/2014/04/alcohol-
ic-lawyer-botched-robert-wayne-holsey-death-penalty-trial?page=2.
13 Ibid.
14
Holsey v. Warden, 694 F.3d 1230, 1275 (11th Cir. 2012) (Barkett, J., dissenting).
15 Jerey Gettleman, “Execution ends debatable case”,
Los Angeles Times, 31 August 2001, avail-
able from http://articles.latimes.com/2001/aug/31/news/mn-40577.
sentenced to death in Houston at trials in which their lawyers slept
16
),
lawyers who were not in court when crucial witnesses testied, and
lawyers who did not even know their client’s names.
17
There are lawyers who never read their state’s death penalty statute,
lawyers who led one client’s brief in another client’s death penalty
appeal without changing the names, and lawyers who missed dead-
lines that cost their clients review of their cases.
James Fisher Jr. spent 261/2 years in the custody of Oklahoma—
most of it on death row—without ever having a fair and reliable
determination of his guilt. The lawyer assigned to represent him
tried his case and 24 others, including another capital murder case,
during September 1983.
18
The lawyer made no opening statement or
closing argument at either the guilt or sentencing phase and uttered
only nine words during the entire sentencing phase.
19
On appeal, the
Oklahoma Court of Criminal Appeals pronounced itself “deeply dis-
turbed by defence counsel’s lack of participation and advocacy during
the sentencing stage, but it was not disturbed enough to reverse the
conviction or sentence.
20
Nineteen years later, a United States Court of Appeals set aside
the conviction and death sentence, nding that Fisher’s lawyer was
16 Even though George McFarland’s lawyer was snoring, the presiding judge took no action,
saying, “The Constitution does not say that the lawyer has to be awake. John Makeig, “Asleep
on the job: slaying trial boring, lawyer said”,
Houston Chronicle, 14 August 1992, p. A35.
McFarland’s conviction and death sentence were twice upheld by the Texas Court of Criminal
Appeals.
Ex parte McFarland, 163 S.W.3d 743 (Tex. Crim. App. 2005); McFarland v. State, 928
S.W.2d 482 (Tex. Crim. App. 1996). Carl Johnson was executed even though his lawyer, Joe
Frank Cannon, slept during parts of trial. David Dow, “The state, the death penalty, and Carl
Johnson”,
Boston College Law Review, vol. 37, no. 4 (1 July 1996), pp. 691-711. Cannon also
slept during the trial of Calvin Burdine. The Texas Court of Criminal Appeals upheld the
conviction and sentence, but the federal court of appeals set aside the conviction, holding, over
a bitter dissent, that a sleeping lawyer is absent from trial and thus a denial of counsel.
Burdine v.
Johnson, 262 F.3d 336 (5th Cir. 2001) (en banc).
17 See Stephen B. Bright and Sia M. Sanneh, “Fifty years of deance and resistance after Gideon
v. Wainwright”,
Yale Law Journal, vol. 122, no. 8 (2013), pp. 2150-2174, available from www.
yalelawjournal.org/essay/fty-years-of-deance-and-resistance-after-gideon-v-wainwright;
Kenneth Williams, “Ensuring the capital defendant’s right to competent counsel: it’s time
for some standards!”,
Wayne Law Review, vol. 51 (2005), pp. 129-162; Jerey L. Kirchmeier,
“Drink, drugs, and drowsiness: the constitutional right to eective assistance of counsel and
the Strickland prejudice requirement”,
Nebraska Law Review, vol. 75 (1996), pp. 425, 455-462;
Bruce A. Green, “Lethal ction: the meaning of ‘counsel’ in the Sixth Amendment”, Iowa Law
Review, vol. 78 (1993), pp. 433 .
18
Fisher v. Gibson, 282 F.3d 1283, 1293 (10th Cir. 2002).
19 Ibid., p. 1289.
20
Fisher v. State, 739 P.2d 523, 525 (Okla.Crim.App.1987).
120 121
“grossly inept, had “sabotaged” Fisher’s defence by repeatedly reit-
erating the state’s version of events, and was disloyal by “exhibiting
actual doubt and hostility toward his client’s case.
21
The Court of
Appeals would not reach the same result today, because Congress
has severely restricted its power to review state court judgments and
grant habeas corpus relief.
22
Today, Fisher would probably be exe-
cuted. And Robert Holsey’s death sentence would almost certainly
have been set aside if the federal courts had considered his case before
the restrictions were adopted.
James Fisher was assigned another bad lawyer for his retrial in 2005.
The lawyer was drinking heavily, abusing cocaine and neglecting his
cases.
23
The lawyer phys-
ically threatened Fisher
at a pretrial hearing and,
as a result, Fisher refused
to attend his own trial.
24
He was again convicted
and sentenced to death,
but this time Oklahoma’s
highest criminal court
recognized the disgraceful incompetence of his lawyer and set the
conviction aside.
25
Prosecutors agreed to Fisher’s release in July 2010,
provided that he be banished from Oklahoma forever.
26
Juan Balderas was sentenced to death in Houston in March 2014.
He was represented by Jerome Godinich, an attorney who missed
the statute of limitations in two federal habeas corpus cases ve years
21 Ibid., pp. 1289, 1300, 1308.
22 The Antiterrorism and Eective Death Penalty Act, adopted in 1996, restricts federal review of
convictions and death sentences imposed in the state courts in many ways. Among its provisions
is one that provides that habeas relief may not be granted unless the state court’s decision
“was contrary to, or involved an unreasonable application of, clearly established Federal law, as
determined by the Supreme Court of the United States” 28 U.S.C. § 2254(d)(1) (2006). The
Supreme Court has held that a “state court’s determination that a claim lacks merit precludes
federal habeas relief so long as ‘fairminded jurists could disagree’ on the correctness of the
state court’s decision.
Harrington v. Richter, 131 S. Ct. 770, 786 (2011), quoting Yarborough v.
Alvarado, 541 U.S. 652, 664 (2004). The Court added in Richter: “If this standard is dicult to
meet, that is because it was meant to be” (ibid.).
23
Fisher v. State, 206 P.3d 607, 610-11 (Okla. Crim. App. 2009).
24 Ibid., p. 610.
25 Ibid., pp. 612-613.
26 Dan Barry, “In the rearview mirror, Oklahoma and death row”,
New York Times, 10 August
2010, available from www.nytimes.com/2010/08/11/us/11land.html.
“THE DEATH PENALTY
IS ONE OF AMERICA’S
MOST PROMINENT
VESTIGES OF SLAVERY
AND RACIAL OPPRESSION.
Stephen B. Bright
earlier, depriving his clients of any review of their cases by inde-
pendent, life-tenure federal judges.
27
Both clients were executed. Yet,
despite such gross malpractice, the Texas Bar took no action, nor did
the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals. The trial court judges in Hous-
ton continued appointing Godinich to defend poor people accused
of crimes, including in capital cases. He has been the lawyer in as
many as 350 criminal cases at one time.
Micah Brown was sentenced to death in May 2014, represented by
Toby Wilkinson, who led appellate briefs in two capital cases in 2006
that contained gibberish, repetitions, and rambling arguments. In one
case, Wilkinson clearly lifted passages from one of his previous cases so
that in places the brief discussed the wrong crime and used the wrong
names. In the other case, Wilkinson included portions of letters sent to
him by his client.
28
No matter how egregiously lawyers handle a capital
case, Texas judges keep appointing them to represent others.
Lawyers have missed the statute of limitations in at least seven other
cases in Texas. In 2014, the federal courts refused to consider an appeal
in the case of Louis Castro Perez, who was sentenced to death in Texas,
because his lawyer without telling Perez or other counsel on the case
did not le a notice of appeal.
29
One judge dissented, pointing out
that the lawyer’s failure to le a notice of appeal was “an egregious
breach of the duties an attorney owes her client” and that Perez had
made a strong showing that he may have been sentenced to death in
violation of the Constitution.
30
In Florida, lawyers assigned to represent
condemned inmates have missed the statute of limitations in 34 cases,
depriving their clients of any review of their cases by federal courts.
31
Many people are sentenced to death and executed in the United
States not because they committed the worst crimes, but because they
had the misfortune to be assigned the worst lawyers. Over 100 people
27 Lise Olsen, “Lawyers’ late lings can be deadly for inmates”, Houston Chronicle, 22 March
2009, available from www.chron.com/news/houston-texas/article/Slow-paperwork-in-death-
row-cases-ends-nal-1736308.php.
28 Maro Robbins, “Convict’s odds today may rest on gibberish”,
San Antonio Express-News, 24
August 2006.
29
Perez v. Stephens, 745 F.3d 174 (5th Cir. 2014).
30 Ibid., pp. 182, 187, 191-92 (Dennis, J., dissenting).
31
Lugo v. Secretary, 750 F.3d 1198, 1216-18, 1222-26 (11th Cir. 2014) (Martin, J., dissenting)
(listing the 34 cases).
122 123
sentenced to death in Houston, Harris County, Texas, have been exe-
cuted in the last 40 years. The reason is no secret: Harris County
judges appoint incompetent lawyers to represent people facing the
death penalty
32
and, after they are sentenced to death, the condemned
are assigned equally bad lawyers to represent them in post-conviction
proceedings. There is not even the pretence of fairness.
33
United States Supreme Court Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg has said, “I
have yet to see a death case, among the dozens coming to the Supreme
Court on eve of execution petitions, in which the defendant was well
represented at trial.
34
United States Circuit Judge Boyce Martin has
pointed out that defendants with “decent lawyers” often avoid death
sentences, while those assigned bad lawyers are sentenced to death.
35
It is disturbing how commonly courts and prosecutors are willing
to overlook the gross incompetence of counsel when it occurs, and
how doggedly they try to defend the death sentences that result.
Trial judges, who are elected in most states, are often the ones who
appointed the incompetent lawyers. And they appoint them in case
after case, as Texas judges have done with Jerome Godinich and
Toby Wilkinson. Prosecutors have no incentive to demand that their
courtroom adversaries be qualied and eective. The poor quality of
counsel in capital cases is well known, but very little, if anything, is
being done about it in many states.
32 For example, one lawyer repeatedly appointed by judges in Houston had 20 clients sentenced
to death due largely to his failure to “conduct even rudimentary investigations. Adam Liptak,
“A lawyer known best for losing capital cases”,
New York Times, 17 May 2010, available from
www.nytimes.com/2010/05/18/us/18bar.html?_r=0. Houston judges repeatedly appointed
Ron Mock, despite his poor performance in capital cases. Sara Rimer and Raymond Bonner,
“Texas lawyer’s death row record a concern”,
New York Times, 11 June 2000, available from
www.nytimes.com/2000/06/11/us/texas-lawyer-s-death-row-record-a-concern.html. Sixteen
people represented by Mock were sentenced to death. Andrew Tilghman, “State bar suspends
troubled local lawyer,
Houston Chronicle, 12 February 2005. Another favourite was Joe Frank
Cannon, who was known for trying cases like “greased lightning” and not always being able to
stay awake during trials; 10 people represented by Cannon were sentenced to death. Paul M.
Barrett, “Lawyer’s fast work on death cases raises doubts about the system”,
Wall Street Journal,
7 September 1994.
33 Stephen B. Bright, “Death in Texas: not even the pretense of fairness”,
The Champion, vol. 23
(July 1999), pp. 1-10, available from http://library.law.yale.edu/sites/default/les/death_in_tex-
as_champion_99.pdf; Stephen B. Bright, “Elected judges and the death penalty in Texas: why
full habeas corpus review by independent federal judges is indispensable to protecting consti-
tutional rights”,
Texas Law Review, vol. 78 (2000), pp. 1805-1837, available from http://library.
law.yale.edu/sites/default/les/electedjudges.pdf.
34 Ruth Bader Ginsburg, “In pursuit of the public good: lawyers who care”, lecture at the District
of Columbia School of Law, 9 April 2001, available from www.supremecourt.gov/publicinfo/
speeches/viewspeeches.aspx?Filename=sp_04-09-01a.html.
35
Moore v. Parker, 425 F.3d 250, 268 (6th Cir. 2005) (Martin, J., dissenting).
RACIAL DISCRIMINATION
The death penalty is one of America’s most prominent vestiges of
slavery and racial oppression.
36
It was essential to the institution of
slavery. Michigan abolished the death penalty in 1846, and other
northern states repealed their death statutes or restricted the use
of the death penalty before the Civil War. But that could not be
done in the South—in states that had a captive population. After
the Civil War, the death penalty continued to be imposed on Afri-
can Americans; some crimes were punishable by death depending
upon the race of the oender and the victim. Slavery was perpet-
uated through the system of convict leasing: Black people were
arrested on minor charges—such as loitering, not having proper
papers, or theft, and then leased to the railroads, coal mines and
turpentine camps.
37
Today, the courts remain the part of American society least aected by
the civil rights movement of the mid-20th century. Many courtrooms
in the South today look no dierent than they did in the 1950s. The
judge is white, the prosecutors are white, the court-appointed lawyers
are white, and, even in communities with substantial African Ameri-
can populations, the jury is often all white. It is well known and well
documented that a person of colour is more likely than a white person
to be stopped by police, to be abused during that stop, to be arrested
after the stop, to be denied bail when brought to court, and to receive
a severe sentence, whether it is jail instead of probation or the death
penalty instead of life imprisonment without the possibility of parole.
38
The two most important decisions made in every death penalty case are
made by prosecutors: whether to seek the death penalty and whether to
36 See Stephen B. Bright, “Discrimination, death and denial: the tolerance of racial discrimination
in the iniction of the death penalty”, Santa Clara Law Review, vol. 35 (1995), pp. 433-483,
available from http://library.law.yale.edu/sites/default/les/discrimination_death.pdf.
37 Douglas A. Blackmon’s
Slavery by Another Name: The Re-Enslavement of Black Americans from
the Civil War to World War II (New York, Doubleday, 2008) describes how slavery was perpetuated
until World War II in Alabama through convict leasing; David M. Oshinsky’s, Worse than Slavery:
Parchman Farm and the Ordeal of Jim Crow Justice (New York, Free Press, 1996) describes convict
leasing in Mississippi and other southern states.
38 See, for example, Amy E. Lerman and Vesla M. Weaver, Arresting Citizenship: The Democratic
Consequences of American Crime Control (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 2014); Cynthia
E. Jones, “‘Give us free’: addressing racial disparities in bail determinations”, New York University
Journal of Legislation and Public Policy, vol. 16 (2013), pp. 919 ; Michelle Alexander, The New
Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness (New York, Free Press, 2010).
124 125
resolve the case through a plea bargain for a sentence less than death. Those
decisions are often inuenced by race. Some people who are intellectually
disabled or mentally ill reject plea oers with little or no understanding of
what they are doing and are later sentenced to death at trial.
Prosecutors continue to use their discretionary strikes to prevent or
minimize the participation of members of racial minorities on juries.
A Supreme Court decision purportedly preventing such discrimina-
tion by requiring prosecutors to give race-neutral reasons for their
strikes is widely regarded as a farce. After calling the process a “cha-
rade, one court described it as follows: “The State may provide the
trial court with a series of pat race-neutral reasons . . . . [W]e wonder
if the reasons can be given without a smile. Surely, new prosecutors
are given a manual, probably entitled, ‘Handy Race-Neutral Expla-
nations’ or ‘20 Time-Tested Race-Neutral Explanations.’”
39
And,
indeed, just such a “cheat sheet” of pat race-neutral reasons to justify
the strike of any minority jury member came to light in North Car-
olina. A one-page handout titled “Batson Justications: Articulating
Juror Negatives” containing a list of reasons a prosecutor could give
for strikes of minorities was distributed at the Conference of District
Attorneys’ statewide trial advocacy course called “Top Gun II.
40
A
North Carolina court found that a prosecutor had used reasons from
the list to justify striking African Americans in four capital cases.
41
The court also found that in capital cases in North Carolina, “pros-
ecutors strike African Americans at double the rate they strike other
potential jurors.
42
The probability of such a disparity occurring in a
race-neutral process is less than one in ten trillion.
43
The court found
a history of “resistance” by prosecutors “to permit greater participa-
tion on juries by African Americans. It continued:
39 People v. Randall, 671 N.E.2d 60, 65 (Ill. App. 1996). A judge discusses the reluctance of judges
to nd that prosecutors intentionally discriminated and then lied about it by giving pretextual
reasons for their strikes—the nding the Supreme Court requires to prohibit a strike motivated
by race—in Mark W. Bennett, “Unraveling the Gordian knot of implicit bias in jury selection:
the problems of judge-dominated voir dire, the failed promise of Batson, and proposed solu-
tions”,
Harvard Law & Policy Review, vol. 4 (2010), pp. 149 .
40
State v. Golpin, Cumberland Co., NC, Superior Nos. 97 CRS 42314-15, 98 CRS 34832,
35044, 01 CRS 65079, at 73-74, ¶¶ 68-72 (Dec. 13, 2012), available from https://www.aclu.
org/les/assets/rja_order_12-13-12.pdf.
41 Ibid., pp. 74-77, ¶¶ 72-79.
42 Ibid., pp. 112-201, ¶¶ 171-393. The Court found that prosecutors statewide struck 52.8 per
cent of eligible black venire members and 25.7 per cent of all other eligible venire members.
Ibid., p. 153, ¶ 254.
43 Ibid.
That resistance is exemplied by trainings sponsored by the North
Carolina Conference of District Attorneys where prosecutors learned
not to examine their own prejudices and present persuasive cases to a
diverse cast of jurors, but to circumvent the constitutional prohibition
against race discrimination in jury selection.
44
The Supreme Court has held that states must minimize the risk of
race coming into play in the decisions that lead to imposition of the
death penalty.
45
But this raises the question of how much racial bias is
acceptable in the process through which courts condemn people to
die. With the long history of slavery, lynchings, convict leasing, segre-
gation, racial oppression and now mass incarceration that has a much
greater impact on racial minorities, surely states should eliminate any
chance that racial prejudice might play a role. But there is only one
way to do that: by eliminating the death penalty.
DEATH FOR PEOPLE WITH INTELLECTUAL
LIMITATIONS AND MENTAL ILLNESSES
There are other equally troubling questions. How much uncertainty
is acceptable with regard to executing people of low intelligence and
people who are mentally ill? Are juries able to measure precisely the
degree of culpability of an intellectually disabled person? Are they
able to discern whether people are so intellectually disabled (or
“mentally retarded”) that they are exempt from the death penalty,
46
or not quite intellectually disabled enough, so that it is acceptable to
execute them? Is a jury capable of determining whether profoundly
mentally ill people are so impaired that their culpability is reduced,
so that they should be spared the death penalty, or so dangerous that
they should be executed?
Dierent people on dierent juries make those decisions, but it is
impossible for them to make them consistently or to know which
ones are reaching the right conclusions. Intellectual disability cannot
be precisely measured. Psychiatrists and psychologists do not fully
44 Ibid., pp. 4-5.
45
McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279 (1987); Turner v. Murray, 476 U.S. 28, 37 (1986).
46
Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002) (holding that execution of the intellectually disabled,
then called the “mentally retarded, violates the Eighth Amendment).
126 127
understand mental illness and often disagree with regard to its exis-
tence, severity and inuence on behaviour. Capital cases are often
inuenced by the passions and prejudices of the moment, which dis-
tort the decision-making process.
As a result, there are many intellectually disabled and mentally ill
people on death rows throughout the country. Among them is
Andre Lee Thomas, sentenced to death in Texas. He suers from schizo-
phrenia and psychotic delusions and has gouged out both his eyes.
After engaging in bizarre behaviour and attempting suicide, Thomas
stabbed and killed his wife and two children, acting upon a voice
that he thought was God’s telling him that he needed to kill them
using three dierent knives so as not to “cross contaminate” their
blood and “allow the demons inside them to live. He used a dif-
ferent knife on each one and carved out the children’s hearts and
part of his wife’s lung, which he had mistaken for her heart, and
stued them into his pockets. He then stabbed himself in the heart
which, he thought, would assure the death of the demons that had
inhabited his wife and children.
After being hospitalized for his chest wound, he was taken to jail,
where he gave the police a calm, complete and coherent account
of his activities and his reasons for them. In jail, ve days after the
killings, Thomas read in the Bible, “If the right eye oends thee, pluck
it out. Thomas gouged out his right eye. After being sentenced to
death and sent to death row, he gouged out his left eye and ate it.
47
Scott Panetti, sentenced to death in Texas, suered from schizophre-
nia, fragmented personality, delusions and hallucinations for which
he was hospitalized numerous times before committing the crimes
for which he was sentenced to death. He was unable to overcome
his mental illnesses even though he took medication that could
not have been tolerated by a person not suering from extreme
psychosis. One day, he dressed in camouage, drove to the home
of his estranged wife’s parents and shot and killed them in front of
47 Marc Bookman, “How crazy is too crazy to be executed?”, Mother Jones, 12 February 2013,
available from www.motherjones.com/politics/2013/02/andre-thomas-death-penalty-men-
tal-illness-texas;
Ex Parte Andre Lee Thomas, 2009 Westlaw 693606 (Tex. Crim. App. March 18,
2009) (Cochran, J., concurring).
his wife and daughter. He was found competent to stand trial and
allowed to represent himself. He wore a cowboy suit during trial
and attempted to subpoena Jesus Christ, John F. Kennedy, and a
number of celebrities, some dead and some alive. His behaviour at
trial was described as bizarre, scary and trance-like, rendering his
trial “a judicial farce.
48
Since his trial in 1995, the courts have debated whether Mr. Panetti
understands the relationship between his punishment and the crimes
he committed, just as courts often wrestle with whether mentally ill
people are capable of participating in a trial, cooperating with their
lawyers and making decisions in their cases. Some experts testify that
they are capable, and other experts testify they are not. The prosecu-
tion will always present an expert who says the person is malingering,
even in cases in which, long before any criminal act, there was bizarre
behaviour, paranoia, delusions, treatment with psychotropic drugs,
hospitalizations, electroshock therapy, suicide attempts or self-muti-
lation. Judges, if they are free from political inuences in deciding
the issue, try to comprehend the incomprehensible and parse legal
concepts when dealing with manifestations of mental disorders. But
at best, their rulings are “a hazardous guess.
49
The more fundamental question is why people like Andre Lee Thomas
and Scott Panetti, who are undoubtedly profoundly mentally ill, are
subject to the death penalty. Of course they committed horrendous
crimes, took innocent lives that left others suering and scarred for
life, and must be isolated to protect society. But through no fault of
their own, they are tormented souls suering from devastating aic-
tions that leave them unable to think and reason like people who are
not so aicted. That is greater punishment that any court can impose.
The intellectually disabled and mentally ill are at an enormous dis-
advantage in the criminal courts. Some have no family support, and
others have families aicted with the same limitations or disorders
that they have. Their court-appointed lawyers may know nothing
about their disabilities, have no idea how to interact with them, and
48 Panetti v. Quarterman, 551 U.S. 930, 936-37 (2007).
49
Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U.S. 399, 412 (1986), quoting Solesbee v. Balkcom, 339 U.S. 9, 23 (1950)
(Frankfurter, J., dissenting).
128 129
know nothing about how to conduct an investigation of the disability
or which experts to consult. In many cases, they do not have adequate
resources for expert consultation or testing.
The Alabama lawyers who represented Holly Wood, who was con-
victed of the murder of his ex-girlfriend, did not present his limited
intellectual functioning as a reason he should be spared the death pen-
alty. It would not have been dicult. Special education teachers who
had Mr. Wood in their classes at the local school would have testied
that his IQ was probably “low to mid 60s, that Wood was “educable
mentally retarded or trainable mentally retarded,
50
and that, even at
the time of his trial, he could read only at the third-grade level and
could “not use abstraction skills much beyond the low average range of
intellect.
51
Alabama executed Mr. Wood, a black man, in 2010.
CONCLUSION
The United States promises equal justice for all in its Constitution and
its pledge of allegiance and above the entrance to its Supreme Court.
Yet poverty, race and mental impairment inuence the selection of
those who will be subject to what Justice Arthur Goldberg called the
“greatest conceivable degradation to the dignity of the human per-
sonality.
52
Finality—not justice—has become the ultimate goal of the
American legal system. Processing cases in as little time as possible—
not competent representation, equal justice or protection of the most
vulnerable—is the concern of most courts, even in cases where life and
death are at stake. Technicalities and procedural rules made up by the
Supreme Court and Congress now prevent enforcement of the Bill of
Rights in most capital cases, particularly those with bad lawyers.
However, there is growing recognition that this is not moral, just or
right. Former President Jimmy Carter, who as Governor of Georgia
signed into law in March 1973 Georgia’s death penalty statute, called
on 12 November 2013 for an end to capital punishment, because it is
being imposed on the poor, members of racial minorities and people
50 Wood v. Allen, 542 F.3d 1281, 1324 (11th Cir. 2008) (Barkett, J., dissenting) (quoting testimony
of teachers), denial of relief armed, 558 U.S. 290 (2010).
51 Ibid. (Barkett, J., dissenting) (quoting the testimony of a psychologist of evaluated Wood.
52 Arthur Goldberg, letter to the editor,
Boston Globe, 16 August 1976.
with diminished mental capacity.
53
Supreme Court Justice John Paul
Stevens, who voted to uphold the death penalty in 1976, observed
before leaving the Court that there are fewer procedural protections
for those facing death, a strong probability that race inuences who
is sentenced to death, and a “real risk of error” with irrevocable con-
sequences. He concluded that “the imposition of the death penalty
represents ‘the pointless and needless extinction of life with only mar-
ginal contributions to any discernible social or public purposes.’”
54
The death penalty has recently been abandoned by Connecticut,
Illinois, Maryland, New Jersey, New Mexico and New York, and gov-
ernors have declared moratoriums on the death penalty in Colorado,
Oregon and Washington.
55
Perhaps there will be a re-examination of
the death penalty before too much more damage is done.
53 “Remarks by former U.S. President Jimmy Carter at the National Symposium on the Modern
Death Penalty in America”, 12 November 2013, available from www.cartercenter.org/news/
editorials_speeches/death-penalty-speech-111213.html; American Bar Association,
National
Symposium on the Modern Death Penalty, available from www.americanbar.org/groups/indi-
vidual_rights/projects/death_penalty_due_process_review_project/national_syposium_death_
penalty_carter_center.html (including videos of presentations by President Carter and others).
54
Baze v. Rees, 553 U.S. 35, 83 (2008) (Stevens, J., concurring), quoting Justice White’s concur-
ring opinion in Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 312 (1972) (White, J., concurring).
55 John W. Hickenlooper, Governor, State of Colorado, “Executive order: death sentence reprieve”,
22 May 2013, available from www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/documents/COexecutiveorder.pdf;
“Gov. John Kitzhaber of Oregon declares a moratorium on all executions”, available from
www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/gov-john-kitzhaber-oregon-declares-moratorium-all-executions;
Governor Jay Inslee of Washington, “Governor Inslee’s remarks announcing a capital punish-
ment moratorium”, available from www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/documents/InsleeMoratorium-
Remarks.pdf.
130 131
THE DEATH PENALTY IN THE
COMMONWEALTH CARIBBEAN:
JUSTICE OUT OF REACH?
Arif Bulkan
1
The Commonwealth Caribbean is made up of 12 independent
nations, all former colonies of Great Britain: Antigua and Barbuda,
the Bahamas, Barbados, Belize, Dominica, Grenada, Guyana, Jamaica,
Saint Kitts and Nevis, Saint Lucia, Saint Vincent and the Grena-
dines and Trinidad and Tobago. In the remaining countries of the
English-speaking Caribbean, namely the dependent territories of
Anguilla, Bermuda, British Virgin Islands, Cayman Islands, Montserrat
and the Turks and Caicos, the death penalty was abolished in 1999.
2
The legal systems in these countries remain largely based on the
common law system they inherited from Great Britain. They diverged
during and after colonisation, but their structure and systems share the
same foundation, and substantive laws are similar in many respects. All
but three of the countries of the Commonwealth Caribbean have
retained the Privy Council based in London as their nal appellate
court—one residual element of colonialism that has proven signi-
cant in death penalty issues. Barbados, Belize and Guyana were the
rst countries to accept the appellate jurisdiction of the Caribbean
Court of Justice, which was established by treaty in 2001 and came
into operation in 2005 with its headquarters in Port of Spain, Trini-
dad and Tobago.
3
CURRENT STATUS OF THE DEATH PENALTY
In all the colonial possessions of Britain in the Caribbean, the death
sentence was mandatory for a number of oences including murder
and treason. After independence, although it was increasingly viewed
1 Arif Bulkan is a member of the Faculty of Law at the University of the West Indies.
2 Roger Hood and Carolyn Hoyle,
The Death Penalty: A Worldwide Perspective, 4th ed. (Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2008), p. 104.
3
Agreement Establishing the Caribbean Court of Justice (14 February 2001), available from www.
caribbeancourtofjustice.org/court-instruments/the-agreement-establishing-the-ccj.
as incompatible with evolving human rights standards and ineective
as a tool of law enforcement, it survived constitutionally across the
Commonwealth Caribbean through one principal mechanism. This
was the constitutional savings clause, of which there are two types in
Caribbean constitutions:
A “special savings” clause preserves punishments predating
independence from challenge based on the prohibition, in
the constitution’s bill of rights, of torture and inhuman and
degrading treatment. It can be found in the bill of rights of
all of the constitutions.
4
A “general savings” clause preserves laws predating indepen-
dence from challenge based on any provision of the bill of rights.
This far more sweeping provision was only inserted in the con-
stitutions of the rst ve territories to achieve independence.
5
Theoretically, these provisions would protect the death penalty in
the Commonwealth Caribbean from challenge on human rights
grounds, since it predated the independence-era constitutions both
as a punishment and as a law. However, over a decade beginning in
the early 1990s, the Privy Council restricted the imposition of the
death penalty across most of the Commonwealth Caribbean. They
did so incrementally, principally by focusing on how the penalty was
imposed and carried out. Key issues addressed during this period are
described below.
Delays in carrying out sentences
In 1993, in a case from Jamaica in which two convicted murderers
had been on death row for more than 12 years, the Privy Council
held that the delay constituted cruel and unusual punishment, and as a
remedy they commuted the sentences of both to life imprisonment.
6
4 A standard formulation is that contained in s 7(2) of the Constitution of Antigua and Barbuda:
“Nothing contained in or done under the authority of any law shall be held to be inconsistent
with or in contravention of this section to the extent that the law in question authorises the
iniction of any description of punishment that was lawful in Antigua on 31st October 1981.
5 Jamaica, s 26(8) of the 1962 Constitution, replaced by section 13(12) in the amended 2011
version; Trinidad and Tobago, s 6; Guyana, article 152; Barbados, s 26; and the Bahamas,
article 30.
6
Pratt and Morgan v. AG of Jamaica (1993) 43 WIR 340.
132 133
In addition, they held that to keep any condemned prisoner on death
row for more than ve years would violate the constitutional prohi-
bition against inhuman or degrading punishment, and that the special
savings clause did not apply because the delay would not have been
lawful prior to independence. The punishment per se was not invali-
dated but rather its manner of implementation.
This was a ne distinction that some found unsupportable,
7
but
the impact was immediate and dramatic. In territories all across the
Caribbean, scores of condemned prisoners awaiting execution for
more than ve years became the beneciaries of the ban on excessive
delay, leading to the observation by two senior Caribbean judges that
the ve-year rule came to be applied with “guillotine-like nality.
8
The ruling meant that Caribbean countries opting to retain the
death penalty had to ensure that their justice systems operated more
eciently. The position of the Privy Council on this was uncom-
promising: “a State that wishes to retain capital punishment must
accept the responsibility of ensuring that execution follows as swiftly
as practicable after sentence, allowing a reasonable time for appeal
and consideration of reprieve. . . . Appellate procedures that echo
down the years are not compatible with capital punishment. The
death row phenomenon must not become established as a part of
our jurisprudence.
9
Pardons
Next to be addressed were the procedures around the granting of
pardons, also referred to as the exercise of the prerogative of mercy,
during which the totality of a condemned person’s case is consid-
ered by a committee that advises the head of state whether the death
sentence deserves to be commuted.
10
Historically, the condemned
person had no right to see the material being put before the Mercy
Committee or to make representations before it.
11
That position was
7 Berthan Macaulay, “The Jamaica Constitution: conict of powers—the Pratt and Morgan case”
(1993) 18 WILJ 45.
8
Joseph and Boyce v. AG of Barbados (2006) 69 WIR 104, per de la Bastide P and Saunders J
at [49].
9 Macaulay, “The Jamaica Constitution”, p. 359.
10 See, for example, Jamaica Constitution, ss. 90 and 91.
11
De Freitas v. Benny (1975) 27 WIR 318; Reckley v. Minister for Public Safety (No. 2) (1996)
47 WIR 9.
based on the view that mercy is not a legal right but an act of grace.
However, the Privy Council reconsidered this position, eventually
holding that the prerogative of mercy should be exercised by pro-
cedures that are fair and proper and amenable to judicial review.
12
In the case that resulted in this ruling, this meant that condemned
prisoners were held to be entitled to sucient notice of the date on
which their case would be considered so that they or their advisers
could prepare representations, which the committee would be bound
to consider.
This Privy Council decision was foreshadowed by the Court of Appeal
of Guyana, which had ruled shortly before that the exercise of the
prerogative of mercy operates more as a safety net for those wrongly
convicted than as an act of grace.
13
In that case, the court reasoned that,
as a constitutional republic, Guyana should not have the same reverence
for the prerogative, which is founded on the arbitrary will of kings. In
the case of the prerogative of mercy, this meant scrutinising, not the
decision itself, but the manner in which it was reached.
These decisions, too, aected many prisoners on death row, for irreg-
ularities in the way their cases had been reviewed potentially meant
they needed to be reconsidered. Inevitably, this entailed a further
delay, which would trigger the embargo on death-row waits of over
ve years.
Petitions to international bodies
When a country accedes to certain international treaties, its citizens
receive the right to petition the treaty body directly regarding a
breach of a right armed by the treaty. A possibly unanticipated
consequence was that as death row inmates availed themselves of
this right, the waiting time post-conviction lengthened. Often,
by the time a decision was delivered, the ve-year time limit had
expired, which meant that the state could no longer execute the
convict. In frustration, Caribbean states tried in a number of ways to
circumvent this problem. Guyana, Jamaica and Trinidad and Tobago
withdrew from Optional Protocol 1, which provides the right of
12 Lewis et al v. AG of Jamaica [2000] 3 WLR 1785.
13
Yassin and Thomas v. AG of Guyana GY 1996 CA 3 (Carilaw).
134 135
petition to the Human Rights Committee, and both Trinidad and
Guyana re-acceded with a reservation.
14
However, the Committee
held this reservation to be invalid, since by its discriminatory pur-
pose it oended basic principles embodied in the Convention,
15
and in response the government of Trinidad and Tobago withdrew
from the Protocol again in 2000. Other conicts involved attempts
to carry out executions while petitions were pending, one noto-
rious instance being the execution of Glen Ashby in 1994, just
one month before the ve-year post-conviction deadline would
have expired.
16
These tensions culminated in erce legal battles, as condemned
prisoners challenged the constitutionality of carrying out execu-
tions while petitions were still pending. Eventually, it was held by
the Privy Council in relation to Trinidad and Tobago that the due
process right entitled condemned prisoners to be allowed to com-
plete any appellate or analogous legal processes that were capable of
resulting in a reduction or commutation of their sentences before
that process was rendered nugatory by executive action (such as
prescribing unrealistic time limits for the petitions or executing
prisoners whose petitions were pending).
17
At that time, only the
Trinidad and Tobago Constitution used the language of “due pro-
cess” in its bill of rights, but this decision was shortly thereafter
held to be applicable to Jamaica (and by extension all the remaining
countries of the Caribbean except Guyana) through the guarantee
of protection of the law.
18
Defying predictions that it was going to reverse the perceived abo-
litionist tendencies of the Privy Council, the Caribbean Court of
Justice in its rst major death penalty appeal arrived at a similar
result, holding that to execute a prisoner while an international
petition is pending would be a violation of the right to protection
of the law.
19
14 Hood and Hoyle, The Death Penalty, p. 108.
15
Kennedy v. Trinidad and Tobago CCPR/C/67/D/845/1999, paragraph 6.7.
16 Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions, 14
December 1994, E/CN.4/1995/61, paragraph 382.
17
Thomas and Hilaire v. Baptiste (1998) 54 WIR 387.
18
Lewis et al v. AG of Jamaica [2000] 3 WLR 1785.
19
Joseph and Boyce v. AG of Barbados (2006) 69 WIR 104.
Mandatory sentences
The next major development was related to the mandatory nature
of the death sentence. Early cases had espoused the view that this
aspect saved the death penalty from unconstitutionality since it
would be applied without discrimination to all those convicted of
murder.
20
By the time this view came to be rejected, the death sen-
tence was nonetheless held to be valid in the Caribbean because of
the special savings clause (preserving punishments predating inde-
pendence)—though not for long.
First, in countries such as Belize where the constitution had no
savings clause, the sentence was struck down because of its indis-
criminate scope—applying to all convictions for murder despite
the potential variations in culpability.
21
It was also struck down in
Jamaica, which had amended the substantive law to rationalise the
oence of murder.
22
In relation to this rationalisation, the Privy
Council held that there could be no category of capital murder
for which a conviction automatically resulted in a death sentence,
and since the law had been amended to create these oences, it
was no longer the protected pre-independence law and thus lost its
immunity. Reading amendments to the law in the Bahamas strictly,
the Privy Council overturned the mandatory aspect of the death
sentence there as well.
23
A more ingenious (and controversial) interpretation was applied to
the countries of the Eastern Caribbean, where, notwithstanding the
special savings clause, the mandatory nature of the death penalty
was struck down on the ground that this clause only preserved
punishments that were “authorised. Since the death penalty was
mandated for certain oences, it could not be said to be authorised
and was therefore not protected by the clause, and thus it consti-
tuted a violation of the prohibition against inhuman and degrading
punishments.
24
20 De Freitas v. Benny (1975) 27 WIR 318; Ong ah Chuan v. Public Prosecutor [1981] AC 648.
21
Reyes v. the Queen [2002] UKPC 11.
22
Watson v. the Queen [2004] UKPC 34.
23
Bowe and Davis v. the Queen (2006) 68 WIR 10.
24
The Queen v. Hughes [2002] UKPC 12 (St Lucia); Fox v. the Queen [2002] UKPC 13
(St Vincent).
136 137
At the end of this unprecedented period of judicial activism, only three
countries were left with a mandatory death penalty: Barbados, Guyana
(which had abolished appeals to the Privy Council and was thus not
bound by any of these developments
25
) and Trinidad and Tobago. Bar-
bados and Trinidad and Tobago were able to retain the death penalty
because of the general savings clause,
26
since neither country had made
changes to the substantive law. In Guyana, statute has since restricted
the death penalty to certain categories of murder and eliminated its
mandatory aspect.
27
Thus, while the death penalty still exists across the
entire Commonwealth Caribbean, only Barbados and Trinidad and
Tobago apply it automatically to every conviction for murder.
APPLICATION OF THE DEATH PENALTY
There have been only a few scholarly analyses of the application
of the death penalty in the Caribbean, but even the most cursory
examination of decided cases suggests the existence of bias at sev-
eral stages, produced by factors such as economic status, social class
and mental capacity. These biases routinely aect the fairness of trials
(and by extension, the safety of convictions), because they inevitably
involve or lead to breaches of due process, liberty rights and evi-
dential safeguards. In Trinidad and Tobago in particular, a number of
recent studies have revealed fundamental deciencies in the criminal
justice system. These studies have been replicated to a lesser extent
in other locations, and considering them along with the case law, it
can be credibly argued that there are many concerns with regard to
the equitable application of the death penalty in the Commonwealth
Caribbean. Specic issues are considered below.
Mental capacity
In common law, the test for insanity is whether, at the time of the
act in question, the defendant was labouring under such a defect
of reason, due to a disease of the mind, as either not to know the
25 This was eected in stages in 1970 by the Guyana Republic Act 1970-9, s 8 and Judicial Com-
mittee (Termination of Appeals) Act 1970-14, and then in 1973 by the Constitution (Amendment)
Act 1973-19, s 4.
26
Boyce v. the Queen [2004] UKPC 32 (PC, Barbados); Matthew v. the State [2004] UKPC 33
(PC, T&T).
27 Criminal Law Oences (Amendment) Act 2010, Act 21-2010 [Guy].
nature and quality of his act or, if he did know this, not to know that
he was doing wrong.
28
From the time of its formulation in the mid-
19th century, this test was heavily criticised,
29
yet it has endured
in spite of complications regarding what constitutes a disease of
the mind and the potential injustice created by the requirement to
prove lack of knowledge of the quality of the act. A cursory check
of reported cases suggests that this test seems to be too technical
for judges to explain adequately or for jurors to evaluate sensibly,
with the result that many convictions are overturned on the basis
of incorrect directions.
30
Aside from its technicalities, another prob-
lem with the legal test seems to be the archaic understanding of
mental illness, and its divergence from what may actually constitute
a mental incapacity. This creates doubt as to whether directions
in any case are properly understood and acted upon, in addition
to the doubts as to whether the law adequately treats those with
mental illnesses.
A case that well illustrates these diculties is Stephen Robinson a/c
Psycho v. the State.
31
The appellant, a destitute and homeless person,
was convicted of the January 2002 murder of a security guard and
sentenced to death in 2009. Medical evidence established that he
had been diagnosed with schizophrenia since 1984. In the opin-
ion of both examining psychiatrists, he had been suering from an
episode when the murder occurred, based not only on this history
but also on his attire and unusual behaviour at the time in ques-
tion. There was no competing evidence to contradict the medical
evidence, but the jury rejected it, presumably on the belief that he
was experiencing a lucid interval. Thus, the opinion of two experts
(one with considerable experience) was discarded in favour of pure
speculation. This is dicult to justify, and it underlines the aws of
the outdated insanity
test, which are exacerbated by the rules of
criminal procedure under which a determination of insanity is a
question of fact for the jury.
28 (1843) 10 Cl & Fin 200.
29 John Cyril Smith and Brian Hogan,
Criminal Law, 7th ed. (London, Butterworths, 1992), p.
207.
30 Amnesty International,
Caribbean: Death Penalty in the English-Speaking Caribbean: A Human
Rights Issue (AMR 05/001/2012, 30 November 2012), available from www.amnesty.org/en/
library/info/AMR05/001/2012/en.
31 CATT Crim 12/2009, decision dated 29 July 2010, available from www.ttlawcourts.org.
138 139
The Court of Appeal of Trinidad and Tobago dismissed an appeal,
even while describing the outcome as unfortunate. Reinforcing the
incongruity of the decision was the majority’s concluding passage:
It is unfortunate that the application of clear legal [princi-
ples] should result in the imposition of the death penalty on
an individual who, on the evidence, has a long outstanding
mental disability. The apparent harshness of the result of
our decision might best be ameliorated, not by a distortion
of the law, but rather by petitioning the appropriate author-
ities, that is, the Mercy Committee.
32
There is something profoundly amiss with a justice system that
regards the outcome in a case as approximating an injustice but
shunts the responsibility for addressing that injustice to extrale-
gal means. Part of the reason for this outcome was that the legal
principles described as clear by the court are in actuality archaic
and repeatedly misapplied and misunderstood, so the matter
was more appropriate for resolution by the court rather than the
Mercy Committee.
Practical concerns also exist in relation to the institutional capac-
ity in many Caribbean states. A recent report of the World Health
Organisation disclosed several deciencies in mental health systems
across the Caribbean, including insucient facilities, outdated prac-
tices and lack of treatment protocols.
33
Some of this could probably
be traced to weak legislative frameworks, insofar as the majority of
countries have mental health legislation predating independence,
as well as to the under-resourcing of this sector, with an average of
only 3.8 per cent of health budgets in the region being devoted to
mental health.
34
Where mental health facilities are nonexistent or
substandard, criminal defendants may go undiagnosed and untreated.
Once caught up in criminal proceedings, it is not uncommon for
people to undergo trial, conviction and sentencing without any
32 Ibid., p. 25.
33 World Health Organization,
WHO-AIMS Report on Mental Health Systems in the Caribbean
Region (2011), available from www.who.int/mental_health/evidence/WHO-AIMS/en.
34 Ibid., p. 13.
recognition that legal liability may be absent due to a lack of
mental capacity.
35
The appellant in Nigel Brown v. the State
36
had been convicted of
murder and sentenced to death; after conviction, fresh evidence was
obtained from a psychiatrist that he was suering from a mental
disorder that called into question his capacity to plead and under-
stand the nature of a trial. In allowing his appeal, the Privy Council
criticized the failure of the system to detect this issue earlier:
There is no doubt that the appellant’s legal advisers should
have been alert to the question of his tness to plead. Yet
no medical evidence was adduced on his behalf nor was
this issue canvassed either on the trial or before the Court
of Appeal. This is a matter of obvious and grave concern.
The Board has been greatly exercised by the fact that these
reports have been produced ex post facto and without any
explanation as to why medical evidence on the issue of
tness to plead has not been produced before now.
37
A recent report by the Death Penalty Project concluded that
“the death penalty [in the Caribbean] is regularly being imposed
on persons with signicant mental illness and/or intellectual
disability.
38
Expert evidence
Closely linked to the issue of mental incapacity are concerns about
the use and availability of expert evidence generally, in which crim-
inal defendants face a recurring disadvantage. This problem was
highlighted in a case from Barbados in which the prosecution relied
on the evidence of a forensic odontologist to establish that bite marks
35 Several of these cases are mentioned in Amnesty International, Caribbean: Death Penalty in the
English-Speaking Caribbean, pp. 18-21.
36 [2012] UKPC 2 (PC, T&T).
37 Ibid., paragraph 68.
38 Saul Lehrfreund, “The systemic failure to grant special protection and all guarantees to ensure
a fair trial in capital cases in the Caribbean, Africa and Asia”, presentation at the Oce of the
High Commissioner for Human Rights panel Moving Away from the Death Penalty—Wrong-
ful Convictions, United Nations Headquarters, New York, 28 June 2013.
140 141
on the arm of the respondent matched the teeth of the deceased.
For over three years the respondent tried to obtain an independent
assessment of the evidence by an expert of his own choosing, but
without success since this required highly specialised and expensive
expertise. The State was willing to underwrite only some of the cost
of the expert’s fees, and the Court of Appeal of Barbados agreed it
was under no obligation to do more than that.
39
Although the Court
of Appeal conceded that “bite mark analysis is a highly complex and
controversial subject and it is sucient to say for the purpose of this
judgment that the respondent may be at a disadvantage if he is unable
to obtain expert help in dealing with the evidence of the prosecu-
tion,
40
it nonetheless held that the respondent was not entitled to
an expert funded by the State. No such right was established in the
Constitution, and in any case, an order to that eect would oend the
principle of separation of powers.
This decision was overturned on appeal, on the ground that the
respondent would be at such a disadvantage without expert evidence
of his own as to aect the fairness of the trial.
41
But the decision of
the lower court is instructive, as it reects the disadvantage suered by
criminal defendants without the resources to mount a proper defence.
Judges are not always sympathetic to the plight of low-income defen-
dants or willing to order the state to incur expenses on their behalf.
Even when a defendant ultimately succeeds, as in this case, a serious
cost of airing these issues is the time that it requires, since delays
are unpredictable and have the potential to prejudice the trial. The
result is to place poor people in a vulnerable and unequal position, a
disparity that takes on heightened signicance in death penalty cases.
The poster case for such inequality is Indravani Ramjattan v. the State,
42
where disabilities of poverty, class and gender combined to produce
an appalling instance of state-perpetrated injustice. Ms. Ramjattan was
convicted along with two codefendants of the murder of her husband
and sentenced to death, and it was not until her nal appeal had been
dismissed that she was allowed to present evidence of her mental state
39 AG of Barbados v. Gibson Civil Appeal No 8 of 2007 (decision dated 15 December 2009).
40 Ibid., paragraph 41.
41
Gibson v. AG of Barbados [2010] CCJ 3.
42
Indravani Ramjattan v. the State (1999) 54 WIR 383 (PC, T&T).
at the time of the crime. This evidence revealed a life of epic suering.
Regularly beaten as a child, she was taken out of school at age 13 and
married by her mother at age 17 to a man 18 years her senior.
43
Over
the course of 10 years she bore several children, all the while being
subjected to extreme physical and emotional abuse by her husband. He
repeatedly accused her of having other sexual relationships, while at the
same time boasting of his sexual encounters with other women. Vio-
lence was a norm of the relationship, including attempted strangulation,
wounding, bruising and rape—summed up by the Court of Appeal of
Trinidad and Tobago as a “reign of terror.
44
Ms. Ramjattan eventually summoned up the courage to leave her hus-
band, escaping to live with her childhood sweetheart, but her husband
hunted her down and forcibly recaptured her. By the time they got
home, she was covered in blood; he then locked her in a bedroom
and told her that he was going to sink her head inside her neck with a
piece of wood. He struck her on the head, hands, arms, back and feet
until she fell unconscious. During the nal week of her husband’s life,
he tortured her and threatened to kill her and the children. All this was
corroborated by her 10-year-old daughter, who testied that her father
regularly beat her mother with his sts, belt and pieces of wood and
threatened to shoot her. She managed to write a letter to her boyfriend,
who came with the third accused to rescue her. The two men beat the
deceased and killed him. Although she was not present at the scene and
denied asking the men to kill her husband, she was convicted along
with the other two of his murder, and all three were sentenced to death.
It was only after Ms. Ramjattan lost her appeal that she was able
to secure a retrial. It was then revealed that she had been unable
to present evidence on her mental state earlier because she did not
have the money or a reasonable opportunity to engage a psychiatrist
to examine her and make a report capable of being used in legal
proceedings. The Privy Council was informed that it was not routine
in Trinidad for the mental health of defendants in murder cases to
be assessed at or before arraignment.
45
Her petition was allowed and
43 These facts are taken from the decision of the Court of Appeal at the re-hearing: Indravani
Ramjattan v. the State (No 2) (1999) 57 WIR 501.
44 Ibid., p. 504.
45 (1999) 54 WIR 383 at 385.
142 143
her case remitted to the Court of Appeal of Trinidad and Tobago to
consider the psychiatric evidence.
A litany of procedural irregularities were uncovered as well: Ms. Ram-
jattan had no counsel at the time of arrest, during the police interviews,
and for more than a year after her arrest. She was tricked into signing a
confession. She was pregnant at the time of her arrest, and subsequently
had a miscarriage while in custody, but received no medical treatment.
At the trial she was poorly represented, and her counsel did not present
any evidence of the abuse she had suered—which meant that the jury
was faced with a choice of acquittal or conviction for murder.
The Court of Appeal accepted the evidence of the psychiatrist that Ms.
Ramjattan, at the time of the crime, suered from an abnormality of
the mind capable of reducing her responsibility for the crime. It was
the doctor’s opinion that she had suered from symptoms of depressive
illness and post-traumatic stress disorder for several years leading up to
the time of the oence and that her psychological reactions were also
characteristic of battered-wife syndrome. For the rst time anywhere
in the Commonwealth Caribbean, evidence of battered-wife syn-
drome was accepted to establish a defence of diminished responsibility.
The Court of Appeal quashed Ms. Ramjattan’s conviction for murder
and substituted one of manslaughter. By this time, she had already spent
eight years in custody, four and a half on death row. Despite the horric
circumstances of her situation, the Court of Appeal still ordered her to
serve an additional ve years in prison.
This case demonstrates discrimination on several levels. The institu-
tional and systemic failings were especially acute, occurring at every
stage of Ms. Ramjattan’s life. The background facts, for example,
reveal an absence of state regulation so complete that it rendered girls
vulnerable to parental abuse and unable to access an education. Later
on, the same failings would enable a decade of spousal abuse without
the implementation of laws or the intervention of social services to
stem such horric and sustained violence.
46
When she acted to protect
herself, the State responded mechanically and harshly, convicting and
sentencing her to the ultimate penalty with no apparent realisation of
46 In the Court of Appeal, the Chief Justice described this situation as endemic in Trinidad and
Tobago: (1999) 57 WIR 501 at 504.
its own responsibility for the events. There were other failings as well:
a legal framework that denied the victim of extreme and sustained
physical abuse the defences of provocation and self-defence, exac-
erbated by an institutional structure that showed no understanding
or empathy for her circumstances. Her situation was aggravated by
poverty, and the absence of legal representation at crucial stages left
her at the mercy of the police, who in their own way continued the
abuse by denying her fundamental liberties.
Poverty and neglect were compounded by disabilities of gender
and race, the latter on display even at the level of the Court of
Appeal. Ms. Ramjattan was a woman of East Indian descent who
had formed a relationship with a man of African descent—not a
gure of much sympathy, as revealed in her treatment at various
levels in the criminal justice system and in the transcript of the
Court of Appeal proceedings. In his judgment, the Chief Justice of
Trinidad and Tobago commented:
It is, of course, no part of our duty to attribute or apportion
moral blame, particularly to a woman who was subjected
to that type of treatment. But we must not lose sight of
the fact that at the time of the murder she was carrying the
child of another man with whom she obviously, from her
evidence, hoped to make a new life. There is nothing wrong
with that, albeit that the other man appears to have been
married himself.
47
In other words, she did not t the stereotype of a victim as chaste
and passive—and despite the protestations of being nonjudgmental,
by referring to the adultery of both participants, the suggestion that
Ms. Ramjattan may have been undeserving of sympathy is a powerful
subliminal message of this passage.
There are indications that the inequalities suered by Ms. Ramjat-
tan exist structurally as well. In 2000 one commentator said that in
Trinidad and Tobago, “most of the women on death row are there as
47 Ibid.
144 145
a result of some form of domestic violence.
48
Whether or not this is
still true, the multiple failings that existed in the Ramjattan case indi-
cate that gender bias in the criminal justice system is an overlooked
problem. One organisation, Equality Now, has suggested that the
discriminatory treatment of women works in the opposite direction
as well—that when they are murder victims, their perpetrators are
treated far more leniently than Indravani Ramjattan was.
49
Poverty and due process
In 2012 Amnesty International commented:
The criminal justice systems in many ESC countries are
struggling with caseloads that far exceed their capacity.
This often results in violation of due process and prolonged
delays. Factors contributing to delays include inadequate
stang levels, resources and legal representation; insucient
jurors; inadequate witness protection programmes; and high
and increasing crime rates. Weaknesses in forensic analysis
and delays in processing evidence in crime laboratories also
contribute to systemic delays and errors in trial proceedings
and scheduling.
50
These deciencies are intensied where defendants are poor and
unrepresented, a reality of many capital cases across the Caribbean.
Even though legal aid is provided by the state, the quality obtained
often reects the paltry remuneration oered. Moreover, legal aid is
activated for the rst time only at the preliminary inquiry, and after
that may not be consistent or structured. This means that at the crucial
pretrial and investigative stage, suspects are at the mercy of the state’s
powerful machinery. Violations thus ourish during this period when
suspects are likely to be held incommunicado, without access even to
relatives or friends, much less a lawyer. At this time, when a suspect is
48 Leonard Birdsong, “In quest of gender-bias in death penalty cases: analyzing the English speak-
ing Caribbean experience”, Indiana International & Comparative Law Review, vol. 10, no. 317
(2000), p. 324 .
49 See Equality Now, “Trinidad and Tobago: the imminent execution of a battered woman and
her defenders” (1 October1998), available from www.equalitynow.org/node/188.
50 Amnesty International,
Caribbean: Death Penalty in the English-Speaking Caribbean.
at his or her most vulnerable, it is easier to obtain signed confessions,
but the possibility that such confessions might be unreliable or just
plain fabricated is suggested by the number of convictions that are
challenged, often successfully, on this ground alone.
51
Even after legal aid is provided, it is by no means assured that crim-
inal defendants will have meaningful access to their advisers, who
tend to change multiple times throughout the process. There have
been several cases in which counsel was appointed on the day of the
trial and either forced to go on immediately or given only a short
adjournment
52
—or even for no counsel to be appointed, leaving the
defendant unrepresented.
53
It is also not unusual for very junior coun-
sel to be appointed—in one case, a lawyer of three months’ standing
was appointed for a defendant on the morning of the trial.
54
Predict-
ably, in these situations the quality of representation is far below the
standard required for a proper defence in any criminal case, much less
one in which the possible outcome is a death sentence.
These failings are powerfully exemplied in
Ann Marie Boodram v. the State,
another case from Trinidad and Tobago.
55
The appellant had been
assigned several lawyers before one was nally secured to represent
her during her retrial. The court-appointed defence counsel failed to
object to deposition evidence of a dead witness, failed to object to a
confession despite doubts as to its voluntary nature, including an alle-
gation that the appellant was raped by a senior police ocer involved
in the investigation, and most astonishing of all, conducted the major-
ity of the defence unaware that it was a retrial. When he became
aware of this, he failed to obtain the transcript of the earlier proceed-
ings. In quashing the conviction, the Privy Council concluded that
“Mr.Sawh’s multiple failures, and in particular his extraordinary fail-
ure ... to enquire into what happened at the rst trial, reveal either
51 The Ramjattan case is a good example of a common situation, but the ndings of the HRC
substantiate this failing in many cases. See Christopher Brown v. Jamaica (775/97); Kennedy v.
Trinidad and Tobago CCPR/C/67/D/845/1999; Errol Johnson v. Jamaica (588/94); Pennant
v. Jamaica (647/95); and the cases discussed by the Inter-American Commission on Human
Rights in The Death Penalty in the Inter-American Human Rights System: From Restrictions to
Abolition (OEA/Ser.L/V/II., Doc. 68, 31 December 2011), pp. 130-138.
52 Desmond Allum and Gregory Delzin,
Report on the Criminal Justice System in Trinidad and
Tobago (2003), paragraph 88.
53
Frank Robinson v. Jamaica, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/35/D/223/1987 (1989).
54
Bernard v. the State (2007) UKPC 34 (PC, T&T).
55 [2001] UKPC 20 (PC, T&T).
146 147
gross incompetence or a cynical dereliction of the most elementary
professional duties.
56
That this is not an isolated example is revealed
by the number of cases across the Caribbean where appeals have been
allowed because of inadequate representation.
57
Another problem with legal aid in most Caribbean countries is that
it is often provided for trials and appeals in capital cases, but only for
criminal and not constitutional proceedings,
58
and never for non-
trial necessities like preparing and
ling documents for an appeal.
59
This results in several injustices.
Criminal defendants—often poorly
educated and sometimes illiterate—
are unable to prepare a Notice of
Appeal. When they do, appeals are
usually conned to the deciencies
of the rst trial, and only rarely is
fresh evidence forthcoming. With
assignments occurring at the time
of trial, appellate lawyers frequently have little time to prepare the
case.
60
Moreover, the state has no obligation to facilitate appeals to
the Privy Council in London, and although a number of English
solicitors provide pro bono assistance in death penalty cases, where
the paperwork is not done in advance, this can be the end of the line
for poor appellants, as happened to the last person to be executed in
the Commonwealth Caribbean.
Charles Laplace was executed on 19 December 2008 in Saint Kitts and
Nevis, shortly after the Eastern Caribbean Court of Appeal upheld his
conviction for the murder of his wife. Laplace would have been entitled
to a further appeal to the Privy Council, but no appeal was led—pre-
sumably because he did not have the means or ability to do so. Laplace
was executed after four years on death row. It remains unclear whether
56 Ibid., paragraph 40.
57 For examples, see
Bethel v. the State (1998) 55 WIR 394 and Bernard v. the State (2007) UKPC
34 (PC, T&T).
58 Inter-American Commission on Human Rights,
The Death Penalty in the Inter-American
Human Rights System, pp. 139-146.
59 Allum and Delzin,
Report on the Criminal Justice System in Trinidad and Tobago, paragraph 86.
60 Ibid.
“THE BULK OF
KILLINGS GO
UNSOLVED, THE
MAJORITY OF
CONVICTIONS
ARE OVERTURNED
ON APPEAL…”
Arif Bulkan
the pardon guidelines established by the Privy Council
61
were faithfully
followed in his case—such as aording him the opportunity to see the
documents being presented to the Mercy Committee or to make rep-
resentations to it. That he was executed when he had not exhausted all
appeals is a graphic illustration of the disadvantages faced by the poor
and the inequalities of the system.
This situation is partly attributable to the breakdown in regional
policing systems, where inadequate training, unrealistic remuneration,
lack of eective oversight and high levels of corruption combine to
produce a toxic brew of incompetence and dishonesty.
62
Instead of
conducting proper analytical and forensic work, police investigators
in the Caribbean often rely solely on confessions, a practice that has
long been criticised.
63
Such deciencies inexorably aect the fairness
of trials, as demonstrated by the number of convictions overturned
for breaches of rights to due process and fair trial.
Arbitrary application
Recent studies of the death penalty in Trinidad and Tobago reveal
not just its utter inecacy as a deterrent but also the arbitrary nature
of its application. An analysis of recorded homicides in Trinidad and
Tobago between 1998 and 2002 established that the probability of
a killing resulting in a conviction for murder is extremely low, with
only 5percent of murders recorded by the police over this period
resulting in a conviction for murder by the end of 2002.
64
Over the
ve-year period examined, 633 deaths were recorded by the police as
murders, of which 280 (44.2 per cent) remained unsolved.
Of the 353 murders classied as solved by the police during this
period, only 33 resulted in a conviction for murder by the end of
2005. Moreover, the clear-up rate varies with the type of murder. The
authors adopted the categorisation of murders employed by the police:
61 Lewis et al v. AG of Jamaica [2000] 3 WLR 1785.
62 Carolyn Gomes, “Police accountability in the Caribbean: where are the people?”, paper pre-
sented at a Workshop on Police Accountability at the Civicus World Assembly, 23-27 May 2007,
Glasgow, Scotland.
63 Allum and Delzin,
Report on the Criminal Justice System in Trinidad and Tobago, paragraph 36.
64 Roger Hood and Florence Seemungal,
A Rare and Arbitrary Fate: Conviction for Murder, the
Mandatory Death Penalty and the Reality of Homicide in Trinidad and Tobago, report to the
Death Penalty Project (Oxford, Centre for Criminology, University of Oxford, 2006).
148 149
gang- and drug-related killings, killing in the course of a robbery or
other crime, killing in the course of a domestic dispute (where the
parties are related), killing in the course of an altercation not involv-
ing a domestic setting, and those with an unknown motive, also called
“body dumped” by the police. Of the 208 killings that were classied
as gang- or drug-related or involving body-dumping—just under a
third of the total—there were only two convictions for murder and
another two for manslaughter by the end of 2005. In contrast, killings
in the course of domestic violence, which represented 17 per cent
of recorded homicides, accounted for 52 per cent of the murders
solved. Thus, the proportion of murders that the police recorded as
solved was lowest for the category that has been increasing the most:
gang- and drug-related murders, and particularly those where the
victim’s body was dumped. Clear-up rates were most successful for
the crimes least likely to be the subject of a carefully planned act.
Review of the trials of all people charged with murder over the same
ve-year period revealed that, for the tiny proportion who were con-
victed of murder, only 8 per cent of their convictions stood after
appeal. The low conviction rate was most pronounced in gang- and
drug-related cases. Convictions were more likely to be for man-
slaughter than for murder.
Thus, the death penalty is infrequently applied in Trinidad and
Tobago. Paradoxically, the type of murder that is least likely to be
planned in advance and most likely to be committed in the heat of
emotion, without consideration of the threat of later punishment, is
the type most likely to end up with a conviction for murder. Even
in this category, as much as 60 per cent of killings do not result in
a murder conviction. Studies in other parts of the Caribbean also
indicate a low percentage of murder convictions. In the Bahamas,
for instance, while 333 murders were recorded between 2005 and
2009, only 10 cases resulted in murder convictions.
65
International law calls for the death penalty, if it is retained, to be
used only in the worst cases.
66
But this is certainly not the case in the
65 Amnesty International, Caribbean: Death Penalty in the English-Speaking Caribbean, p. 27.
66 The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Article 6(2), states: “In countries
which have not abolished the death penalty, sentence of death may be imposed only for the
most serious crimes.
Caribbean, where all available studies indicate that it is both infre-
quently and arbitrarily applied. The study summarized above likened
the possibility of receiving the death penalty in Trinidad and Tobago
to that of being struck by lightning.
67
This underlines the vagaries and
weaknesses of the criminal justice system and its profound unfairness
in capital cases.
CONCLUSION
Across much of the Commonwealth Caribbean, the bulk of killings
go unsolved, the majority of convictions are overturned on appeal,
the administration of justice is slow, and low-income suspects face
severe barriers to their ability to present an eective defence. There
is strong evidence that the death penalty disproportionately aects
the weak, poor and vulnerable. Caribbean states need to strengthen
their criminal justice systems at both the investigative and trial levels;
retaining the death penalty is unlikely to help them address their
rising crime rates.
67 Hood and Seemungal, A Rare and Arbitrary Fate, paragraph 98.
150 151
THE DEATH PENALTY IN INDIA:
DOWN A SLIPPERY SLOPE
Usha Ramanathan
1
The death sentence has generated a great deal of agonized deliberation
over the decades. It has been in the Indian Penal Code since 1860 and
the Criminal Procedure Code since 1898. India’s Constitution, pro-
mulgated in 1950, provided for the continuance of “all the law in force
in the territory of India immediately before the commencement of
this Constitution … until altered or repealed or amended” and “subject
to the other provisions of this Constitution” (Article 372). Article 21
of the Constitution reads: “No person shall be deprived of his life or
personal liberty except according to procedure established by law.
This has been understood to mean that not only personal liberty, but life
itself, may be taken so long as it is “according to procedure established by
law. This article in the Constitution does not establish the limits within
which this power over life and death is to be exercised; the challenge to it
has thus focused on judicial discretion, arbitrariness, delay, the method of
execution and how the president is to exercise clemency powers.
From 1950 to the early 1970s, Parliament concerned itself with taming
the death penalty. In the early 1960s, abolition of the death sentence
was raised in Parliament and sent to the Law Commission to be delib-
erated upon. Since then, the Supreme Court has addressed it, in part
because of abolitionist judges on the bench who argued that the death
sentence was unconstitutional, and partly because of the vagaries that
judicial discretion in sentencing brought with it.
2
And since the 1980s,
Parliament has altered its position, introducing the death sentence in the
Terrorism and Disruptive Activities (Prevention) Act 1985, the Narcot-
ics and Psychotropic Substances Act 1985 and its amendment in 1988,
section 364-A of the Indian Penal Code, which made kidnapping for
1 Usha Ramanathan is an independent law researcher working on the jurisprudence of law,
poverty and rights.
2
Jagmohan Singh v. State of Uttar Pradesh judgment dated 3 October 1972, reported in AIR 1973
SC 947, which was a decision of a bench of ve judges, Rajendra Prasad v. State of Uttar Pradesh
judgment dated 9 February 1979, reported in AIR 1979 SC 916, and Dalbir Singh v. State of Pun-
jab, with diering opinions by two judges on the death sentence in judgment dated 4 May 1979,
reported in AIR 1979 SC 1384, illustrate the turmoil in the court on the issue of the death penalty.
ransom punishable by death by amendment in 1993, the Prevention of
Terrorism Act 2002, and the Unlawful Activities (Prevention) Act 1967
as amended in 2004 for “commission of a terrorist act . . . if such act has
resulted in the death of any person.
3
State legislatures have passed laws,
such as the Maharashtra Control of Organised Crime Act 1999, that
prescribe the death penalty where death results during the commission
of organized crime.
4
Until 1955, where an oence in the Penal Code was punishable by
either death or life imprisonment, the death sentence was the rule, and
a court imposing the lesser sentence was required, under Section 367
of the Criminal Procedure Code 1898, to set out “special reasons” for
that sentence. That requirement was repealed by Parliament in 1955.
A debate in Parliament in 1962 on abolition of the death sentence
led to the question being referred to the Law Commission for con-
sideration. The Law Commission concluded in 1967 that India was
not ready for abolition.
5
Addressing the question of whether a court
should be required to explain its choice between the death penalty
and any alternate punishment, the Commission said: “The adoption
of either alternative would mean, or be construed as meaning, a leg-
islative determination that the sentence for which reasons are to be
given is to be the exception, and the other sentence is to be the rule,
and that the court should be required “to state its reasons, wherever it
awards either of the two sentences in a capital case. A later report on
3 The Terrorism and Disruptive Activities (Prevention) Act lapsed in 1995, but cases registered
under the Act continued to trial and judgment and sentence. There are still prisoners on death
row under sentence of death convicted under this Act. The kidnapping provision was chal-
lenged in the Supreme Court and referred to a larger bench of three judges in
Vikram Singh v.
Union of India in judgment dated 2 July 2013, available from http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/
imgs1.aspx?lename=40503. The matter is pending in the Supreme Court. Section 364A pre-
scribes that the court may impose the death penalty on a convict even where no death or hurt
was caused. Allegations of abuse of the provisions of Prevention of Terrorism Act resulted in the
law falling into political disrepute and being repealed by Parliament in 2004.
4 Section 3, Maharashtra Control of Organised Crime Act 1999. See also, section 3 of the Andhra
Pradesh Control of Organised Crime Act, 2001, and section 3 of the Arunachal Pradesh Con-
trol of Organised Crime Act, 2002.
5 The Law Commission of India has periodically revisited the death sentence, in 1967 in its 35th
Report (Capital Punishment), available from http://lawcommissionondia.nic.in/1-50/Re-
port35Vol1and3.pdf; in 1997 in its 156th Report on the Indian Penal Code, volume I, chapter
III, “Death penalty”, pp. 42-61, available from http://lawcommissionondia.nic.in/101-169/
Report156Vol1.pdf; in 2003 in its 187th Report on Mode of Execution of Death Sentence and
Incidental Matters, available from http://lawcommissionondia.nic.in/reports/187th%20report.
pdf. In May 2014, the Law Commission issued a Consultation Paper on Capital Punishment as
a prelude to a research project on the death penalty.
152 153
recommendations for revising the Code of Criminal Procedure 1898
reiterated this point.
6
Parliament was more categorical. The revamped Code of Crimi-
nal Procedure 1973 read: “When the conviction is for an oence
punishable with death or, in the alternative, with imprisonment for
life or imprisonment for a term of years, the judgment shall state
the reasons for the sentence awarded, and, in the case of sentence
of death, the special reasons for such sentence” (Section 354).
Parliament had decided that the death sentence would be the excep-
tion. A requirement was introduced at the same time that an accused,
upon conviction, must be heard before sentencing (Section 235).
CHALLENGES TO THE DEATH PENALTY
The court has been confronted with questions about the constitution-
ality of the death penalty since the early 1970s. In 1972, when the death
penalty was challenged as unconstitutional, the court responded with
caution about its role in deciding these matters, and about the sentence
itself. It held that the Code of Criminal Procedure 1898 prescribed the
procedures to be followed in trial and punishment, that so long as these
had not been shown to be invalid, they were valid.
7
This formalistic approach to the death sentence changed in the late
1970s. The weight of imposing a sentence of death rests on courts,
and the deep discomfort with the existence and exercise of judicial
discretion in matters of life and death has found expression in the
judgments of courts through the years.
8
6 Law Commission of India, 35th Report (Capital Punishment), pp. 254-255, paragraphs 821 and
822; Law Commission of India, 41st Report (The Code of Criminal Procedure, 1898) (1969)
volume I, p. 232, paragraph 26.10, available from http://lawcommissionondia.nic.in/1-50/Re-
port41.pdf.
7 Jagmohan Singh v. State of Uttar Pradesh in judgment dated 3 October 1972, reported in AIR
1973 SC 947.
8 See, for instance, Rajendra Prasad v. State of Uttar Pradesh judgment dated 9 February 1979,
reported in (1979) 3 SCC 646; Ediga Anamma v. State of Andhra Pradesh in judgment dated 11
February 1974, reported in (1974) 4 SCC 443; Dalbir Singh v. State of Punjab judgment dated
4 May 1979, reported in (1977) 3 SCC 745, where the majority of two judges expressed their
opposition to the death penalty while the dissenting judge said that abolition was the task of Parlia-
ment and not of the courts. Bachan Singh v. State of Punjab, reported in (1980) 1 SCC 754, was
referred on the same day, 4 May 1979, to a larger bench prompted by dierences between two judges
on the bench (which was of three judges) on whether Rajendra Prasad v. State of Uttar Pradesh,
which held that “special reasons” for imposing the death sentence must relate not only to the crime
but also to the criminal, was good law.
In 1980, a Constitution Bench of ve judges of the Supreme Court
debated the constitutionality of the death penalty.
9
Their decision
constitutes a landmark in the development of the law on the death
penalty in India. Four of the ve judges were unwilling to hold that
the death penalty was unconstitutional. But at the same time, they
adopted the “rarest of rare” standard. “A real and abiding concern
for the dignity of human life postulates resistance to taking a life
through law’s instrumentality, the court said. “That ought not to be
done save in the rarest of rare cases when the alternative option is
unquestionably foreclosed. The court was open to applying the test
of “aggravating” and “mitigating” circumstances when deciding on a
sentence, so far as that did not become a fetter on judicial discretion.
It also ruled that in “making the choice of punishment or for ascer-
taining the existence or absence of ‘special reasons’ in that context,
the Court must pay due regard both to the crime and the criminal.
10
The dissenting judge, Justice Bhagwati, held that “insofar as [the law]
provides for imposition of death penalty as an alternative to life sen-
tence it is ultra vires and void as being violative of Articles 14 and 21
of the Constitution since it does not provide any legislative guidelines
as to when life should be permitted to be extinguished by imposition
of death sentence.
11
Since then, issues such as what constitutes aggravating and mitigat-
ing circumstances, that the crime and the criminal ought both to
be considered in deciding the sentence, that hanging is a cruel and
unusual punishment, that it is not about a balance between mitigating
and aggravating circumstances but that there must be no mitigat-
ing circumstances to explain sentencing a person to death, that the
possibility of reform must be considered, and the widely varying
consequences of judicial discretion that make it a “lottery” have
challenged judicial thought.
12
Recent years, especially since 2009,
have witnessed renewed concern about the death penalty, especially
regarding judicial discretion in imposing it.
9 Bachan Singh v. State of Punjab, judgment dated 9 May 1980, reported in (1980) 2 SCC 684.
10 Ibid., paragraphs 132, 207, 201 and 199.
11 Ibid., paragraph 210.
12 Amnesty International,
Lethal Lottery: The Death Penalty in India—A Study of Supreme Court
Judgments in Death Penalty Cases 1950-2006 (London, 2008), available from www.amnesty.
org/en/library/info/ASA20/007/2008.
154 155
The “rarest of rare” standard, and the consideration of aggravating and
mitigating circumstances, have been integral parts of the law since the
pronouncement of the Constitution Bench in 1980 in the Bachan
Singh case. In 1996, in a decision of the Supreme Court in Ravji v.
State of Rajasthan
,
13
the Bachan Singh dictum was ignored and it was
held that it was “the nature and gravity of the crime but not the crim-
inal, which are germane for consideration of appropriate punishment
in a criminal trial. Two accused were given the death sentence based
on this reasoning. Seven cases that followed relied on Ravji, leading
to 13 convicts being sent to death row without applying the Bachan
Singh procedure for determining the sentence. In 2009, the court
found that the Ravji court had been in contravention of the law.
14
This meant that there were people on death row who had not been
sentenced “according to procedure established by law. In 2012, 14
former judges of the Supreme Court and the High Courts wrote to
the President of India drawing his attention to the error in the judg-
ments of the court that had sent 13 convicts to death row—including
two, Ravji Ram and Surja Ram, who had already been executed,
which the 14 former judges called the gravest miscarriage of justice
in the history of crime and punishment in independent India.
15
In 2004, Dhananjoy Chatterjee, a security guard at an apartment
block, was executed after having been convicted of the rape and
murder of a 14-year-old schoolgirl. This was believed to have
brought to an end a virtual moratorium with no executions in
almost 10 years. That is now known not to have been the case,
but at the time, the Ravji Ram and Surja Ram executions (which
13 Ravji v. State of Rajasthan, decided on 5 December 1996, reported in (1996) 2 SCC 175.
14 Santosh Kumar Satishbhushan Bariyar v. State of Maharashtra judgment dated 13 May 2009,
reported in (2009) 6 SCC 498. Two further decisions of the court—Dilip Tiwari v. State of
Maharashtra, decided on 10 December 2009, reported in (2010) 1 SCC 775, and Rajesh
Kumar v. State, decided on 28 September 2011, reported in (2011) 13 SCC 706—made the
same nding.
15 V. Venkatesan, “A case against the death penalty”, Frontline, 25 August-7 September 2012,
available from www.frontline.in/navigation/?type=static&page=archive. Since the letter
from the former judges, the President has commuted the sentence of three of the 13, and the
Governor of Orissa has done the same in a fourth instance; the mercy petition of six convicts
has been rejected by the Governor, and the matter is now pending in the Supreme Court in
three of the cases; Saibanna’s mercy petition was rejected, and his case is now pending in a writ
in the Karnataka High Court; Mohan Anna Chavan has had his mercy petition rejected by the
Governor, and the matter is now in the Ministry of Home Aairs. Information from the les of
Yug Chaudhry, lawyer, and Anup Surendranath, law teacher and researcher, personal communi-
cation, 28 July 2014.
occurred in 1996 and 1997) were not public knowledge. In the
eight years following Dhananjoy Chatterjee’s execution, there were
no further executions, at least in part because of the President not
agreeing to reject mercy petitions. Beginning in 2012, with the
hanging of Ajmal Kasab for his role in the attack in Mumbai in
November 2008, there has been a revival of executive sanction
for carrying out the death sentence. Afzal Guru, an accused in the
attack on Parliament in December 2001, was executed in February
2013. There followed a spate of rejections of mercy petitions by
the President which, but for the intervention of lawyers and civil
liberties organisations, who took the matter to the Supreme Court,
may have resulted in a steep climb in executions.
16
A decision of the
Supreme Court rst stayed the executions and then, essentially on
the ground of delay in carrying out the sentence, reduced the death
sentences to life imprisonment.
17
This has provided a much-needed
respite for those questioning the validity and fairness of this sen-
tence, but it is still some way from taking the death penalty out of
routine application, and further from doing away with it altogether.
Outside the courtroom, there has been public outrage over crime,
especially the frequency and brutality of crimes against women, par-
ticularly rape.
18
This has spilt into the courtroom, as when judges on
16 See, for instance, Mayura Janwalkar, “Dead against it”, Indian Express, 1 March 2014, available
from http://indianexpress.com/article/india/india-others/dead-against-it/. The Peoples Union for
Democratic Rights was among the petitioners who went to court to stop the executions; Shatrughan
Chauhan v. Union of India in judgment dated 21 January 2014, paragraph 2, available from
http://indiankanoon.org/doc/59968841/.
17 Shatrughan Chauhan v. Union of India in judgment dated 21 January 2014, paragraph 2, avail-
able from http://indiankanoon.org/doc/59968841/.
18 See, for example, Jiby Kattakayam, “Two admit to gang rape; anger spills over Delhi streets”,
The Hindu, 19 December 2012, available from www.thehindu.com/news/national/two-admit-
to-gangrape-anger-spills-over-delhi-streets/article4217180.ece?ref=relatedNews; “India Gate,
Raisina Hills closed for public, security beefed up”, The Hindu, 29 December 2012, available
from www.thehindu.com/news/cities/Delhi/india-gate-raisina-hills-closed-for-public-secu-
rity-beefed-up/article4252191.ece?ref=relatedNews; Betwa Sharma, “Photos: Indian court
echoes populist outcry, gives 4 rapists death sentence”, Vocativ, 11 September 2013, available
from www.vocativ.com/world/india/photos-india-demands-death-for-gang-rape-killers/;
Priyanka Kakodkar and Alok Deshpande, “Outrage in Mumbai over gang rape”, The Hindu, 20
March 2014, available from www.thehindu.com/news/national/other-states/outrage-in-mum-
bai-over-gang-rape/article5050225.ece.
“THERE IS, IN THE RESURGENCE OF THE DEATH
PENALTY, A LACK OF RESPECT FOR LIFE, FOR THE
LAW AND FOR PROCEDURE ESTABLISHED BY LAW.
Usha Ramanathan
156 157
the Nagpur bench of the Bombay High Court stated, while imposing
the death sentence on a defendant convicted of rape and 30 years
without remission on a co-defendant:
We also cannot ignore the recent amendments brought to
the Indian Penal Code on account of huge public hue and
cry that arose on account of dastardly act in the heinous and
gruesome rape and murder of Nirbhaya. The amendment as
a matter of fact echoes the sentiments of the society at large.
The sentiment of the society is glaring (sic), that such heinous
crime on hapless women are required to be dealt with an iron
hand. We have, therefore, no hesitation to hold that, in the
perception of the society it would surely be a “rarest of rare”
case wherein the death sentence is required to be imposed. .
. . As such, while deciding the present case, we will have to
keep ourselves aloof from our personal opinion as regarding
the desirability or otherwise of retaining death penalty. What
is required by us, is to decide as to whether in the perception
of the society at large, the present case is a case which can be
considered as rarest of rare case warranting death sentence.
19
Yet, there is a growing concern among judges about the use of judi-
cial discretion in deciding matters of life and death.
20
The resumption of executions in 2004 provoked much debate about
the death penalty. In June 2004, when it appeared that the date for
the execution of Dhananjoy Chatterjee might be xed, civil liberties
activists launched a series of initiatives to stop the execution, including
appealing to the President to exercise his power to commute the sen-
tence to life in prison, and going to court to halt the execution. These
eorts did not succeed, and Dhananjoy Chatterjee was hanged on 14
August 2004. Newspapers announced on 15 August, Independence
19 State of Maharashtra v. Rakesh Manohar Kamble in judgment dated 20 March 2014, pp. 109-
110 and 105, Nagpur Bench of the Bombay High Court at http://bombayhighcourt.nic.in/gen-
eratenewauth.php?auth=cGF0aD0uL2RhdGEvbmFnanVkZ2VtZW50cy8yMDE0LyZmbm-
FtZT1DUkNPTkYzMTMucGRmJnNtZmxhZz1O.
20 See, for instance, Santosh Kumar Satishbhushan Bariyar v. State of Maharashtra in judgment
dated 13 May 2009, reported in (2009) 6 SCC 498; Sangeet v. State of Haryana in judgment
dated 20 November 2012, reported in (2013) 2 SCC 452; Gurvail Singh v. State of Punjab in
judgment dated 7 February 2013, available from http://indiankanoon.org/doc/32917452/.
Day, that a virtual moratorium on the death penalty had been broken.
From June to August, there had been a urry of media reports on the
crime, the victim’s background, and the hangman.
21
Public opinion
was aroused to the point that the President, who would not sign the
death warrant for any other prisoner, signed this one.
Years later, the then President, Abdul Kalam, wrote about his sur-
prise that almost all cases of clemency “had a social and economic
bias” and that deciding the matter of clemency was one of the more
dicult tasks that he had to undertake as President. About the only
case in which he refused clemency, he said: “Of course there was one
case where I found that the lift operator (Dhananjoy Chatterjee) had
in fact committed the crime of raping and killing the girl without
doubt. In that case I armed the sentence.
22
Nothing in the Presi-
dent’s statement explained why he made an exception of Dhananjoy
Chatterjee, whose case was based on circumstantial evidence. He was
from an impoverished background in rural West Bengal.
23
He had
been on death row for 10 years and there was nothing to indicate that
he had been any trouble while in prison that would warrant anxious
concern.. The public sentiment whipped up by the media, and the
call for the execution that it engendered, could oer an explanation.
RAPE AND THE DEATH PENALTY
In this period, members of the women’s movement met to discuss
how we should respond. The Indian women’s movement has had
violence against women on its agenda, and rape in particular, since
21 “Dhananjoy’s death”, Hindustan Times, 27 December 2004 at http://www.hindustantimes.com/
news-feed/nm3/dhananjoy-s-death/article1-26259.aspx; Sujoy Dhar, “Death penalty: an Indian
hangman speaks”, National Confederation of Human Rights Organizations, India, available from
http://nchro.org/index.php?option=com_content&view=article&id=5267:death-penalty--an-in-
dian-hangman-speaks&catid=2:capital-punishment&Itemid=10; Dipannita Ghosh Biswas,
“Hangman’s tale”, India Today, 27 June 2005, available from http://indiatoday.intoday.in/story/
documentary-on-hangman-nata-mullick/1/194691.html; “Hang him and save our daughters”,
Redi.com, 30 June 2004, available from www.redi.com/news/2004/jun/30hang.htm.
22 “APJ Abdul Kalam: Pendency of death cases had social, economic bias”, Times of India, 2
July 2012, available from http://timesondia.indiatimes.com/india/APJ-Abdul-Kalam-Pen-
dency-of-death-penalty-cases-had-social-economic-bias/articleshow/14590447.cms; A.P.J. Abdul
Kalam, Turning Points: A Journey through Challenges (New Delhi, HarperCollins Publishers
India with The India Today Group, 2012). The Supreme Court judgment, Dhananjoy Chatterjee v.
State of West Bengal in judgment dated 11 January 1994, reported in (1994) 2 SCC 220, records
him as having been a security guard.
23 Suhrid Sankar Chattopadhyay, “The case of death sentence” Frontline, 14-27 August 2004,
available from www.frontline.in/static/html/2117/stories/20040827004602100.htm.
158 159
at least 1979
24
. The law on rape, and on other forms of violence,
had been amended to reect the growing concern about tolerance
of crimes such as rape—where the process re-victimised the victim,
and all too often let the perpetrator o with a light sentence. In
2002, the Home Minister said in Parliament that he would introduce
the sentence of death for rape. This set o much discussion among
women’s groups, which rejected this penalty.
25
As a practical issue,
feminists like Vina Mazumdar expressed alarm that the possibility of
a death sentence was more likely to result in the victim of rape also
being murdered so as to remove the witness. This was not protec-
tion for women. As a political issue, the women’s movement and the
human rights movement, which overlapped signicantly, agreed that
the work of the state was to protect life and liberty, and it would
be unwise to hand over the power to kill to the state—and that the
death penalty was a diversion from the real issue, safety of women and
the working of the criminal justice system in a way that stigma and
disbelief would be displaced by a process that led to a fair trial and
conviction of the oender.
This was not an isolated resort to paternalism and patriarchy to address
the issue of rape. In the latest amendment to the Indian Penal Code in
2013, Parliament again acted to prescribe the death penalty in the name
of women. Until then, where the death sentence had been imposed for
rape, it has been because the rape was accompanied by murder. Without
murder, there could be no sentence of death. The 2013 amendment
introduced the death sentence in cases in which a person who has been
previously convicted for rape, or inicts “an injury which causes the
death of the person or causes the person to be in a persistent vegetative
state, is subsequently convicted of as a repeat oence.
24 Upendra Baxi, Vasudha Dhagamwar, Raghunath Kelkar and Lotika Sarkar,`An Open Letter
to the Chief Justice of India’ published in (1979) 4 SCC (Journal) 17; the case that prompted
the Open Letter was Tukaram v. State of Maharashtra in judgment dated September 15, 1978
reported in (1979) 2 SCC 143.
25 “Advani favours death sentence for rapists”,
Times of India, 26 November 2002, available
from http://timesondia.indiatimes.com/india/Advani-favours-death-sentence-for-rapists/article-
show/29451444.cms; Laxmi Murthy, “Why L.K. Advani is wrong”, Boloji, 12 January 2003,
available from www.boloji.com/index.cfm?md=Content&sd=Articles&ArticleID=6324; “Advani
remarks, a political grandstand play”, The Hindu, 29 November 2002, available from http://hin-
du.com/2002/11/29/stories/2002112905720900.htm; “Death penalty for rapists”, news24
archives, 27 November 2002, available from www.news24.com/World/Death-penalty-for-rap-
ists-20021127.
There is a signicant prelude to this amendment. In December
2012, a young woman accompanied by a friend boarded a bus after
watching a lm and was brutally raped; she died of her injuries less
than two weeks later. There was an outpouring of anger against a
government that had paid little or no attention to the lack of safe
spaces for women in the city. The incident revealed the inadequate
approach to crime prevention, and it was suggested that the crime
could have been prevented if the police had acted when alerted. In
a bid to contain the reaction, the central government set up a com-
mittee of three people— Justice J.S. Verma, former Chief Justice
of India, Justice Leila Seth, former Chief Justice of the Himachal
Pradesh High Court, and Gopal Subramanium, a senior counsel
in the Supreme Court Bar—to report on how the law should be
changed to deal with the escalating violence against women. The
committee heard women’s groups expressly reject the introduction
of the death penalty in the name of protecting women. Its report
included the following:
Taking into account the views expressed on the subject by
an overwhelming majority of scholars, leaders of women’s
organisations, and other stakeholders, there is a strong
submission that the seeking of death penalty would be a
regressive step in the eld of sentencing and reformation.
26
The law was amended to include the death penalty despite this advice.
In April 2014 it produced the rst conviction and sentence of death,
leading a legal scholar and women’s rights activist to lament that:
The verdict, though expected, has left us with a bitter
taste and a sense of betrayal. Not only is the sentence
meted out to the young boys from impoverished back-
ground too harsh, but our fear is that it will set a bad
precedent and serve to dilute the “rarest of rare” premise
upon which a verdict of death penalty must hinge as per
our criminal jurisprudence.
26 Justice J.S. Verma (Chairperson), Report of the Committee on Amendments to Criminal Law
(2013), p. 245, paragraph 24.
160 161
While most countries are moving towards abolition of
death penalty, this is a move in the reverse direction.
27
One of those implicated in the December 2012 rape and murder was
a juvenile. The clamour to have the law amended so that a juvenile
could stand trial as an adult because of the heinous nature of the
crime also saw a case being led in the Supreme Court asking that
the age at which a person may stand trial be reduced from 18 to 16.
The Supreme Court turned down the petition, citing, among other
things, developments in international law.
28
This case is symptomatic of expressions of public ire that have now
become common. Who was this boy? A national daily newspaper who
visited his village quoted his mother as saying “I thought he was dead”:
Ever since she was told that her son had been arrested in
a gang rape case—police claim he was the most brutal of
the six—the woman has not stirred out of her home. It’s
a hut with no roof, only a plastic sheet as cover. Residents
of the village say the family of the juvenile is the poorest
among them. When The Sunday Express met the juve-
nile’s mother, she said her son used to send them Rs 600,
twice a year. But that stopped ve years ago. Neighbours
told her he had been spotted at a hotel in East Delhi where
he worked as a waiter. Later, they told her they couldn’t
nd him. She said he left the village eleven years ago. “His
father is mentally ill. He was the eldest, so he went to
Delhi to work at a hotel with some people from the village.
Rs 600, twice a year, was a big help, she said.
29
27 Flavia Agnes, “Opinion: Why I oppose death for rapists”, Mumbai Mirror, 5 April 2014, avail-
able from www.mumbaimirror.com/mumbai/cover-story/Opinion-Why-I-oppose-death-for-rapists/
articleshow/33250078.cms.
28 Subramanian Swamy v. Raju thru Member, Juvenile Justice Board, judgment dated 28 March
2014, available from http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgs1.aspx?lename=41356.
29 Prawesh Lama, “I thought he was dead, says mother of juvenile accused”, The Sunday Express,
6 January 2013, available from http://archive.indianexpress.com/news/i-thought-he-was-
dead-says-mother-of-juvenile-accused/1055151/; Matthias Williams and Arup Roychudhury,
“Delhi rape accused lived on margins of India’s boom” Reuters,12 January 2013, available
from http://in.reuters.com/article/2013/01/12/india-rape-delhi-accused-juvenile-ram-
sin-idINDEE90B01S20130112.
It is one of the tragedies reected in this episode that the police
visited the village twice after the crime: once to inform the parents
about the arrest, and a second time as part of their inquiries into his
age. In the years between his leaving home and the crime, the state
seems not to have been there. The public outcry after the crime was
directed as much at the failures of the state, but the trial and con-
viction of the four accused and the focus on the juvenile defendant
deected attention and anger to the accused and the crime.
Poverty is invariably accompanied by powerlessness in the making
of criminal law policy. The idea of post-conviction investigation is
nonexistent. Far too often the criminal justice system has failed to
produce convincing convictions. A well-respected public intellectual,
Gopalkrishna Gandhi, who has also served in the bureaucracy and
been a governor, said recently:
There has been a steady, and now a steep, decline in the
ability of the system to deal with crime. The machinery
grows, crime grows. But the latter, remaining one step ahead.
Attempts to preserve the legitimacy of the system, however,
have produced ironic phenomena such as scapegoating,
which amounts to saying “Go nd someone, anyone, but
there needs to be a conviction.”
30
TERRORISM AND THE DEATH PENALTY
In 1985, the Terrorism and Disruptive Activities (Prevention) Act
started a dilution of procedure and process in the conduct of criminal
trials. It survived till 1995, when it lost political support. In 2002,
following an attack on Parliament in December 2001, the Preven-
tion of Terrorism Act was enacted; it survived until 2004. The trials
under these laws have, however, been taken to judgment. There are
features of trial under these extraordinary laws that hold them apart
from regular law. For instance, they create special tribunals to deal
with terrorist oences. The Evidence Act 1872 makes confession to
30 Gopalkrishna Gandhi, “Eclipse at noon: shadows over India’s conscience”, D.P. Kohli Memorial
Lecture delivered on 15 April 2014 in New Delhi.
162 163
a police ocer inadmissible
31
—an implicit acknowledgment of the
prevalence of torture and coercion during investigation. But anti-ter-
ror laws make confessions to a police ocer admissible, so long as
the police ocer is of a certain rank, the presumption being that
high-ranking ocials will not be complicit in torture.
32
Disturbing decisions may result from the process. Illustratively,
Devinder Pal Singh Bhullar’s petition for clemency was rejected
by the President on 8 May 2011.
33
Bhullar’s wife then moved the
Supreme Court seeking commutation on the ground of delay and
because, while in prison, he had become mentally ill, and in keeping
with human rights norms, a person with mental illness should not be
executed. On 12 April 2013, a bench of the Supreme Court refused
relief, holding that the factor of delay in execution was inapplicable
in situations where the conviction was under the terrorism law or
similar statutes.
34
The court refused to accept the document on his
mental health condition, saying that it did not convince the court that
the convict was of unsound mind suciently to halt execution. On
31 March 2014, this decision was categorically set aside by a larger
bench of the Supreme Court,
35
but not before the vagueness in the
application of the law was revealed.
It seems clear that anti-terror laws are made in political contexts that
are invariably weighted against a distinctive community of people. In
1985, militancy in Punjab led Parliament to enact the anti-terrorism
law. People tried under this law were almost invariably Sikhs. And the
carrying out of the sentence of death could be understood to serve
the symbolic purpose of establishing that the state was dealing with
31 See Arup Bhuyan v. State of Assam judgment dated 3 February 2011, available from www.
indiankanoon.org/doc/792920/.
32 This provision, Section 15 of the Terrorist and Disruptive Activities (Prevention) Act, which
makes admissible confessions made to a police ocer, was upheld by the Supreme Court in
Kartar Singh v. State of Punjab in judgment dated 11 March 1994, reported in (1994) 3 SCC
569 even as, p. 687, paragraph 250.
33 For a brief setting out of the circumstances of Bhullar’s case, see Usha Ramanathan, “Futile
penalty”, Frontline, 25 August-7 September 2012, available from www.frontline.in/navigation/?-
type=static&page=archive.
34 Devinder Pal Singh Bhullar v. State of NCT of Delhi in judgment dated 12 April 2013, available
from http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgst.aspx?lename=40266.
35 Navneet Kaur v. State of NCT of Delhi in judgment dated 31 March 2014, available from
http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgst.aspx?lename=41363, exercising its “inherent jurisdic-
tion.” This is in the nature of a power given to the Supreme Court in the Constitution, Article 142,
for “doing complete justice.”
terror. Jinda and Sukha, who were tried and executed for the murder
of General Vaidya, were convicted on the basis of their alleged con-
fessions.
36
They refused to appeal the decision, seeing their executions
as their martyrdom. Rajoana, convicted of the assassination of the
ex-Chief Minister of Punjab, has refused to appeal or claim clemency,
writing to the Chief Justice of the High Court that “the legal system,
judicial system of this Country and the rulers of this Country have
been discriminating” and that “slavery of such system is not accept-
able to me.
37
That the death penalty has been counterproductive
in dealing with terrorist crimes is evident. Years after militancy in
Punjab had reached a quietus, the death sentences given to these
prisoners only served to reopen wounds.
The 1985 anti-terrorism law was applied in dealing with the after-
math of the assassination of former Prime Minister Rajiv Gandhi in
May 1991. A total of 26 people were tried for the crime in a special
court; all 26 were convicted and sentenced to death. The Supreme
Court later acquitted 19 of the 26 of the capital oence. One person
was acquitted altogether, and 18 others were convicted of lesser
oences and released soon after the case concluded. The sentence of
death was conrmed for four of the prisoners.
38
None of the accused
who stood trial were at the core of the conspiracy. Till 17 May 1991,
the court observed in its judgment, only three people—Sivarasan,
Subha and Dhanu—knew the object of the conspiracy, which was to
kill Rajiv Gandhi. One of them was the suicide bomber, who died
on the spot; all three were dead before they could be sent to trial. The
four people, one woman and three men, who were given the death
sentence, were peripheral participants at best. Perarivalan, for instance,
was convicted of having purchased a 9-volt battery used in the explo-
sive device that killed Rajiv Gandhi. His knowledge, according to the
court, was that a 9-volt battery can be used to detonate an explosive
device; and, although the court did not attribute knowledge of the
crime to any of the accused before 17 May 1991 (the assassination
36 State of Maharashtra v. Sukhdeo Singh judgment dated 15 July 1992, available from http://indi-
ankanoon.org/doc/1824507/.
37 Ruchi Gupta, “Why Balwant Singh Rajoana never appealed his death sentence”, Times of
India, 29 March 2012, available from http://timesondia.indiatimes.com/india/Why-Balwant-
Singh-Rajoana-never-appealed-against-his-death-sentence/articleshow/12458451.cms.
38 State through Superintendent of Police, CBI/SIT v. Nalini judgment dated 11 May 1999, report-
ed in (1999) 5 SCC 253.
164 165
was on 21 May), it declared that he was “in the thick of conspiracy.
39
The leadership in this conspiracy was seen as leading up to Sri Lankan
separatist leader Prabhakaran, but he could not be reached by the law.
The people who could be found, it appears, received the penalty
that could not be imposed on those who were truly responsible for
the assassination.
Perarivalan (Arivu) has asserted his innocence through the years. In
2006, his protestation of innocence was published as a book, An Appeal
from the Death Row: Rajiv Murder Case—The Truth Speaks, with
a series of forewords written by retired judges, senior journalists and
human rights activists. In November 2013, newspapers carried a star-
tling statement: A retired police ocer who had recorded Perarivalan’s
confession had said, in a documentary, that he had not recorded it
verbatim. V. Thiagarajan IPS (retired), who was the then CBI SP of
the Kerala Branch, said he had been assigned the task of recording
the statement of accused persons in 1991. “Arivu told me that he did
not know why they asked him to buy that [the battery]. But I did not
record that in the confessional statement. Then the investigation was in
progress, so that particular statement I did not record. Strictly speaking,
law expects you to record a statement verbatim. . . . we don’t do that in
practice, The Hindu reported him as saying.
Mr. Thiagarajan went on to explain that though he felt this
before, he could not do anything at that stage. With regard
to Arivu in particular, he always felt “a little uneasy” that
the confessional statement was not appreciated the way it
should have been. “Supercially they took it and jumped
to the conclusion. . . . they took a strong view that Arivu
knew of the killing and he bought the battery. That is not
the truth. We cannot speculate, it is very dangerous to spec-
ulate.” And that “there was subsequent internal evidence to
clearly say that Arivu had no prior knowledge that Gandhi
was going to be killed.”
40
39 Judgment of Justice D.P. Wadhwa in State through Superintendent of Police, CBI/SIT v. Nalini
judgment dated 11 May 1999, reported in (1999) 5 SCC 253.
40 S. Vijay Kumar, “Former CBI ocial says he did not record Perarivalan’s confession verbatim”,
The Hindu, 24 November 2013, available from www.thehindu.com/news/national/tamil-nadu/
former-cbi-ocial-says-he-did-not-record-perarivalans-confession-verbatim/article5384370.ece.
On 18 February 2014, the Supreme Court commuted the sentences of
the three people still under a sentence of death in connection with the
Rajiv Gandhi assassination to life imprisonment on the ground of delay.
41
In an attack on Parliament in December 2001, though all ve intrud-
ers were shot dead, four others were charged and tried for having
conspired in the attack. All four were convicted, and three were
given the death sentence. By the time the case had run its course
through the High Court and the Supreme Court,
42
two had been
acquitted, including Gilani, who had been given the death sentence
by the trial court. Shaukat had the death sentence reduced to 10
years in prison, and Afzal Guru was given the death sentence. Afzal
Guru was hanged in February 2013, in circumstances that have raised
serious questions about violations of procedure and about the ethics
of executions carried out by the court in secrecy and announced
after their occurrence.
43
Nothing more is known about who the
ve intruders were. The Home Minster said from the oor of the
Assembly that they were Pakistani terrorists, because “the dead men
looked like Pakistanis, and no further information has emerged since
then. But this resulted in troops being massed along the border in an
eyeball-to-eyeball confrontation; and the High Court increased the
sentence from life imprisonment to death for the oence of waging
war, as conspirators, because “the clouds of war with our neighbour
loomed large for a long period of time” and “the nation suered not
only an economic strain but even the trauma of an inhuman war.
44
41 T. Suthendra Raja @ Santhan v. Union of India judgment dated 18 February 2014, available
from http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgst.aspx?lename=41228. This followed a ruling earlier
in the year in the landmark case of Shatrughan Chauhan v. Union of India judgment dated 21
January 2014, reported in (2014) 3 SCC 1). The death sentence of the fourth person who had
been handed the death penalty by the courts, Nalini, was commuted to life in prison on 24 April
2000 after Sonia Gandhi, wife of the slain former Prime Minister, petitioned for clemency. Nalini
had by then had a child while in prison.
42 State v. Mohd Afzal judgment dated 29 October 2003, reported in (2003) 107 Delhi Law Times
385, available from http://indiankanoon.org/doc/1031426/; State (NCT of Delhi) v. Navjot
Sandhu judgment dated 4 August 2005, available from http://indiankanoon.org/doc/1769219/.
43 See also Nirmala George, “India’s secret executions cause concern in the wake of Mohammad
Afzal Guru hanging”, Hungton Post, 23 February 2013, available from www.hungtonpost.
com/2013/02/23/indias-secret-executions-mohammad-afzal-guru-_n_2749329.html; Usha
Ramanathan, “The disturbing truth about an execution”, The Hindu, 13 March 2013, available
from www.thehindu.com/opinion/lead/the-disturbing-truth-about-an-execution/article4501567.
ece.
44 Nirmalangshu Mukherji (2005), December 13, available from http://books.google.co.in/
books?id=PeVW26gYhsYC&printsec=frontcover&source=gbs_ge_summary_r&cad=0#v=onep-
age&q&f=false; see also, Usha Ramanathan, “A case for a public inquiry”, Frontline, 23 April-6
May 2005, available from www.frontline.in/navigation/?type=static&page=archive.
166 167
There are questions about what the death penalty has achieved in
cases such as these. Considering the role attributed to those given
the death sentence, the potential for defence seems small. There
may be an element of retribution which answers the call of the
“collective conscience” of the people—a reason that the court has
used to explain why it arms the death sentence.
45
Women’s rights
and human rights activists and others have distanced themselves
from this imagined collective,
46
even as the death penalty has indeed
become a rallying cry for those angry and rendered insecure by
a state that seems unable to ensure safety. The death penalty has
intensied controversy generated by the failures of the criminal
justice system.
47
The trial, conviction and execution of Ajmal Kasab, the sole surviving
member of the attack on Bombay in November 2008, raises some of
the same concerns as the anti-terror cases described above, but there
is more.
Ajmal Kasab was a Pakistani national who, along with nine others,
entered Bombay illegally and attacked and killed 164 people, injuring
many others. He was charged with killing seven people as well as
other oences. How is a fair trial to be ensured in an environment
that is (with reason) hostile to an accused foreigner whose country
does not extend any support—in law, language or any other way—
and whose understanding is limited by his experience and education
and by the isolation of prison life?
45 Machhi Singh v. State of Punjab judgment dated 20 July 1983, reported in (1983) 3 SCR 413,
p. 431.
46 See, for instance, Justice JS Verma (Chairperson),
Report of the Committee on Amendments to
Criminal Law (2013), p. 245, paragraph 24; Flavia Agnes, “Opinion: Why I oppose death for rap-
ists”, Mumbai Mirror, 5 April 2014, available from www.mumbaimirror.com/mumbai/cover-story/
Opinion-Why-I-oppose-death-for-rapists/articleshow/33250078.cms.
47 Voices were raised against the death sentence given to Devinder Pal Singh Bhullar in Punjab
(for example, www.siasat.pk/forum/showthread.php?175761-Bhullar-case-Akali-Dal-seeks-
PM-s-intervention-Sikh-s-Upset-in-India), Afzal Guru in Kashmir (for example, www.bbc.
com/news/world-asia-india-21406874), the Tamilnadu government’s decision to remit the
sentences of those incarcerated in connection with the Rajiv Gandhi assassination (Arundhati
Ramanathan, “Tamil Nadu decides to free Rajiv Gandhi case convicts”,
Livemint, 19 February
2014), which the Centre protested the state government did not have the authority to do, and which
has now been referred to a ve-judge bench of the Supreme Court for a decision (“SC refers case of
Rajiv Gandhi’s killers to Constitution Bench”, Tehelka, 25 April 2014, available from www.tehel-
ka.com/sc-refers-case-of-rajiv-gandhis-killers-to-constitution-bench/), Rajoana in Punjab (“India
puts Sikh radical Rajoana’s execution on hold”, BBC News, 28 March 2012, available from www.
bbc.com/news/world-asia-india-17532832).
This problem is not unique to Kasab; it is uncomfortably common,
but only the politically explosive cases seem to reach the public eye,
and this needs the attention of the international community.
That Kasab was put through the “ossication test” to establish
whether or not he was a juvenile should worry those watching the
use of the death penalty. The eects on the trial of the publicity
surrounding the case—the crime occurred in public, and parts of
his involvement were aired in the media, which raised the pitch of
public disapprobation—have yet to be fully understood. The case
presents a range of traditional fair-trial concerns, including legal
assistance and representation, defence access to documents, and lan-
guage barriers.
48
Clemency jurisdiction
The Indian Constitution gives the executive, acting through the Pres-
ident (Article 72) or the governor of a state (Article 161), the power
to commute the death sentence. The power has in recent times been
used to reject mercy petitions, clearing the way for executions.
49
The
Supreme Court has stepped in and, essentially accepting the ground
of delay, reduced the sentences from death to life.
50
In the meantime,
the record raises questions about how clemency is exercised. Bandu
Baburao Tidake’s death sentence was commuted by the President on
2 June 2012—but he had been dead since 18 October 2007; “the
report about his death apparently did not reach the Home Ministry
when it recommended his commutation.
51
No guidelines apply to
48 Mohammed Ajmal Kasab v. State of Maharashtra in judgment dated 29 August 2012, available
from http://supremecourtondia.nic.in/outtoday/39511.pdf. See also Ritesh K. Srivastava, “Legal
aid for Kasab?”, Zee News, available from http://zeenews.india.com/MumbaiTerror/story.aspx-
?aid=498251; V. Venkatesan, “Gaps in Kasab case”, Frontline, 3-16 November 2012, available
from www.frontline.in/static/html/2922/stories/20121116292203700.htm.
49 Bharti Jain, “President rejects mercy pleas of Nithari killer, 5 others”, Times of India, 19 July
2014.
50 Shatrughan Chauhan v. Union of India judgment dated 21 January 2014, reported in (2014) 3
SCC 1; T. Suthendra Raja @ Santhan v. Union of India in judgment dated 18 February 2014 at
http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgst.aspx?lename=41228; Navneet Kaur v. State of NCT of
Delhi in judgment dated 31 March 2014, available from http://judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgst.
aspx?lename=41363.
51 Manoj Mitta, “After six years on death row, spared for being a juvenile”, Times of India, 21
August 2012, available from http://timesondia.indiatimes.com/india/After-six-years-on-death-
row-spared-for-being-a-juvenile/articleshow/15577973.cms; V. Venkatesan, “A case against the
death penalty”, Frontline,25 August-7 September 2012, available from www.frontline.in/static/
html/2917/stories/20120907291700400.htm.
168 169
executive clemency, and no reasons are required to be given. While
the death penalty is still on the statute book, the mercy jurisdiction
has to be re-imagined as a state responsibility. Ravji Ram and Surja
Ram were executed in 1996 and 1997 after an erroneous judgment
was reached without following the procedure established by law—a
constitutional prerequisite to depriving life. Ankush Maruti Shinde,
a convict on death row, was declared a juvenile and removed from
death row;
52
there is nothing to indicate an enquiry into why a juve-
nile was made to stand trial in a capital case.
CONCLUSION
In recent years, India has seen a number of troubling events related
to the death penalty. Two people have been executed under an order
arrived at without following the procedure established by law. An
amendment to the criminal law provides for the imposition of the
death sentence where hurt or death is threatened, even where it may
not have been caused. A law made under the pretext of protect-
ing women prescribes an alternative sentence of death for a repeat
oender who has been convicted of rape. The threat of execution of
people convicted in anti-terror cases has given rise to a politics that
exacerbates regional and community passions. A juvenile has been
made to stand trial, convicted and sent to death row, from where he
was removed only after a human rights lawyer took his matter to a
sessions court, and where the judge was willing to entertain a petition
in a matter that had already been decided by the Supreme Court.
53
The reaction to the involvement of young persons in violent crime,
including rape, has generated a clamour for reducing the age of the
juvenile from 18 to 16. A President has written, in an autobiograph-
ical account of his years in oce, that in his experience, almost all
pending cases “had a social and economic bias. Secret executions
have been carried out. The judiciary has expressed concern about the
injustices that the criminal justice system has been seen to produce,
including delay and error, while the executive has set the clock back
on executions. The Law Commission has found that there has been
no research on the death penalty, and so we know very little about its
ecacy or its absence. And a number of other ills beset the criminal
52 Venkatesan, “A case against the death penalty”.
53 Mitta, “After six years on death row, spared for being a juvenile”.
justice system, including torture in custody, poor investigative skills,
severe deciencies in legal aid and legal representation, overcrowded
dockets, delays and lack of witness protection.
At this point, the reasonableness of the death penalty is questionable.
There is no evidence that it has any deterrent eect. Whether exe-
cutions happen in secret or in public, are barely noticed or treated
as spectacles, the logic of the sentence is not evident. “Collective
conscience” seems to have substituted for all other understandings
of punishment, along with a return of retribution. The recent spate
of rejections of clemency applications threatens to lead to a spate of
executions. There is, in the resurgence of the death penalty, a lack of
respect for life, for the law and for procedure established by law.
170 171
THE DEATH PENALTY IN
BOTSWANA: BARRIERS
TO EQUAL JUSTICE
Alice Mogwe
1
Discrimination is treating people dierently based on their actual or
perceived membership in a certain group or category, “especially in a
worse way from the way in which you treat other people.
2
Exclusion
forms the basis of discrimination. In addressing the topic of discrim-
ination and the death penalty, I would like to take you on a journey
through my country, Botswana, a country that has retained the death
penalty. We have a population of about 2 million. Our most recent
execution was in 2013, when Orelesitse Thokamolelo was hanged on
27 May.
Opponents of the death penalty believe that its arbitrariness and the
inuence of socio-political and economic conditions on its imple-
mentation mean that it must be abolished. Studies have found that
the eect of race and class on human rights have serious implications
for defendants’ ability to obtain a fair trial and equal access to justice.
3
The permanence of the death penalty makes its use particularly dire
when there is any question about the fairness of the trial.
THE AFRICAN HUMAN RIGHTS CONTEXT
Botswana is a member of the African Union and the African Com-
mission on Human and People’s Rights. The right to life is protected
in the following documents:
The African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, Article
4, states, “Human beings are inviolable. Every human being
1 Alice Mogwe is director of DITSHWANELO, the Botswana Centre for Human Rights.
2
Cambridge Dictionaries Online, “Discrimination”, available from http://dictionary.cambridge.
org/us/dictionary/british/.
3 Amnesty International,
United States of America: Death by Discrimination: The Continuing Role
of Race in Capital Cases (2003); International Federation for Human Rights and Center for
Constitutional Rights, Discrimination, Torture, and Execution: A Human Rights Analysis of the
Death Penalty in California and Louisiana (2013).
shall be entitled to respect for his life and the integrity of his
person. No one may be arbitrarily deprived of this right.
The African Charter on the Rights and Welfare of the
Child, Article 5, states, “Every child has an inherent right
to life. This right shall be protected by law. . . . [the] death
sentence shall not be pronounced for crimes committed
by children.
The Protocol to the African Charter on Human and People’s
Rights on the Rights of Women in Africa, Article 4, states,
“Every woman shall be entitled to respect for her life and the
integrity and security of her person.
In 1999, the African Commission adopted a resolution at its 26th
ordinary session in Kigali, Rwanda, urging States parties to the Afri-
can Charter to consider the possibility of a death penalty moratorium
and eventual abolition. In 2006 the Working Group on the Death
Penalty was established. In October 2012, its mandate was renewed
and expanded and it was renamed the Working Group on Death
Penalty and Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Killings in Africa. It
reports twice a year to the African Commission.
The Working Group’s Study on the Question of the Death Penalty in
Africa was adopted by the African Commission at its 50th ordinary
session in 2011. The study was ocially launched in April 2012, in
collaboration with the partners of the Working Group, namely, the
International Federation for Human Rights, FIACAT and World
Coalition against the Death Penalty. One of the key strategies recom-
mended in the study is that the ACHPR should continue working
closely with United Nations organs, in particular the Oce of the
High Commissioner for Human Rights, as well as with national
human rights institutions and civil society organisations, to mobilise
action towards the abolition of the death penalty.
4
Another key strat-
egy recommended in the study is the production of a protocol to the
African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights on the abolition of
the death penalty in Africa.
5
4 Part VII, Strategies, p. vi.
5 Ibid., p. vii.
172 173
As at January 2014, the status of the death penalty in Africa could be
summed up as follows:
6
17 formally abolitionist countries: Angola, Benin, Burundi,
Cabo Verde, Côte d’Ivoire, Djibouti, Gabon, Guinea-Bissau,
Mauritius, Mozambique, Namibia, Rwanda, Sao Tome and
Principe, Senegal, Seychelles, South Africa and Togo.
24 de facto abolitionist countries (no executions for
at least 10 years—the year of the last execution is given in
parentheses): Burkina Faso (1988), Cameroon (1988), Cen-
tral African Republic (1981), Chad (2003), Comoros (1997),
Republic of the Congo (1982), Democratic Republic of the
Congo (2003), Eritrea (before independence in 1993), Ghana
(1993), Guinea (2001), Kenya (1987), Lesotho (1995), Liberia
(2000), Madagascar (1958), Malawi (1992), Mauritania (1987),
Morocco (1993), Niger (1976), Sierra Leone (1998), Swazi-
land (1982), Tanzania (1994), Tunisia (1991), Zambia (1997)
and Zimbabwe (2003).
2 retentionist countries observing a moratorium on
executions: Algeria and Mali.
11 retentionist countries: Botswana, Egypt, Equatorial
Guinea, Ethiopia, Gambia, Libya, Nigeria, Somalia, South
Sudan, Sudan and Uganda.
In Botswana, the most recent execution was in 2013. As at 13 June
2013, Botswana had executed 47 people since independence in 1966.
7
THE BOTSWANA HUMAN RIGHTS CONTEXT
Botswana is a signatory to the International Covenant on Civil
and Political Rights, which refers to the death penalty in Article 6:
“Anyone sentenced to death shall have the right to seek pardon or
commutation of the sentence. . . . Sentence of death shall not be
6 Hands O Cain (2014).
7 T. Kgalemang, “Botswana hangs 47 since independence”,
Botswana Gazette, 13 June 2013,
available from www.gazettebw.com/?p=3350.
imposed for crimes committed by persons below 18 years of age and
shall not be carried out on pregnant women. Botswana is a State
party to the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights and the
African Charter on the Rights and Welfare of the Child, but not to
the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights’ Protocol on the
Rights of Women in Africa.
The Botswana Constitution (Section 3) recognises the right to life,
liberty and security of the person and protection of the law. However,
the Penal Code provides for the death penalty for murder, treason,
instigating a foreigner to invade Botswana and committing assault
with intent to murder in the course of piracy. The Botswana Defence
Force Act also contains capital oences: aiding the enemy, cowardly
behaviour and mutiny.
The Penal Code provides that any person convicted of murder shall
be sentenced to death unless the court believes that there are exten-
uating circumstances. To determine the extenuating circumstances,
the court shall take into consideration the “standards of behaviour
of an ordinary person of the class of the community to which the
convicted person belongs” (Section 203). The Penal Code further
states that the death sentence shall not be pronounced against any
person who is under the age of 18 or pregnant women under
any circumstances (Section 26). When a woman facing a death sen-
tence can prove that she is pregnant, her sentence will be reduced to
life imprisonment.
BARRIERS TO EQUAL JUSTICE
DITSHWANELO, the Botswana Centre for Human Rights, worked
on a death penalty case (DITSHWANELO v. Attorney General of
Botswana
8
)—that exemplies some key barriers to equal justice for poor
people and ethnic minorities in Botswana. Tlhabologang Maauwe and
Gwara Brown Motswetla, two indigenous men of the Basarwa/San
ethnic group, were found guilty of the murder of a herdsman whose
ox they had killed. The Basarwa/San are generally poor and have few
economic and educational opportunities. They tend to depend for sur-
vival on employment by wealthier cattle owners and on government
8 MISCRA Case No. 2 of 1999.
174 175
assistance programmes. At the time of the murder, Botswana was expe-
riencing the severe drought of 1994-1995. The crops had failed, and
the families of the defendants had little to eat. The only animals in the
area which the families were legally allowed to hunt were squirrels,
but they had not been successful in nding any. Mr. Maauwe and Mr.
Motswetla killed a stray ox, and when the herdsman came across them
with the remains of the ox, a ght ensued and the herdsman was killed.
They were arrested for the murder.
During the original trial, some of the defendants’ court-appointed
lawyers never consulted them, a clear case of inadequate represen-
tation. The prison log books did not contain any evidence of the
lawyers visiting their clients in prison. One of the pro deo lawyers
ed Botswana amid allegations of fraud. The other initially resisted
handing over his le to DITSHWANELO, until he was informed
that a court order would be sought. The le contained no con-
sultation or trial notes. Mr. Maauwe and Mr. Motswetla had not
been informed by their legal representatives about their options
under Botswana law—an accused can choose to remain silent or
give sworn testimony subject to cross-examination or an unsworn
statement not subject to cross-examination. While the latter can be
persuasive to the court, it has less evidentiary weight than sworn
testimony. Both men had given unsworn statements without being
informed of the implications. No substantive extenuating circum-
stances were presented to the court following the handing down of
the death sentence.
9
In January 1999, DITSHWANELO intervened in the case upon
reading in the media about their impending execution. The judge
recognised that lack of resources and remoteness from centres of
development and communication can militate against an individual’s
access to human rights. He also recognised that certain “organisations
may have the ability to motivate the protection of individuals, who
may not be able to act for themselves in any meaningful way. He
consequently recognised that DITSHWANELO had legal standing
in the case.
10
9 Elizabeth Maxwell and Alice Mogwe, In the Shadow of the Noose (Gaborone, DITSHWANE-
LO, 2006), pp. 30 and 40.
10 Ibid., p. 42.
The two men were ultimately released in 2006, following the Court
of Appeal decision to grant a permanent stay, prohibiting the carrying
out of both men’s death sentences as well as any further criminal
proceedings against them in relation to the death of the herdsman.
Arrested in 1995, they were released seven years after coming to
within hours of their execution in 1999.
This case illustrates a number of the problems defendants can have
in accessing equal justice; these will be discussed further in the sec-
tions below.
Access to representation
The Constitution guarantees the right to legal representation in
criminal cases at the accused’s own expense (Section 10). State-
funded (pro deo) counsel is available for defendants charged with
a capital oence. The Government recognises that the fees paid to
counsel are not attractive compared with those that obtain in private
practice. The Registrar of the High Court has reportedly tried to
address the problem by instructing every law rm to take up one pro
deo case a year, but this has not resolved the problem of the quality
of representation for the indigent.
11
The University of Botswana runs
a legal clinic staed by law students and supervised by a law lecturer
in an attempt to ll the void, but it is poorly resourced. A few NGOs
provide extremely limited legal aid for the indigent. In 2011, a State-
funded Legal Aid Project was established. It is, however, limited to
civil matters.
The indigent experience discrimination as they are forced to rely
on a legal system to which their access is limited because of their
poverty and poor education. They are dependent on the pro deo
system, which tends not to attract skilled, experienced and commit-
ted lawyers. Senior lawyers tend to refer pro deo cases to their junior
partners. The role of non-governmental organisations is critical in
facilitating access to justice for the poor.
11 Botswana Initial Report to the United Nations Committee on Civil and Political Rights, 12 Sep-
tember 2005, Article 6 (Right to Life), p. 42.
176 177
Transparency of clemency proceedings
The Constitution (Sections 53 and 54) provides for appeal to the
President for the commutation of the death sentence on the advice
of the Advisory Committee on the Prerogative of Mercy. Neither the
appellant nor his or her legal representative have the right to appear
before the Committee. The lawyers and families of the appellant learn
of the outcome of an unsuccessful appeal through the announcement
of the execution after it has been conducted.
In 1998, DITSHWANELO
wrote to the Commissioner of
Prisons to enquire about the
outcome of the clemency pro-
cess of Mr. Maauwe and Mr.
Motswetla. The response from
the Commissioner of Prisons
was that such information was
classied.
12
The secrecy sur-
rounding the clemency process renders it a ritualistic process with
little substantive signicance for those seeking mercy. There has been
only one reported case of a commutation of a death sentence to a life
sentence since independence in 1966; this occurred in 1975.
13
In the case of Lehlohonolo Bernard Kobedi v. the State Court of Appeal,
14
Mr.Kobedi’s new legal representative presented new ballistic evidence
that proved that he could not have committed the murder. However,
according to the rules of the court, that evidence ought to have been
presented to the lower court, and it was not admissible. The Court
declared itself “functus ocio, or unable to act further in the case, and
advised that the appellant seek mercy from the President. The request
for mercy was not successful, and Mr. Kobedi was executed.
Defendants represented by inexperienced counsel, who lack the resources
and commitment to adequately prepare for capital cases, experience dis-
crimination as they have less chance of receiving a fair trial. Even an
12 Ibid., p. 32.
13
Botswana Initial Report to the United Nations Committee on Civil and Political Rights, p. 43.
14 Criminal Appeal No. 25 of 2001, High Court Criminal Trial No. F.29 of 1997.
“DISCRIMINATION
IS A PROBLEM IN
THE APPLICATION
OF THE DEATH
PENALTY AROUND
THE WORLD.
Alice Mogwe
ideal judicial system is run by human beings, and all humans are fallible.
A clemency process provides an essential “fail-safe.
15
But in Botswana,
the exercise of the prerogative of mercy (clemency) is not guided by any
publicly accessible procedures or restricted by rules of evidence.
Language barriers
Botswana is home to more than 30 ethnic groups. Its ocial language
is English and its national language is Setswana, the language of eight
of the ethnic groups. Language barriers can seriously hinder the judi-
cial process, from investigation to interrogation and appearance in
court. In the case of DITSHWANELO v. Attorney General of Botswa-
na,
16
the prisoners, Mr. Maauwe and Mr. Motswetla, were illiterate
and did not know their exact dates of birth. They could understand
some words of the national language, Setswana, but spoke neither
Setswana nor the other commonly spoken language of their area,
iKalanga. They spoke Secherechere, a dialect of Sesarwa.
They argued that they had not understood the confession documents
on which they had axed their thumbprints, had not been able to
communicate with the authorising ocer when their statements
were taken in Setswana, and had complied when asked for their
thumbprints because they feared the police. The three-way commu-
nication in the High Court—Sesarwa to Setswana to English—used
a dialect of Sesarwa unknown to them. They had a letter written
on their behalf stating, “We are Basarwa and we do not understand
Setswana well. Therefore we had diculties in communication at the
High Court. The Registrar of the High Court received the letter,
but neither assigned them a new lawyer nor placed the letter in their
le for the Court of Appeal. It was during the case that the issue of
poor interpretation, inability to communicate and the letter that had
been written about it were discovered and raised.
Members of ethnic minorities who cannot communicate in the lan-
guage(s) of the court depend on the help of skilled translators. Often
these are not provided. Their combination of poverty and illiteracy
15 H errera v. Collins, 506 US 390 (1993), quoted in Amnesty International, United States of America:
Death by Discrimination.
16 MISCRA Case No. 2 of 1999.
178 179
made it impossible for Mr. Maauwe and Mr.Motswetla to meaning-
fully engage the legal system and receive a fair trial.
Race
Race has not been a striking factor in most capital cases in Botswana
courts. There has, however, tended to be a noticeably dierent reaction
when a white person is involved in a case, whether as a victim or a
perpetrator. In 2001, South African Mariette Bosch was executed after
being found guilty of murdering the wife of a man with whom she was
engaged in a romantic aair. They married three months after the murder.
Ms. Bosch was the rst white person to be executed in Botswana. Local
lawyer Themba Joina, whose black male client Lehlohonolo Kobedi (also
a non-national, from Lesotho), was on death row at the time, said, “The
foreign media were only concerned about Bosch because she is white.
Since she was hanged, we don’t see cameras in Botswana anymore.
17
There was a marked dierence in international reaction to the execution
of Ms. Bosch, including from international human rights organisations,
compared with other executions before and since.
Secrecy of executions
Those on death row in Botswana suer due to the secrecy with
which the death penalty is carried out. The accused is entitled to a
minimum of 24 hours notice. In many cases, legal representatives and
family members are not notied prior to the execution. In one case,
while the legal representatives were preparing a request for clemency,
the accused were executed. Lehlohonolo Kobedi, whose case was dis-
cussed above, had written asking DITSHWANELO to visit him on
death row. The Commissioner of Prisons refused to grant permission
for this visit, and Mr. Kobedi was executed soon thereafter.
Other challenges to fair and equal access
Additional concerns include delays in processing of cases and phys-
ical distance from urban areas where most legal services are located.
17 Executed Today, “2003: Lehlohonolo Bernard Kobedi”, archive for 18 July 2013, available
from www.ExecutedToday.com. Mr. Joina’s client was Lehlohonolo Kobedi, whose case was
discussed above.
Families of victims of murder and families of the executed are
excluded from the judicial process. Various groups working with
families of victims have raised concerns about the death penalty and
its inability to bring them closure. Others have expressed serious dis-
comfort at not being kept informed about the progress of the cases
of their family members. Within a retributive justice system, there is
little room for restoration or restitution.
CONCLUSION
Discrimination is a problem in the application of the death penalty
around the world. It remains an open question whether it will be
possible to end discrimination without systemic change concerning
the fundamental issue of access to justice for all.
The call by the African Commission on Human and People’s Rights
for a moratorium on the death penalty appears to be bearing fruit
in Africa. With only 11 of the continent’s 54 states actively retaining
the death penalty, there is hope that the message will be heard that it
violates the most fundamental of all human rights. Commitment to
sustainable people-centred development, based on promotion, pro-
tection and respect for human rights, is key to ensuring that the full
range of rights—civil, political, socio-economic and cultural, includ-
ing the right to life—are enjoyed by all citizens. As United Nations
Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon has said, “The right to life is the
most fundamental of all human rights.
18
18 Ban Ki-moon, “Secretary-General’s message to the International Commission against the
Death Penalty”, delivered by Ms. Kyung-wha Kang, Deputy High Commissioner for Human
Rights, Geneva, Switzerland, 25 February 2013.
180 181
THE DEATH PENALTY IN
ZIMBABWE: LEGAL AMBIGUITIES
Innocent Maja
1
On 20 December 2012, the United Nations General Assembly passed
Resolution 67/176, Moratorium on the Use of the Death Penalty.
It recommended among other things reduction of the number of
oences punishable by death, restrictions on who can be sentenced to
death and a moratorium on executions. This paper analyses the extent
to which Zimbabwe, which retains the death penalty,
2
has heeded
these recommendations.
REDUCTION OF THE NUMBER OF OFFENCES
PUNISHABLE BY DEATH
Since independence, the list of crimes punishable by death has
changed several times. The 1979 Constitution applied the death pen-
alty to nine oences (including attempted murder, rape and political
violence). This list was limited to murder, treason and mutiny in the
1990s.
3
In the year 2000, the Genocide Act extended the imposi-
tion of the death penalty to genocide crimes that result in death. In
2004 the Criminal Law (Codication and Reform) Act expanded
the application of the death penalty to attempted murder, incitement
or conspiracy to commit murder and terrorism-related crimes that
result in death.
However, Section 48(1) of the 2013 Constitution establishes a right
to life limited only by Section 48(2), which provides that a “law may
permit the death penalty to be imposed only on a person convicted
of murder committed in aggravating circumstances. Under Section
48(2), there is still no mandatory death penalty. The death penalty
could be established if a law were passed imposing it for murder in
1 Innocent Maja is a senior partner in Maja & Associates and a lecturer at the University of Zim-
babwe.
2 From 1980 to 2004, when the last executions were carried out, 78 people were executed.
3 Sections 20(1) and 47(2-3) of the Criminal Law (Codication and Reform) Act [Chapter 9:23]
and Section 75(1-2) of the Defence Act [Chapter 11:02].
aggravating circumstances, but passage of such a law is discretionary,
as shown by the use of the word “may.
4
At the time of this writing, no law had been passed imposing the
death penalty. Thus, technically a person convicted of murder com-
mitted in aggravating circumstances cannot be sentenced to death.
To formally abolish the death penalty, Zimbabwe could take the step,
in realigning the laws—especially the Criminal Law (Codication
and Reform) Act, the Criminal Procedure and Evidence Act and the
Defence Act—of removing all provisions relating to the death penalty
from the statute books.
RESTRICTIONS ON WHO CAN BE SENTENCED
TO DEATH
Resolution 67/176 encourages the progressive restriction of the use
of death penalty on children below age 18 and pregnant women.
Section 48(2)(c) of the Zimbabwean Constitution provides that the
death penalty must not be imposed on people who were less than
21 years old when the oense was committed, people more than
70 years old and women. Thus the potential imposition of the death
penalty is restricted to men aged between 21 and 70 who commit
murder in aggravating circumstances.
The Zimbabwean government is urged to totally abolish the death
penalty for a number of reasons:
4 This is radically dierent from the pre-2013 Constitution, under which the death penalty
was mandatory unless extenuating circumstances were proved. For instance, section 47(2) and
(3) of the Criminal Law (Codication and Reform) Act [Chapter 9:23] states that “a person
convicted of murder shall be sentenced to death unless (a)the convicted person is under the
age of eighteen years at the time of the commission of the crime; or (b) the court is of the
opinion that there are extenuating circumstances; in which event the convicted person shall
be liable to imprisonment for life or any shorter period. (3) A person convicted of attempted
murder or of incitement or conspiracy to commit murder shall be liable to be sentenced
to death or to imprisonment for life or any shorter period. Section 337 of the Criminal
Procedure and Evidence Act [Chapter 9:07] empowers the High Court to sentence to death
any person who commits murder unless there are extenuating circumstances. The lacuna that
currently exists is that these laws have not yet been revised to align with the
new Constitution.
“PEOPLE CONVICTED OF MURDER ARE
USUALLY REPRESENTED ON A PRO BONO
BASIS BY JUNIOR LAWYERS.
Innocent Maja
182 183
1. People convicted of murder are usually represented on a pro
bono basis by junior lawyers inexperienced in trial work.
Legal representation is also limited to the trial stage. This
essentially means that people convicted of murder who
cannot pay for legal representation go through the appeal
process without it.
2. Even though Section 112 of the Constitution empowers the
President to commute a sentence of death upon submission
of a mercy petition, presidential discretion in this matter is
broad. There is no right for the petitioner to be heard. Nei-
ther is the court permitted to inquire into the manner in
which the President exercises this discretion.
3. Inmates sentenced to death are kept in cells that are small
and dirty and have little ventilation and no sanitary facilities.
They use a 20-litre bucket to relieve themselves. They are
kept in solitary connement for 23 hours a day with very
limited access to the outside world. This section of the prison
is referred to as the condemned section.
5
The trauma that
death penalty inmates experience is further worsened by the
delay in executions.
4. The method of killing by hanging
6
is horrendous, inhuman,
brutal and uncivilised.
7
MORATORIUM ON EXECUTIONS
There are currently 90 male inmates on death row. The last exe-
cution was carried out in 2004 when Stephen Chidumo and
others were executed for murder. The current Minister of Justice,
Emerson Mnangagwa, is on record as opposing the death penalty
and saying that he would rather resign than sign an execution
warrant. However, there is no ocial moratorium on executions.
5 See Catholic Commission for Justice and Peace v. Attorney General and Others, 1 Zimbabwe Law
Reports 242 (1993), Supreme Court, Harare, Zimbabwe.
6 Section 339(2) of the Criminal Procedure and Evidence Act. Section 75(1) and (2) of the
Defence Act [Chapter 11:02] provides that a sentence of death passed by a court martial shall
be executed in private by a ring squad.
7 See the Tanzanian High Court decision of
R v. Mbushuu, Tanzania Law Report 146 [1994],
High Court, Dodoma, Tanzania.
Even though Zimbabwe can be deemed a de facto abolitionist
country, its refusal to adopt an ocial moratorium on executions,
coupled with the employment of an executioner in 2011, raises the
question of whether Zimbabwe intends to resume executions.
8
It is recommended that the Zimbabwean government maintain the
status quo of not executing those on death row and go a step further to
commute death sentences to either life imprisonment or a lesser penalty.
8 This fear is not misplaced. In 1995, Zimbabwe resumed executions after seven years of not
executing. It will be sad if history repeats itself.
184
“The way to restore a wrong is not through
another wrong. Rather, a counterweight is needed, so
that the more evil there is on the one side, the more
good there is on the other side.
—Mario Marazziti
185
CHAPTER 4
VALUES
This chapter, which focuses on values, contains articles by a Catholic nun who
works with prisoners on death row, two authors active in both civil society
and politics and two experts in human rights. Sister Helen demonstrates the
fruitlessness of the death penalty from the perspective of the healing process for
family members of the victims. Marazziti nds arguments against the death
penalty in the world’s religions, while Bhatti warns of its social and political
dangers. Rodley describes the evolution of Human Rights Committee’s juris-
prudence on the death penalty, while Heyns focuses on the right to life and
the way that the UN and regional bodies increasingly interpret it to reduce the
scope of the death penalty.
Helen Prejean, a Catholic nun, has for over three decades engaged in accom-
panying the condemned on death row and through this experience, has also
come to know many murder victims’ families. From her experience, wounded
and grieving families—even after many years of waiting—can never be healed
by watching the Government kill the perpetrators. What they need instead are
compassionate people who will accompany them on the long road to healing,
as well as counselling and sometimes nancial help.
Mario Marazziti, an Italian parliamentarian and aliate of the Commu-
nity of Sant’Egidio, a Christian lay association, examines the doctrines of
Buddhism, Hinduism, Judaism, Islam and Christianity as they apply to the
death penalty, looking for arguments against it. Each of these large, complex
communities of believers has an ancient tradition that has inspired both rever-
ence for life and, sometimes, support for the taking of life. But while individual
believers have sometimes chosen death, he argues, these religions’ core teachings
emphasize the sacredness of life.
For Dr. Paul Bhatti, civil society activist and former Minister for National
Harmony and Minorities Aairs in Pakistan, giving or taking a human life is
a divine prerogative. However, there are social and political arguments against
the death penalty as well. National criminal justice systems are less than
perfect, and the death penalty can be misused against political opponents. He
argues that imposing the death penalty on terrorists is dangerous, as it may
transform criminals into martyrs, justify the taking of life, and aid future
recruitment.
Parents of victim granting mercy to convicted murderer by removing the rope from around his neck and halting the execution at the last minute. © EPA/Arash Khamooshi
186 187
Nigel Rodley, member and a long time Chair of Human Rights Commit-
tee, describes the process of broadening and deepening of the human rights
consciousness that has led to the death penalty to be discussed in human
rights terms. If the state is the principal guarantor of human rights, why
would the state then deprive anyone from the inherent right to life?
Christof Heyns, the UN Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary and
arbitrary executions, and Thomas Probert, his colleague from the University
of Pretoria, point to an emerging consensus that at least the practice of exe-
cutions is no longer acceptable for the UN human rights mechanisms, leaving
states to determine the best manner in which to achieve a moratorium.
Regional organizations can act as important fora for discussion of trends
towards abolition that are more regionally, and perhaps culturally, sensitive.
DEATH PENALTY: VICTIMS’
PERSPECTIVE
Sister Helen Prejean
1
Over the three decades I have been engaged in accompanying the
condemned on death row and seeking every means I know to save
their lives, I have also come to know many murder victims’ families.
At rst, I was so intimidated by the enormity of their loss and sorrow
that I avoided them. I wondered why they would want to have any-
thing to do with me, working passionately to abolish the very penalty
they were seeking. Staying away from them was a very big mistake.
I’ve learned a lot since, and I wish to share some of what I’ve learned
with you, whom I regard as our most representative global forum to
achieve peace.
I’m pleased that you’re hosting a forum to explore the plight of
murder victims’ families vis a vis the death penalty. In my experience
I’ve seen over and over the tragic eects that government’s imposition
of death to the oenders wreaks on these families, despite the popular
perception (or, perhaps, at root, the political assumption) that only
the execution of the perpetrator is capable of rendering “justice” to
those harmed by their crimes.
We couldn’t have a more direct view into the tragic dynamic that
occurs between victims’ families and the death penalty than what
happened in Boston on June 24, 2015: the day of Dzhokhar Tsar-
naev’s formal sentencing to death for his participation in the Boston
Marathon bombing in 2013. As part of this proceeding, victims’ fam-
ilies are allowed to present Victim Impact statements about how the
crime has aected their lives, which is unspeakably horrible. As they
testify about their loss, grief, and traumatized lives, most believe the
death penalty is justied, and some express their deance by refusing
to call themselves “victims, determined to carry on with their lives.
Not all, however, seek death. Some want to see Mr. Tsarnaev live
1 Sister Helen is a Roman Catholic nun, a member of the Congregation of St. Joseph and a leading
American advocate for the abolition of the death penalty.
188 189
in prison for the rest of his life because they consider that a greater
punishment, others, so that over time he can come to grips with
and take responsibility for his horrendous crime. I have witnessed
this tragic scene many times: victims’ families in the public spotlight,
laying bare their pain, reliving their unspeakable trauma – all because
their testimony is a necessary part of prosecution’s decision to seek a
sentence of death.
Descending now into the complexity of the legal machinery of death
- if Mr. Tsarnaev’s fate had been left to a Massachusetts’s jury, no
death penalty would have been sought. That’s because, since the late
60s, Massachusetts has not had the death penalty. But in this case the
federal government, designating the bombings as a “terrorist” attack,
trumped state law and sought the death penalty. Consequently, during
the trial traumatized victims’ families have had to recount and re-live
their horror over and over: once during the guilt phase, again during
the sentencing phase, and now again, at the formal sentencing. If
government prosecutors had chosen, they could have accepted the
defendant’s admission of guilt and apology and sentenced him to life
imprisonment, where he would have disappeared behind prison walls,
and victims’ families would seldom if ever hear his name again. But
now on the news they will hear his name again and again as the years
of appeals drag on, which capital cases inevitably bring in their wake.
In an eort to avoid this very situation, after Mr. Tsarnaev was found
guilty, the Richard family, whose young son, Martin, was killed in the
bombing, made a public plea on the front page of the Boston Globe
begging prosecutors, not to seek the death penalty. To no avail.
My state, Louisiana, was the rst state to oer victims’ families the
option to witness the execution of the perpetrator convicted of kill-
ing their loved one. The rationale was straightforward: who better
than these families deserve to be ocial witnesses for the state? In my
book, Dead Man Walking, I tell of one such victim’s family, the Har-
veys, for whom the execution of Robert Lee Willie, the killer of their
daughter could not happen quickly enough. A week before Willie’s
execution in the electric chair, Vernon Harvey held his own press
conference, urging the authorities to “bring it on” and he wished he
could be the one to “pull the switch. What I’ll always remember (as
spiritual advisor to the condemned, I was also present at the execu-
tion) is that immediately after the execution, members of the media
asked Mr. Harvey if witnessing the execution had satised him, and
he said, “Anybody got any whiskey? Anybody want to dance? We
killed that SOB tonight, and I got to watch him die! Then he added:
“But you know what? The SOB died too quick. I hope he burns
in hell. And as he said this he jerked his thumb downward over and
over. As I heard him that night, I remember thinking to myself that
this poor, distraught man could have watched his daughter’s murderer
die a thousand times, and it would never be enough. And now that
the object of his hatred was dead, where could all that pent-up rage
of his go? My image of him that night is of a very thirsty man who
had just drunk a long drink of salt water.
I’ve been studying the death penalty in the U.S. for a very long time.
I keep learning about it, and one of the key things I’ve learned about
its application is that very few death sentences are actually handed
down, and then, how exceptionally few murder victims’ families ever
get to witness the execution of their loved one’s killer. And then it
is almost exclusively reserved for those who kill people of European
descent, almost never those who murder people of color. Evidently
their lives, their deaths don’t seem to matter in the same way, no out-
rage is felt at their passing, and, often enough no serious investigation
of their murders is pursued.
When we do abolish the death penalty in the U.S. and we are now on
our way toward that day as public support plummets and executions
become more and more rare, a signicant part of our enlightenment,
I believe, will be the recognition that wounded, grieving families,
after long years of waiting, can never be healed by watching as the
government kills the perpetrator. If anything, witnessing such vio-
lence only serves to re-traumatize them. Such was the testimony of
many murder victims’ families to the legislature in New Jersey as the
state set about to repeal the death penalty in 2007, the rst state to
legislatively do so in the modern era. “Don’t kill for me” they said.
“THERE’S NOTHING HONOURABLE IN KILLING
FELLOW HUMAN BEINGS WHO ARE DEFENCELESS.
Sister Helen Prejean
190 191
In my journey on this death penalty road, I have seen how the violent
process of government killings produces its own collateral victims:
among them, guards in execution squads whose job demands that
they must seize from their cells prisoners, rendered defenseless, and
forcibly strap them down onto gurneys to be killed. In my book,
Dead Man Walking, I tell the story of Major Kendall Coody in Loui-
siana, who assisted in ve executions. One day he called me into his
oce and conded that he was going to quit his job, that he couldn’t
be part of executions anymore, that he knew the crimes of the men
and how ghastly their murders were, but he said that when you’re up
close to it, when you’re the one to take an alive human being out to
kill them, and knowing that they’re defenseless and can’t ght back,
and how afterwards you come home and you can’t sleep and you
can’t eat and you know you just can’t do it anymore.
Prison wardens, whose job it is to signal the executioner to begin
the killing, are also emerging as victims of the death penalty process.
Former Florida Warden Ron McAndrew presided at three exe-
cutions, and that was more than enough for him. He now speaks
publicly, testifying openly that he is still in therapy, trying to heal from
his participation in executions and how the memory of them haunts
him still. He tells how he had taken on the job as prison warden,
believing it was an honorable profession to protect the citizens and
possibly help to restore the fractured lives of the prisoners. But pre-
siding at executions had undone him. There’s nothing honorable in
killing fellow human beings who are defenseless, he says.
What murder victims’ families really need, I’ve found out, are com-
passionate people to talk to, who will accompany them on the long
road to healing. They need counseling and sometimes nancial help
when they lose their jobs because the trauma and grief causes them
to lose focus or even the energy to get out of bed to go to work.
Parents who lose a child often also lose their marriage. Seventy per-
cent of them divorce. They need counseling and encouragement and
community support. And the siblings of murdered children all too
often slip through the cracks and are in need of attention and help.
In one grieving family I knew, the parents became so xated on the
court proceedings and getting the perpetrator executed that their
younger daughter became invisible to them. She told me that all
they cared about, all they ever talked about was getting justice for
her dead sister, and she didn’t matter anymore, and how they would
always remember the anniversary date of her sister’s death, but when
her birthday came, they never even noticed. Sometimes families
even need nancial help with funeral expenses. Most States have
Victim Compensation Funds, but they’re often meager and dicult
for families to access. And now most District Attorneys’ oces have
victims’ assistance sta, whose job it is to reach out in a supportive
way to families traumatized by murder. But murders are many and
the sheer numbers of hurting families are overwhelming. And when
DAs are more bent on chalking up capital convictions than on real
justice, the only murder victims’ families that matter to them are the
ones who agree to testify in support of the death penalty. Meanwhile,
the enormously inated cost of seeking the death penalty sucks the
coers dry, pre-empting real and eective eorts toward actual crime
prevention. Which, as I see it, is at the heart of the heart of the matter.
The most genuine help we can ever give victims’ families, the best
would be to prevent the violence and crime that makes them victims’
families in the rst place.
192 193
WORLD RELIGIONS AND
THE DEATH PENALTY
Mario Marazziti
1
After the Dalai Lama nished speaking at an event on the Capitoline
Hill in Rome, I asked him to be one of the rst signatories of the
Community of Sant’Egidio’s Appeal for a Moratorium on the Death
Penalty. He accepted immediately—he signed in green ink—and
frankly, it was no surprise. Who more than the Dalai Lama is identi-
ed with unconditional respect for life?
Buddhism, however, exists in many forms, so it is hard to say that
it has one clear message on the death penalty. And so it is with all
world religions. On the one hand, their core teachings seem to argue
strongly against taking life; on the other, religious bodies have often
vigorously supported the death penalty.
BUDDHISM
All schools of Buddhism emphasize compassion, nonviolence and
respect for human life, and they encourage their adherents to abstain
from killing or injuring any living creature. But the Buddha, while
against physical punishment in general, left no clear statement about
capital punishment.
The way to restore a wrong is not through another wrong. Rather,
a counterweight is needed, so that the more evil there is on the one
side, the more good there is on the other side. Buddhists believe in
the cycle of birth and rebirth, Samsara, and that the death penalty
will negatively aect both souls, the one who is punished and the
one who punishes. Trying to gain recompense for evil, even violent
death, by inicting further death will simply cause a greater imbal-
ance in the world; only rehabilitation has a chance to restore the
harmony in life.
1 Mario Marazziti, spokesperson for the Community of Sant’Egidio and currently a member of
the Italian legislature.
The cruel ultimate punishment has little chance of healing society
and re-establishing the law, because excessive cruelty injures the mind
of the oender and of those who administer death, whatever the
reason. Compassion cannot cope with capital punishment; if a crime
is horrible, as a last resort, the oender should be banished from the
community so as not to do any further harm.
But in many countries where Buddhism is inuential, such as Myan-
mar and Thailand, the death penalty is still legal and executions are
still carried out; the practical needs of the society have prevailed. It
seems that capital punishment and Buddhism are on two opposite
sides philosophically but not historically.
Buddhist doctrines hold nonviolence and compassion for all
life in high regard. The First Precept of Buddhism requires
individuals to abstain from injuring or killing all living
creatures and Buddha’s teaching restricts Buddhist monks
from any political involvement. Using historical documents
and interviews with contemporary authorities on Buddhist
doctrine, our research uncovered a long history of political
involvement by Buddhist monks and Buddhist support of
violence. Yet, there seems to be limited Buddhist involve-
ment in Southeast Asian countries in death penalty issues.
...
The death penalty is inconsistent with Buddhist teachings.
... Yet, evidence suggests that most Southeast Asian coun-
tries practiced capital punishment long before the Buddhist
inuence emerged in India in 400 to 500 B.C.
2
Tomoko Sasaki, a former member of the Japanese parliament, evoked
retribution: “A basic teaching [in Japanese Buddhism] is retribution.
If someone evil does something bad, he has to atone with his own life.
If you take a life, you have to give your own.
3
The concept of retri-
bution could be seen as consistent with the central concept of karma
in Buddhism, the way in which the Buddha explained inequality and
2 Leanne Fiftal Alarid and Hsiao-Ming Wang, “Mercy and punishment: Buddhism and the death
penalty”, Social Justice, vol. 28 (2001), pp. 231-247.
3 Charles Lane, “Why Japan still has the death penalty”,
Washington Post, 16 January 2005.
194 195
contradictions in the world. But capital punishment can be a deadly
interruption of the possibility of balancing the dierent karmas and
improving the world, favouring a higher level of mercy and life: a
death sentence would be a powerful obstacle to communication
between the reproductive karma, the supportive karma, the obstruc-
tive karma and the destructive karma.
When the Dalai Lama subscribed to the appeal I submitted on
behalf of the Community of Sant’Egidio in Rome, he also sub-
mitted this message, read at an event organized by Peace Center on
April 9, 1999:
The death penalty fullls a preventive function, but it
is also very clearly a form of revenge. It is an especially
severe form of punishment because it is so nal. The
human life is ended and the executed person is deprived
of the opportunity to change, to restore the harm done or
compensate for it. Before advocating execution we should
consider whether criminals are intrinsically negative and
harmful people or whether they will remain perpetually
in the same state of mind in which they committed their
crime or not. The answer, I believe, is denitely not.
However horrible the act they have committed, I believe
that everyone has the potential to improve and correct
themselves. Therefore, I am optimistic that it remains pos-
sible to deter criminal activity, and prevent such harmful
consequences of such acts in society, without having to
resort to the death penalty.
HINDUISM
“An eye for an eye makes the whole world blind. This adage of
Mahatma Gandhi, who is regarded as a sage by many Hindus and
others, is often quoted by opponents of the death penalty. India, while
home to diverse religions, is heavily inuenced by Hinduism. The
country recently restarted executions after an almost decade-long de
facto moratorium. But given the small number of executions, the
death penalty is almost non-existent.
Those who do support the death penalty give reasons that are dier-
ent from those most often heard in the West. The founder of the Hare
Krishna movement, Srila Prabhupada, said that the reason a murderer
should be condemned to death is so that “in his next life he will not
have to suer for the great sin he has committed.
4
Another Hindu
thinker has argued that
Hinduism is full of compassion and forgiveness. Leave
aside human beings; we are supposed to be kind even to
insects and animals. We are not supposed to kill a small
insect. Therefore, taking the life of a human being is a very
big issue for us. Our Hindu dharma is very clear that use
of violence against anyone is not allowed. Any other type of
punishment may be given, but we should not take anyone’s
life. Our scriptures and Vedas do not favor capital punish-
ment. They advocate the principle of non-violence.
5
That is akin to the teachings that Mahatma Gandhi made well
known, rooted in Ahimsa, a Hindu form of thinking based on
non-violence: “By birth I am a Vaishanavite, and was taught Ahimsa
in my childhood. ... In its negative form, it means not injuring any
living being, whether by body or mind. I may not therefore hurt the
person of any wrong-doer, or bear any ill will to him and so cause
mental suering.
This attitude is very nearly inscribed in the Indian Constitution,
where the death penalty is reserved for “the rarest of the rarest cases.
On the one hand, this means that the framers of the Constitution must
have approved of capital punishment; on the other hand, it suggests
that disagreement among them was strong enough that they sought
to strictly limit its use. Babasaheb Ambedkar, a primary architect of
the Indian Constitution, wanted to keep capital punishment out of
it. He said that while many people who believe in nonviolence may
not follow it in practice, “they certainly adhere to the principle of
non-violence as a moral mandate which they ought to observe as far
4 Srila Prabhupada, Bhagavad-Gita as It Is (New York, Macmillan, 1968).
5 Samvidananda Saraswati, the head of Kailam Ashram, in
Hinduism Today (October-December
2006).
196 197
as they possibly can” and therefore “the proper thing for this country
to do is to abolish the death sentence altogether.
JUDAISM
The Bible and the Talmud contain passages treating the death penalty
as legitimate and widespread: 36 crimes in the Bible are punished by
death, among them idol worship, profanation of the Sabbath, adultery,
incest and public incitement to apostasy. The Mishnah (Sanhedrin
7:1) lists the methods of execution as slaying by the sword, stoning,
burning and strangling. But it also says that a death sentence can
only be imposed after a trial before 23 judges. Other Talmudic texts
contain discussions that lead towards a denial of the right to execute,
requiring at least two witnesses to testify to something that is unlikely
in practice: both that they witnessed the brutal crime for which the
defendant is on trial, and that they had warned the defendant in
advance so that he or she had full awareness that it would incur the
death penalty. In this perspective, not even the defendant’s own con-
fession was accepted as evidence.
The Mishnah Makkot (1:10) says: “A Sanhedrin that puts a man to
death once in seven years is called destructive. Rabbi Eliezer ben Aza-
riah says: even once in seventy years. Rabbi Akiba and Rabbi Tarfon
say: had we been in the Sanhedrin none would ever have been put to
death. Rabbi Simeon ben Gamaliel says: they would have multiplied
shedders of blood in Israel.
Like Hinduism, Judaism seems to have developed a gap between
theory and practice on capital punishment. Scriptural passages
favouring the death penalty are set against the respect for human life
and the uniqueness of each life, created in the divine image and with
the sacred right to life:
One of the most striking expressions of this in Jewish
Jurisprudence is the text of the admonition recorded in the
Mishnah (Sanhedrin 4:5) given by the court to witnesses
in capital cases. “Know you, the judges would say to the
witnesses “that capital cases are not like civil cases ... for
in civil cases (if false testimony is given intentionally or
unintentionally and the defendant is unjustly convicted)
he may make nancial restitution and thus atone (for his
sin or error). While in capital cases, his blood and that of
his descendants through all eternity are upon him. For that
reason the human being was (originally) created singly; to
teach you that he who destroys one person’s life, it is consid-
ered as if he destroyed a whole world, and he who preserves
one person’s life, it is as if he has preserved a whole world.
... And to declare the greatness of the Holy One Blessed
be He, for when a human person mints coins from the one
mold they all appear identical, but the Holy One Blessed
be He “minted” every person from the mold of the rst
human being, but not one is identical to another, therefore a
person should say, the world was created for me.
6
In Orthodox Judaism, it is held that in theory the death penalty is a
just punishment for some crimes.
7
However, in practice the applica-
tion of such a punishment can only be carried out by humans whose
system of justice is nearly perfect.
When the State of Israel was founded, the Knesset ruled as a secular
body. And the Knesset decided to abolish the death penalty com-
pletely except as a punishment for genocide or treason committed in
time of war. Israel has administered capital punishment only once, to
Adolf Eichmann, a principal organizer of the Holocaust.
In the United States, the Central Conference of American Rabbis and
the Union for Reform Judaism have publicly opposed the death pen-
alty since 1959. The Union for Reform Judaism has stated: “We believe
that there is no crime for which the taking of human life by society is
justied, and that it is the obligation of society to evolve other methods
in dealing with crime. This practical approach is echoed, but strength-
ened by a refusal “both in concept and in practice” —formally stated
by the Central Conference of American Rabbis in 1979.
6 David Rosen, Judaism and Human Rights.
7 “Orthodox Judaism”,
Wikipedia, available from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Orthodox_Juda-
ism.
198 199
The Union for Reform Judaism has appealed “to our congregants
and to our co-religionists and to all who cherish God’s mercy and
love to join in eorts to eliminate this practice [capital punishment]
which lies as a stain upon civilization and our religious conscience.
ISLAM
The mercy of God is at the centre of Islam’s vision about the death
penalty. But of Arab and Islamic countries, only Albania has repealed
capital punishment. Several countries with a large Muslim popula-
tion, such as Algeria, Bosnia, Morocco, and even Pakistan, with the
largest death row in the world, have a de facto moratorium. Thus,
there is no automatic relationship between being strongly rooted in
Islam and using capital punishment.
Forgiveness is in principle always preferable to retribution, since for-
giveness and peace are crucial Koranic themes. The mainstream of
Islam prefers forgiveness and peace; the umma or Muslim community
is spread across a huge variety of nations, uniting more than one bil-
lion people with many diverse traits. In 2005, Muslim scholar Tariq
Ramadan called in Geneva for a global moratorium of executions in
the Islamic world.
The Koran (6:151) says: “Take not life, which God has made sacred,
except by way of justice and law. Some Islamic countries have estab-
lished sharia (Islamic law), while others follow secular law. The 2011
Moroccan Constitution says that Islam is the religion of the State, but
not that Morocco is an Islamic State. Article 20 says: “The right to life
is every human being’s right. In February 2013, the group Moroc-
can Parliamentarians against the Death Penalty was organized, a few
months before the Fifth World Congress against the Death Penalty
took place in June 2013 in Madrid, where the process of creating an
international network of World Parliamentarians against the Death
Penalty was begun.
In Islamic law the death penalty is related to two types of crime. One
is intentional murder. In these cases, the families of the victims are
given the option to insist on the death penalty, ask for compensation
instead, or simply forgive. Their decision is binding on the state.
The second type of death-penalty-eligible crime, according to the
Koran, includes fasad l-ardh—spreading mischief in the commu-
nity or in the land. This can have a broad meaning or a strict one,
but it includes acts thought to undermine the authority of the state
or destabilize the community. This can be a way for authoritarian
regimes to control opposition, spread terror or eliminate political
opponents. Treason, but also apostasy, terrorism, rape, piracy, adultery
and homosexual activity may fall in this group of capital crimes.
The Koran (5:32) says: “Whoever slays a soul, unless it be for man-
slaughter or for
mischief in the land,
it is as though he slew
all men; and whoever
keeps it alive, it is as
though he kept alive
all men.
Imad-ad-Dean Ahmad, the President of the Minaret of Freedom
Institute, said:
The views of American Muslims on the death penalty
vary somewhat, but the range is narrow compared to the
enormous disagreements among Christians. All Muslims
accept the permissibility of the death penalty because it
is addressed in the Qur’an. However, our views range
from those who would apply it for a moderately short list
of crimes (short compared to the enormous list of capital
crimes in the Old Testament) to those who would apply it
to a somewhat shorter list still, and nally, to those who
would call for a moratorium on the death penalty in Amer-
ica altogether.
In fact, those references in the Koran may be read as narrowing dra-
matically the circumstances in which a murderer’s life can be taken,
and as well as providing an exemption from the general prohibition
on killing a human being.
“THE CRUEL ULTIMATE
PUNISHMENT HAS LITTLE
CHANCE OF HEALING
SOCIETY.
Mario Marazziti
200 201
Many majority-Muslim countries are considering ocial steps
towards a legal moratorium, and many are already applying a de facto
moratorium. But it remains an open question whether capital pun-
ishment is structurally related to Islam. Theoretically, there is some
limited acceptance of the death penalty in the Koran. But opposition
to capital punishment is a giant leap forward compared to the habits
of the people to whom the Koran was rst addressed. Most Koranic
commentators would have diculty in accepting that the interpreta-
tion of the text may have evolved over time. But some hold that it can
and must be interpreted and that, to be faithful to the deep meaning,
an evolving interpretation is necessary.
Siti Musdah Mulia, a professor of Islamic theology and Islamic law
at the University of Jakarta, is ghting for an end to the use of the
death penalty in Indonesia, the most populous Muslim country in
the world. Indian Muslim scholar Wahiduddin Khan, a peace activist
and author of a commentary on the Koran, explained to me that if
among God’s creations, human beings are the most perfect (Koran,
Sura al-Isra’, 17:70), they must be respected without prejudice to race,
ethnicity, religion, colour, language or gender. One form of respect
for human beings is not to take their lives (Koran, 27:33; 5:32) or
cause them to suer physical or psychological pain (5:45).
Iman al-Ghazali, who died in AD 1111, said that the core objective
of Islam is to protect ve basic human rights: the rights to life, free
expression of opinions, religious freedom, reproductive health and
property, which later became known as al-kulliyah alkhamsah. In these,
Siti Musdah Mulia found a basis for acceptance of something like a
declaration of human rights and said that “the Islamic teaching is not
compatible with the death penalty.
CHRISTIANITY
From its beginning, the Christian church was marked by a strong
rejection of the death penalty and of violence. Nonviolence was part
of the moral framework of the rst generations of Christians. This
included refusal to serve in the army and was connected to refusal to
honour the Emperor as a divinity.
The Bible contains many references to killing and to crimes punish-
able by death. But even the famous eye-for-an-eye code was a way
of reducing revenge and punishment from “seventy times seven” to a
more proportionate measure. And the seal on Cain’s forehead to pro-
tect him from physical vengeance, after he killed his brother, showed
a second line of teaching that culminated in the Book of Job, where
life and the soul are in the hands of God and no one else can have
power over them. Thus, no state has the authority to take life away.
Finally, the commandment to love one’s neighbour and the Gospels’
call to break down walls between the enemy and the brother, as in
the parable of the Good Samaritan, and the invitation to forgive and
not even to say a bad word to the one who oends us, are just some
of the many reasons that the taking of human life has been considered
incompatible with Christianity.
In the fourth century AD, Roman Emperor Constantine legalized
Christianity and established a special link between religion and
politics. Beginning with the Council of Arles, military service was
no longer banned; rather, to refuse to serve in the army caused
exclusion from the sacraments. Not long afterwards, St. Augustine
introduced the concept of just war. The legitimization of the death
penalty continued in the Middle Ages. St. Thomas Aquinas argued
for it, introducing the concept of a higher good for society, which
may require the acceptance of a lesser good or an evil. Centuries
later, Martin Luther argued that the power of life and death that is
in God’s hands had been delegated to the political authorities. He
opposed the use of the death penalty for ecclesial crimes, so as not
to mingle the gospel and human rules, in which regard he diered
from other Protestant thinkers such as Calvin and Zwingli, who
considered heresy a crime with political consequences and as such
punished by ordinary laws.
With the Second Vatican Council, the Catholic Church came closer
to the original spirit of Christianity and contributed to Europe’s pro-
cess of relinquishing the death penalty. Paul VI abolished the death
penalty in the Vatican State in 1967. Its full elimination from the
Penal Law was carried out by John Paul II in 2001.
202 203
On Christmas day 1998, during the Urbi et Orbi blessing, John Paul
II called for a ban on the death penalty. On 23 January 1999, in
Nuestra Senora de Guadalupe basilica in Mexico City, while reaf-
rming the need to ght for a “culture of life ... from conception
to natural death, he launched the appeal: “Never again terrorism and
narco-tracking, never again torture and the death penalty. In St.
Louis four days later, he said “I renew the appeal . . . to end the death
penalty, which is both cruel and unnecessary.
With John Paul II there was an acceleration away from the death
penalty. While the new catechism of the Catholic Church still
acknowledges the death penalty as an option, it speaks to its practical
inutility in the presence of alternative means to guarantee security
and eective, rehabilitative punishment. Thus, the rst step has been
a practical and partial repudiation of the death penalty.
Cardinal Ratzinger, later Pope Benedict XVI, established a dierence
in moral gravity between the violation of life through euthanasia and
abortion (exclusion from the sacraments) and the violation of life
through participation in a war or in carrying out the death penalty.
John Paul II had already asked the Governor of Missouri to save the
life of a prisoner sentenced to death during his visit to the state and
inaugurated the regular intervention of the Holy See to try to stop
individual executions in the United States and elsewhere.
Nowadays the Christian churches are among the organizations with
the longest and most continuous advocacy against the death penalty.
In 2007, the Primate of the Church of England, Rowan Williams, said:
People will sometimes still speak as if the only way of
honouring the value of human life, let’s say in the case of
murder, were to take a life as a punishment. And I think
there is a contradiction in there somewhere. The culture
of life means a culture of profound respect for every life,
however much we may disapprove of actions or wish to
condemn them. The culture of life is one which is essentially
a culture of hope. And the death penalty is one of those
things which always speaks against hope.
In so many countries where the death penalty exists, it is not
the death penalty alone, it is the whole environment that
grows up around it: the environment of the condemned cell,
of the long periods where many people wait for execution.
I have been in countries where people . . . have been on
death row for 20 years. That is an inhumanity. I’ve also
been in countries where it’s quite clear that certain races,
certain classes, certain sections of the population are much
more likely to receive the death penalty than others. So we
need to remember: it’s not only the iniction of death itself,
it is everything that goes with it that dehumanizes.
Pope Francis reminded us in 2014 that our world still asks for “human
sacrices” and “laws allow to do so. He could not be clearer.
204 205
THE DEATH PENALTY AS A
HUMAN RIGHTS ISSUE
Nigel S. Rodley
1
For the rst 70 years of the 20th century, law students examined the
question of the death penalty, if their curriculum touched on it at all,
either as an ordinary criminal-justice policy issue or in the context
of theoretical conceptions of legal justice. When discussed in Parlia-
ment in the United Kingdom, the discourse fell largely within the
same paradigms: Did the ultimate penalty deter and so prevent capital
crime, and did it oer an appropriate form of justice for the grave
crimes (in practice, murder) for which it was meted out? Another key
element was public opinion: Was the public ready for abolition? The
answer to the last question was invariably negative; in fact, although
the death penalty was eectively abolished in Britain as long ago as
1965, it was not until 2015—50 years later—that public support for
the death penalty dropped below 50 per cent.
2
It seems that in any national debate on the death penalty similar
notions are in play. But a new, potent dimension has been added: the
human rights perspective. In line with a broadening and deepening
human rights consciousness that moved from marginality onto the
centre stage of international politics in the last quarter of the 20th
century, the death penalty, too, came to be analysed and discussed in
human rights terms. After all, if human rights values proclaim that
every human being has the inherent right to life, by what logic could
the state, the principal guarantor of human rights, deprive someone of
life? In the naïve words of a lapel badge of that decade: “Why do we
kill people to show that killing people is wrong?” Moreover, if Article
5 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) ordained
that “no-one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or
degrading treatment or punishment, by what mental gymnastics
could deliberately and cold-bloodedly putting someone to death be
exempted from categorization as cruel, inhuman and degrading?
1 Sir Nigel Rodley is Professor of Law and Chair of the Human Rights Centre, University of Es-
sex, and a Member and former Chairperson of the United Nations Human Rights Committee.
2 NatCen Social Research, British Social Attitudes, “Support for the death penalty falls below 50% for
the rst time, 26 March 2015, available from www.bsa.natcen.ac.uk/media-centre/latest-press-re-
leases/bsa-32-support-for-death-penalty.aspx?_ga=1.76012437.189869271.1430156008.
THE UNITED NATIONS AND THE DEATH
PENALTY
It was no accident that many of the early discussions on the death
penalty at the United Nations took place from a crime prevention
rather than a human rights perspective. The rst product of that
approach was Marc Ancel’s seminal 1962 study Capital Punishment,
the rst of several periodic studies of the practice. There is only one
explicit reference to human rights in this 68-page study:
At the end of the second world war, there was a renewed
upsurge of those humanitarian tendencies which, like the
desire to safeguard human rights and human dignity, had
been the mainspring of the movement for the abolition of
the death penalty.
3
The issue of the death penalty, then, may have been like human
rights issues, in the sense of reecting analogous humanitarian ten-
dencies, but it was not itself a human rights problem. Even in the
section of the study dealing with the “present state of the contro-
versy, Ancel only mentioned that capital punishment was “a form
of cruelty and inhumanity unworthy of a civilization which claims
to be humane.
4
This is at least resonant with the prohibition in
Article 5 of the UDHR.
The United Nations has dealt with the death penalty in theory
and as applied in practice. The human rights implications of the
(mis-)application of the death penalty have always been easy to
recognize. This has not been so true of the death penalty as an
institution. If the death penalty were acknowledged as inherently
violating human rights, then the conclusion would have to be that it
is unlawful under international law, since there is no doubt that the
human rights that are principally at issue (right to life, prohibition
of cruel punishment) are solidly grounded in international law. Yet,
for virtually all of the last century, a majority of states were reten-
tionist in law and a majority of these in practice. So, since states are
3 Marc Ancel, Capital Punishment (New York, United Nations Department of Economic and
Social Aairs, 1962), paragraph 1.
4 Marc Ancel, Capital Punishment, paragraph 227.
206 207
the framers as well as the subjects of international law, it was clear
that states were not prepared to recognize the death penalty as being
incompatible with that law.
5
From this it followed that they could
not accept an interpretation of the human rights in question that
would acknowledge that the death penalty transgressed them. This
reected a political stand-o that had rst appeared at the time of
the drafting of the UDHR itself. Article 3 of the UDHR declares,
“Everyone has the right to life, liberty and the security of person.
That is all that is said of the right to life. Voices had been raised to
bring the death penalty within its remit, but the matter was left for
further consideration in the context of drafting the International
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR).
6
In fact, the human rights dimension of the death penalty issue was
referred to as early as the rst General Assembly resolution contem-
plating abolition. This was Resolution 2857 (XXVI) in 1971, in which
the Assembly modestly armed (in operative paragraph 3) that “the
main objective to be pursued is that of progressively restricting the
number of oences for which capital punishment may be imposed,
with a view to the desirability of abolishing this punishment in all
countries. The purpose was stated as “fully to guarantee the right to
life, provided for in article 3 of the Universal Declaration of Human
Rights. This elegant language managed to invoke the values under-
lying the right to life without requiring acceptance that its current
interpretation prohibited the death penalty. At the time, there was no
consensus that the UDHR was legally binding.
The resolution was far from uncontroversial. It was adopted by a
vote of 59 in favour and 1 against, with 54 abstentions. Thus, the
armative votes barely exceeded the rest. Moreover, it remained
the high point for the next quarter of a century in United Nations
action promoting the normative proscription of the death penalty.
In 1977, General Assembly Resolution 32/61, this time accepted by
consensus, picked up the same language but dropped the phrase “in
all countries. The human rights language was moved from an oper-
ative paragraph to the preamble; but this time, by referring not only
5 See William A. Schabas, The Abolition of the Death Penalty in International Law, 3rd edition (Cam-
bridge, Cambridge University Press, 2002).
6 Lilly E. Landerer, “Capital punishment as a human rights issue before the United Nations,
Revue des droits de l’homme – Human Rights Journal, vol. 4 (1974), 511, 517-518.
to Article 3 of the UDHR but also to Article 6 of the ICCPR, the
Assembly invoked the notion of legal obligation, though evidently
a limited obligation (as discussed below), and only applicable to the
states parties to the ICCPR.
For some two decades after 1977, attempts failed even to rearm
the limited normative proscription of the death penalty achieved in
1971. A number of retentionist countries mobilized against abolition
with some success. Thus, at the Sixth United Nations Congress on
the Prevention of Crime and the Treatment of Oenders in Caracas
in 1980, a vigorous attempt by Austria and Sweden to promote aboli-
tion in a full-throated human rights framework was beaten back and
the sponsors had to withdraw the text to avoid defeat. The text would
have called for “the total abolition of capital punishment throughout
the world. The human rights perspective was framed as follows:
Capital punishment raises serious questions in relation to
respect for the dignity of all human beings and for human
rights, in particular, the right to life, which is the most
fundamental of all human rights, and the right not to be
subjected to cruel, inhuman or degrading punishment.
7
The scene had been set by the Secretary-General himself, who
opened the Congress by stating that “the taking of life of human
beings violates respect for the dignity of every person and the right to
life, as declared in the basic postulates of the United Nations.
8
Eectively the last attempt in that United Nations venue to address
the issue took place at the Eighth United Nations Crime Congress
in Havana in 1990. All that would have been sought was a rear-
mation of the language of the General Assembly resolutions of the
1970s, together with a recommendation that states consider impos-
ing a moratorium of at least three years. The draft resolution was
approved by a majority, but not the two-thirds majority needed for
adoption. By then, action on the issue had moved to the human
rights sector. The 1970s resolutions were the main abolitionist legacy,
7 UN Doc. A/CONF.87/C.1/L.1. On these and subsequent proceedings in the crime congresses
and the General Assembly, see Nigel S. Rodley and Matt Pollard, The Treatment of Prisoners under
International Law, 3rd edition (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 284-286.
8 UN Doc. A/CONF.87/9, paragraph 98.
208 209
with their invocation of the right to life but not the prohibition of
cruel punishment. The crime prevention part of the Secretariat (now
the United Nations Oce on Drugs and Crime) is still responsible
for commissioning the (now quinquennial) United Nations studies
on the death penalty.
After the disappointment at the 1980 Caracas Crime Congress, the
governments traditionally most active on the issue (Austria, Costa
Rica, Italy, Portugal and Sweden, joined by the Federal Republic
of Germany) introduced a draft optional protocol to the ICCPR,
whereby states becoming parties would commit themselves to
abolition. The ICCPR had not required states parties to abolish
the death penalty. Its Article 6(6) stated that nothing in it should be
invoked to justify non-abolition, but it did allow retentionist states
to become parties, while subjecting them to certain restrictions.
The Human Rights Committee, the expert body established to
monitor implementation of the Covenant, stated that Article 6
“refers generally to abolition in terms which strongly suggest . . . that
abolition is desirable.
9
It also asserted that “all measures of abolition
should be considered as progress in the enjoyment of the right to
life. Thus the 1980 draft was aimed at translating desirability into
legal obligation.
In 1982, the Assembly referred
the matter to the Commission on
Human Rights, which two years
later passed the buck further
down to its expert sub-body, the
Sub-Commission on Prevention
of Discrimination and Protec-
tion of Minorities. Despite not having a specic mandate to adopt a
text (as opposed to studying the idea), the Sub-Commission decided
to adopt an amended draft text on the recommendation of Special
Rapporteur Marc Bossuyt. The Sub-Commission forwarded the text
to the Commission, which referred it on, through the Economic and
Social Council to the General Assembly. The Assembly, by a majority
vote (59 votes for, 26 against and 48 abstentions), adopted the text of
9 “General comment no. 6: the right to life” (1982), reproduced in UN Doc. HRI/GEN/1/
Rev.9 (Vol. I) (2008), paragraph 6.
what is now the Second Optional Protocol [to the ICCPR] Aiming
at the Abolition of the Death Penalty.
The preamble to the Protocol refers to the right to life in language
borrowed from the Human Rights Committee’s general comment on
ICCPR Article 6; it also directly cites UDHR Article 3 and ICCPR
Article 6. It does not explicitly invoke the prohibition of cruel pun-
ishment, though it expresses the belief that abolition “contributes to
the enhancement of human rights and progressive development of
human rights. Presumably, the drafters preferred to avoid the use
of language like “cruel, inhuman or degrading” to characterize the
penal practices of states that may not yet be ready to ratify but would
be willing to abstain from voting on adoption of the text, as long as
they did not feel insulted. Meanwhile, by 1994, the Human Rights
Committee was making clear that, had Article 6 of the ICCPR not
provided for retention, Article 7’s prohibition of cruel punishments
would have been applicable.
10
Also in 1994, Italy tried unsuccessfully to get another weak abo-
litionist resolution through the General Assembly.
11
In 1997, Italy
decided to centre its eorts on the United Nations Commission
on Human Rights, where it successfully proposed a stronger text.
This repeated the earlier General Assembly call for the progressive
restriction of capitally punishable oences and establishment of a
moratorium “with a view to completely abolishing the death pen-
alty.
12
After a number of resolutions reiterating this language, by
2003 the Commission was able to make the stronger direct call, in
its Resolution 2003/67, “to abolish the death penalty completely
and, in the meantime, to establish a moratorium on executions.
It repeated the approach in its nal substantive session in 2005
(Resolution 2005/59). Like earlier initiatives, it referred to UDHR
Article 3 and ICCPR Article 6.
10 Ng v. Canada, UN Doc. CCPR/C/49/D/469/1991 (1994), paragraph 16.2; see William A.
Schabas, The Death Penalty as Cruel Treatment and Torture (Boston, Northeastern University Press,
1996).
11 States would merely have been invited to “consider” progressive restriction of the number of
capitally punishable oences and the “opportunity” of instituting a moratorium, albeit with the
ambitious goal of abolition by the year 2000; UN Doc. A/C.3/49/L.32 (1994).
12 Commission on Human Rights Resolution 1997/12—27 for, 11 against and 14 abstentions;
see Nigel S. Rodley and Matt Pollard, The Treatment of Prisoners under International Law, 286-287.
“WHY DO WE KILL
PEOPLE TO SHOW THAT
KILLING PEOPLE IS
WRONG?”
Nigel S. Rodley
210 211
The successor Human Rights Council has not so far addressed the issue.
Nor has it needed to, for the issue has now returned to the General
Assembly. In 2007, Italy successfully proposed General Assembly Reso-
lution 62/149, calling for “a moratorium on executions with a view to
abolishing the death penalty. The resolution’s preamble acknowledged
the important role of the Commission on Human Rights. While the
softening of the language on abolition to a tone reminiscent of earlier
formulations is notable, the General Assembly’s support for a morato-
rium is an important step. It was controversial, but an absolute majority
voted for it (104 for, 54 against and 29 abstentions). Since then, several
similar resolutions have been adopted, with a larger adopting major-
ity each time. The latest was General Assembly Resolution 69/186 in
2014, with 117 votes in favour, 37 against and 34 abstentions.
One other development in these resolutions has been the invocation
of human rights in general terms, without reference to any specic
right, even the right to life. The UDHR and ICCPR are invoked in
the preamble without reference to specic articles, with the state-
ments that “the use of the death penalty undermines human dignity”
and a moratorium “contributes to the enhancement and progressive
development of human rights. It is hard to evaluate the signicance
of this. On the one hand, no right is identied as being (potentially)
violated by the death penalty. On the other, the language implies that,
in addition to the right to life, other rights relating to human dignity
may be at stake. The most prominent of these would be the right not
to be subjected to torture or cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment
or punishment, which has traditionally been depicted as at the core
of the notion of human dignity.
For instance, according to Article 2
of General Assembly Resolution 3452 (XXX) of 1975, “Any act of
torture or cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment is
an oence to human dignity.
THE ROLE OF CIVIL SOCIETY
If substantial majorities of United Nations member states are now will-
ing to express themselves repeatedly in favour of abolition of the death
penalty, this must be primarily attributable to the fact that a clear major-
ity (105) of the world’s 198 states are now abolitionist for all crimes
(98) or for “ordinary crimes” (crimes not imperilling state security,
such as treason or other serious crimes committed in wartime) (7). In
comparison, in 1973, only 25 states were abolitionist. That was the year
that Amnesty International adopted a policy supporting abolition of the
death penalty, not only in political cases but also for ordinary crimes.
In 1977, Amnesty International convened a major international con-
ference on abolition of the death penalty that took place in Stockholm.
It was accompanied by a book-length report on the death penalty
worldwide, and it met while representatives of the organization were
receiving the Nobel Peace Prize in Oslo. This conuence of events led
to substantial media coverage of the issue. After that, the organization
intensied its existing collaboration with other non-governmental
organisations (NGOs) in the human rights eld to promote abolition
and, particularly important, to intervene to try to save people sentenced
to death from execution. Whatever the individual results of such actions
were, it was evident that international awareness of the issue was on the
rise. This took place within the context of a dominant human rights
discourse. NGOs had no hesitation in invoking both the right to life
and the prohibition of cruel and inhuman punishment. Human rights
discourse was beginning to play an inuential role in international
politics generally; the death penalty component of it caught this wave.
At the United Nations, NGOs did not play a powerful role in insti-
gating action, and they were unable to prevent the setbacks discussed
earlier. However, at the regional level, their role was unmistakable. In
1983, the Council of Europe adopted the Protocol to the European
Convention of Human Rights, which pledged states to abolition of
the death penalty, at least for ordinary crimes. The initiator of the
process leading to this achievement was Austrian Justice Minis-
ter Christian Broda, who had attended the Stockholm conference.
Four years later, in a speech in Strasbourg accepting the Council of
Europe’s 1987 Human Rights Prize, he said:
We owe to the World Conference against the death pen-
alty, organized in Stockholm by Amnesty International on
10-11 December 1977, the idea . . . that anyone who
opposes torture must favour abolition of the death penalty.
13
13 Council of Europe, press release, 28 January 1987, doc. D (87) 3.
212 213
Amnesty International went on to lobby Council of Europe member
states in favour of adoption (and later ratication) of the Protocol. It is
also likely that its adoption inuenced the adoption, six years later, of
the Second Optional Protocol to the ICCPR. To this extent at least,
it may be inferred that NGOs inuenced the adoption of the latter
protocol, and from a purely human rights perspective.
HUMAN RIGHTS ISSUES IN THE APPLICATION
OF THE DEATH PENALTY
The human rights dimensions of the application of the death penalty
have been more evident and less controversial. Thus, General Assem-
bly Resolution 2393 (XXIII) of 1968, invoking Articles 3 and 5 of
the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, called on governments
of retentionist countries “to ensure the most careful legal procedures
and the greatest possible safeguards for the accused in capital cases. In
1980, General Assembly Resolution 35/172 urged states “to respect
as a minimum standard the content of the provisions of articles 6, 14
and 15 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights.
The formula was followed in several subsequent resolutions.
The signicance of this was that states were being asked to respect
treaty-based standards, regardless of whether they were parties to the
treaty. Those standards involved substance as well as procedure. Article
6 requires that the death penalty be reserved for only the most serious
crimes and crimes not contrary to other provisions of the Covenant
(evidently implying those involving the exercise of the other human
rights, such as the freedoms of speech, assembly and association).
Articles 6 and 15 both prohibit retroactive punishments of any sort,
particularly in capital cases. Article 14 lays down the basic elements
of a fair trial and requires the possibility of review by a higher tri-
bunal. Article 6 also demands the possibility of seeking pardon or
commutation of sentence. And it insulates from the death penalty
people who committed crimes when they were under 18 years old,
as well as pregnant women. These standards were resumed and given
some limited elaboration in Economic and Social Council Resolu-
tion 1989/64 on Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights
of Those Facing the Death Penalty.
The case law of the Human Rights Committee is also relevant to
interpretation of the ICCPR provisions. Each of the standards lends
itself to extensive commentary, but this is not the place for that.
Rather, the message is that, to the limited extent that the death pen-
alty may still be permitted, human rights are centrally relevant to the
legitimacy of its application in practice.
Furthermore, one only has to read the other chapters of this book
to see how human rights principles are oended by the inherently
and inescapably arbitrary and discriminatory application of the death
penalty. The maintenance of the death penalty and respect for human
rights must surely soon come to be seen universally as mutually
incompatible goals.
214 215
THE RIGHT TO LIFE AND THE
PROGRESSIVE ABOLITION
OF THE DEATH PENALTY
Christof Heyns and Thomas Probert
1
By a number of measures, support for the death penalty is dimin-
ishing worldwide. There has been a slow but steady decline in the
number of states that legally recognise it.
2
The number of states that
actually practise the death penalty also continues to drop.
3
Moreover,
while the death penalty used to be a global practice, of all executions
known to have been conducted in 2014 outside of China, nearly
three-quarters took place in just three countries: Iran, Iraq and Saudi
Arabia.
4
If unconrmed reports of a drastic reduction in executions
in China over the last decade are accurate,
5
then the absolute number
of people being executed per year is also going down. If represented
as executions per capita, the trend is even more striking.
It would appear, therefore, that the death penalty is in gradual—
quite possibly terminal—decline worldwide. This chapter places this
observation in the context of the treatment of the right to life in
international law, which is evolving towards the idea that life may as
a general rule not be taken intentionally except if there is no other
1 Christof Heyns is the United Nations Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or
arbitrary executions and professor of human rights law at the University of Pretoria, where he
co-directs the Institute for International and Comparative Law in Africa. Thomas Probert is the
senior researcher of the Unlawful Killings Unit of the Centre for Human Rights at the Univer-
sity of Pretoria and a research associate at the Centre of Governance and Human Rights at the
University of Cambridge.
2 According to the classication of abolition used by Amnesty International, Fiji became the 99th
abolitionist state in early 2015.
3 According to Amnesty International, at least 22 countries were known to have carried out
executions in 2014. Though this number is the same as in 2013, and a slight increase from 21
in 2012, the trend over the last two decades has been one of decline from a high of 41 in 1995.
See Amnesty International, Death Sentences and Executions in 2014 (London, Amnesty Interna-
tional, 2015), p. 5.
4 Amnesty International do not attempt to estimate the number of people executed in China,
where the extent of the practice remains a state secret, but is thought to extend to thousands
of executions each year. Of the remaining States, Iran executed at least 289 people, Iraq at least
61, and Saudi Arabia at least 90, out of at least 607 executions worldwide. Next in number of
executions was the United States (35), followed by Sudan (at least 23) and Yemen (at least 22).
See Amnesty International, Death Sentences and Executions in 2014, p. 5.
5 Dui Ha, “China executed 2,400 people in 2013, Dui Hua”, 20 October 2014, available from
http://duihua.org/wp/?page_id=9270.
way to preserve another person’s life. This evolution is taking place
in the context of an international legal framework that imposes an
obligation on states at least progressively to work towards abolishing
the death penalty. In the context of that framework, there is a trend
among a range of international actors explicitly to turn away from
capital punishment.
In the gradual transition away from the death penalty, many have
worked in a way that was in practice abolitionist, while taking care
to note that international law was not inherently abolitionist.
6
An
understanding of the international law surrounding the right to life
(such as the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
Article 6) as being at least “progressively abolitionist” could allow
an approach that is more in line with current state practice. It thus
seems fair to say that international law is abolitionist in the sense that
it requires the abolition of the death penalty, either immediately, or
through the taking of steps in that direction. States that expand the
scope of the death penalty are not acting in conformity with their
international obligations, but so are states that maintain the status quo
and do not take measures to reduce the scope and application of this
form of punishment. This normative position has been reinforced by
important initiatives taken by regional mechanisms, which can play
a signicant role in the promotion and protection of the right to life
around the world.
THE “PROTECT LIFE” PRINCIPLE
If one proceeds from the starting point that each life is of immea-
surable value and each unwarranted loss of life is a tragedy, then it is
clear that there is no room for complacency as long as there is deadly
violence anywhere.
Yet encouragement can be taken from the gen-
eral trend worldwide towards the realisation of what might be termed
the “protect life” principle, which underlies the understanding of
the right to life in international law. This principle requires that, as a
6 The mandate of the United Nations Special Rapporteur on extrajudicial, summary or arbitrary
executions (most recently stated in July 2014 by Human Rights Council Resolution 26/12)
includes a responsibility “to monitor the implementation of existing international standards on
safeguards and restrictions relating to the imposition of capital punishment. For an example of
an interpretation of the mandate as at least formally non-abolitionist, see Philip Alston, Report
of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions on Mission to the United
States (28 May 2009) [A/HRC/11/2/Add.5], paragraph 3.
216 217
general rule, for one human being to take the life of another, the act
must as a minimum be necessary in order to save another life.
7
The
“protect life” principle is the standard posed in law enforcement and
in personal self-defence and the defence of others.
8
It is increasingly
seen as the global norm, and there is arguably increasing compliance
in practice as well.
There has thus been a gradual movement away from the historical
notion that the state could use force against its population to protect
law and order (or the sovereign power of the ruler) or to impose
other abstract values and towards the notion that it may use force
only to protect life and limb.
9
It is also possible to discern the impact of the “protect life” principle
on the application of the death penalty. Not long ago, there were few
constraints on using the death penalty to enforce state authority in
general or to punish a wide range of oences. Now, if used at all, it is
only as a punishment for the “most serious crimes, understood to be
crimes involving murder.
The contemporary approach is moving closer to the “protect life”
principle, insofar as the intentional taking of life—murder—is usually
seen as the only crime that merits the death penalty. However, this
approach still falls short of fully honouring the “protect life” princi-
ple, because the taking of life by the state comes as a punishment after
the act, and its value as a deterrent, once assumed, is now strongly
contested.
10
If the death penalty cannot be shown to prevent loss
of life, there is little justication for its potential violation of human
rights—it does not meet the “protect life” standard.
Regrettably, though the standard of “most serious crimes” is well
established in international human rights law, some states that still
7 See Principle 9 of the Basic Principles on the Use of Force and Firearms by Law Enforcement Ocials,
adopted by the Eighth United Nations Congress on the Prevention of Crime and the Treat-
ment of Oenders, Havana, Cuba, 27 August to 7 September 1990, available from www.ohchr.
org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/UseOfForceAndFirearms.aspx.
8 Christof Heyns, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions
(1 April 2014) [A/HRC/26/36], paragraphs 70-73.
9 This historical shift has been explored by theorists such as Michel Foucault, among others.
10 J. J. Donohue and J. Wolfers, “Uses and abuses of empirical evidence in the death penalty de-
bate”, Stanford Law Review, vol. 58 (2006), pp. 791-846.
impose the death penalty do so for lesser crimes, often meeting with
strong condemnation from the international community.
THE REQUIREMENT FOR PROGRESSIVE
ABOLITION UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW
The stronger the normative consensus on the “protect life” principle
grows, the more apparent it becomes that the death penalty, even if
conned to the most serious cases, does not sit easily with human
rights norms. While this tension is not new, the increasing willingness
of human rights actors to address the question of capital punishment
lends support to the contention that there is a logic of progressive
realisation (normally associated with social, economic and cultural
rights) within international law concerning the death penalty.
During the drafting of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights of 1966, the compromise between abolitionist and
retentionist states was to prohibit arbitrary deprivation of life (in para-
graph 1 of Article 6), while still carving out some space for the death
penalty (in paragraph 2) by stating that “in countries which have not
abolished the death penalty” it may be imposed only for the “most
serious crimes, subject to certain further restrictions. This exception
was expected to shrink. According to the chairperson of the drafting
group, the wording of Article 6, paragraph 2, was intended to “show
the direction” in which it was hoped that practice would move,
meaning that a “constant reappraisal” of the scope of the term would
be necessary. The wording chosen reected the expectation that the
category of permissible capital oences would narrow over the years
as the value attached to life and other human rights increased.
11
This expectation is underlined in Article 6, paragraph 6, which states
that nothing in Article 6 “shall be invoked to delay or to prevent the
abolition of capital punishment by any State Party”. The fact that the
death penalty has a foothold, albeit a shrinking one, in article 6 (2),
may thus not serve as an argument against the contention that the
modern interpretation of rights such as the right against torture, cruel
11 Roger Hood, “The enigma of the ‘most serious’ oences”, Working Paper No. 9 (Center for
Human Rights and Global Justice, New York University School of Law, 2006), p. 3. Also see
William A. Schabas, The Abolition of the Death Penalty in International Law, 3rd ed. (Cambridge,
UK, Cambridge University Press, 2002), p. 68
218 219
or inhuman dignity or treatment, or the right to dignity, demand an
end to this form of punishment.
This approach that article 6 (2) envisages the withering away of the
death penalty was armed in 1971 by the United Nations General
Assembly, which armed in Resolution 2857 (XXVI) that “in order
fully to guarantee the right to life . . . the main objective to be pursued
is that of progressively restricting the number of oenses for which
capital punishment may be imposed, with a view to the desirability
of abolishing this punishment in all countries.
While the debate continues about whether the death penalty con-
icts with the right to life, it has meanwhile become widely seen as
a violation of the right to be free from torture and cruel, inhuman
or degrading treatment or punishment, the right to equality and the
right to dignity. The debate has thus taken a practical turn, leaving the
question of whether the death penalty per se is a violation of the right
to life, and turning to the practical question of whether it can ever be
implemented without violating other human rights. Likewise, as dis-
cussed above, the mandate of the special rapporteur on extrajudicial,
summary or arbitrary executions has in the past been interpreted as
not necessarily abolitionist, instead focusing on ensuring that relevant
international safeguards are observed.
However, given the shift that has taken place in state practice, it seems
accurate to say that the mandate of the special rapporteur is at least
progressively abolitionist. For the same reason, it is no longer nec-
essary to state in an unqualied manner that the death penalty per
se is not contrary to the requirements of international law. Over the
past several years, the perspective has emerged that international law
requires the progressive abolition of the death penalty. This is not to
say that it requires immediate compliance, as is usually the case with
civil and political rights. Instead, the drafting history suggests that
international law requires at least the gradual, progressive abolition
of the death penalty, as is often the case with socio-economic rights.
The progressive-abolition perspective is further bolstered by the
language of the Second Optional Protocol to the International Cov-
enant on Civil and Political Rights of 1989, which observed that the
language of Article 6 “refers to abolition of the death penalty in terms
that strongly suggest that abolition is desirable” and underlined that
“all measures of abolition of the death penalty should be considered
as progress in the enjoyment of the right to life.
This would bring the mandate into line with most global human
rights organisations, the Secretary-General of the United Nations,
and the Oce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, all of
which are unambiguous in their calls for the end of at least the practice
of the death penalty. In July 2014, stating that the death penalty “has
no place in the 21st century, the United Nations Secretary-General
called on states to support the biennial General Assembly resolution
calling for a global moratorium on its application.
12
The language of
these resolutions has been designed to be broad and inclusive, calling
not for the abolition of the death penalty but for a moratorium on
executions with a view to future abolition. The goal of these General
Assembly resolutions thus ts the pattern described above—progres-
sive abolition.
A moratorium does not completely solve the problem of the death
penalty. The Special Rapporteur on torture and other forms of cruel,
inhuman and degrading treatment or punishment has expressed the
view that lengthy detention on death row, even if a moratorium is in
place, may constitute cruel and inhuman treatment. However, from
the perspective of the right to life, a moratorium is a very helpful
step forward; it allows the sometimes lengthy processes of legal and
constitutional reform to take place without further loss of life.
Each iteration of the General Assembly resolution has been passed
by a wider margin, reecting the progressive global movement away
from the death penalty. In 2014, 117 states voted in favour of the
resolution, an increase from 111 in 2012, 109 in 2010, 106 in 2008
and 104 in 2007.
13
The ways in which states vote on United Nations moratorium reso-
lutions has been taken into account in several instances. For example,
12 UN News Service, “Death penalty has no place in 21st century, declares UN chief”, 2 July
2014, available from www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?NewsID=48192#.U_WzhsWSySp.
13 The most recent of these resolutions, General Assembly Resolution 69/186, was adopted in
December 2014.
220 221
in 2014, the Human Rights Committee, in a decision concern-
ing extradition to Ghana, found that, although there had been no
recorded execution for more than 20 years, a de facto moratorium
did not ensure that an execution would not be carried out in the
future, citing as a consideration the fact that Ghana had not voted
for any of the United Nations resolutions calling for a moratorium.
14
On the other hand, several United Nations special rapporteurs were
concerned by executions that took place in Somalia earlier in 2015.
A statement issued through the Oce of the High Commissioner for
Human Rights drew attention to the fact that Somalia had voted for
the 2012 resolution calling for a global moratorium, and that Somalia
was therefore directly contravening its commitments at the interna-
tional level.
15
The United Nations currently regards 10 years as a suitable threshold
for a state to pass without conducting an execution before it might
be considered de-facto abolitionist. One could debate which country
is more de facto abolitionist—one that has not executed anyone for
ve years since a change of administration and in that time has voted
for three General Assembly resolutions calling for a death-penalty
moratorium, or one that has not executed anyone for 10 years but has
consistently opposed these resolutions? In either case, the subsequent
resumption of executions would be regarded as a step backwards
and—depending on the circumstances, especially regarding notice
given—possibly an arbitrary killing; but the question remains, in
which case would it be the greater surprise?
The trend towards the abolition of the death penalty is not linear, and
a number of states have resumed the death penalty or increased its
14 Human Rights Committee decision in Johnson v Ghana (2014) [CCPR/C/110/D/2177/2012]
paragraph 7.2.
15 UN News Centre, “Somalia: UN rights oce calls for moratorium after ‘hasty’ execution
of alleged murderer”, 4 April 2014, available from www.un.org/apps/news/story.asp?News-
ID=47503&Cr=death+penalty&Cr1=#.U_XvE8WSySp
scope. In the past two years, 10 countries have conducted executions
after a period of two years or more without any. In some cases—for
example, The Gambia, India and Nigeria—the practice of non-ex-
ecution had been rmly entrenched.
16
Another troubling recent
phenomenon has been the sentencing of large groups of individuals
in mass trials, which has occurred in several countries including in
Viet Nam and Egypt. This has led to serious concerns that such mass
trials violate international fair-trial standards and other safeguards.
Without a fair trial, the death penalty cannot be applied in a non-ar-
bitrary fashion.
These setbacks notwithstanding, it can still be said that the normative
shift of international law away from the death penalty is reected
and reinforced by state practice. Though the number of executions in
any given year varies (at least in part because in several jurisdictions
around the world the full statistics are not publicly available), the fact
that international law explicitly prevents states that have abolished
the death penalty from re-introducing it means that the number of
abolitionist states should always be increasing.
17
It seems likely that in the coming years a number of factors will play
a role in further reducing the space for the death penalty. Meanwhile,
there will be increased pressure on states and corporations that col-
laborate with states that carry out executions, as well as increased
pressure for transparency, since General Assembly Resolution 69/186
has called on states to release information about their use of the death
penalty. In an interconnected world there will be less room for states
to hide their practices and insulate themselves from scrutiny and pres-
sure. The fact that China has become identied as the only country
not publicly revealing its execution gures may exert pressure to
change its practice.
The increased availability of DNA testing has the potential of showing
that the death penalty has been wrongfully imposed, which under-
mines its credibility. The global visibility of botched executions and
16 See Christof Heyns, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Execu-
tions (6 August 2014) [A/69/265].
17 See Human Rights Committee decision in Piandong et al. v Philippines (no. 869/1999) CCPR/
C/70/D/869/1999 paragraph 7.4.
“TRADITIONALLY, THE DEATH PENALTY WAS THE
NORM, NOW ABOLITION IS THE NORM.
Christof Heyns and Thomas Probert
222 223
the resulting embarrassment is also likely to discourage the practice.
It will become increasingly dicult to execute someone in a manner
agreed to be humane. Hanging, shooting by ring squad, electrocu-
tion, asphyxiation and lethal injection have all in one way or another
become discredited or at least seriously questioned. But what are
the alternatives?
There seems to be a growing disbelief in the myth of deterrence.
In spite of all the opposition to the death penalty and the increased
availability of crime data, the deterrent eect of capital punishment
has not been proven. And the onus is on those who want to limit the
right to life to justify that limitation. Those relying on deterrence
alone to justify the death penalty need to address the fact that to
obtain its maximum possible deterrent eect, it would have to be
mandatory, or at least highly probable, and therefore used on a sub-
stantial scale across most categories of homicide—which is not an
option for democratic states bound by the rule of law and concern
for human rights.
18
There is increasing support for the view that the death penalty vio-
lates the prohibition of torture and cruel, inhuman and degrading
treatment or punishment. The normative perspective has shifted:
While traditionally, the death penalty was the norm, now abolition
is the norm. The onus is on those states that want to retain the death
penalty to justify their position. The increasing number of states that
have either abolished the death penalty, ceased to practice it or revised
the law to restrict its scope—often in the context of engagements
with international human rights bodies—presents a clear pattern.
This trend increases the weight of the claim that international law
requires the gradual abolition of the death penalty.
THE IMPORTANCE OF REGIONAL INITIATIVES
Regional human rights systems play an important role in the protec-
tion of the right to life, including with respect to the death penalty.
The system is a holistic unit, with each component playing a vital role.
Regional systems are in many cases closer to the people concerned
18 For a general discussion of deterrence, see Roger Hood and Carolyn Hoyle, The Death Penalty:
A Worldwide Perspective, 5th ed. (New York, Oxford University Press, 2015), chapter 9.
than the global system and, as such, are able to facilitate greater par-
ticipation in the international system and to foster its legitimacy.
19
The Council of Europe is the only regional human rights mechanism
to have achieved universal abolition in practice, through its Protocol
6 (1983) and Protocol 13 (2002). Three Council of Europe member
states, (Armenia, Azerbaijan and Poland) have abolished the death
penalty but not ratied Protocol 13. Russia has not abolished the
death penalty in law, but it has not applied it since 1999 following
a moratorium decision by its Constitutional Court.
20
In continuing
this moratorium and trying to move towards abolition, the Court has
highlighted that invitation into the Council of Europe occurred in
part because of its expressed intention to establish a moratorium and
take steps towards abolition.
21
Signicantly, from the perspective of the progressive-abolition argu-
ment advanced above, the European Court of Human Rights argued
in 2010 that the protocols, combined with state practice across the
region, “are strongly indicative that article 2 has been amended so
as to prohibit the death penalty in all circumstances.
22
In July 2014,
the Court held that “the fact that imposition and use of the death
penalty negates fundamental human rights has been recognised by
the member States of the Council of Europe.
23
This represents the
moment of realisation for a process of progressive abolition, whereby
the death penalty is declared to be a violation of the European Con-
vention despite the explicit wording adopted 60 years earlier.
Article 2(1) of the European Union Fundamental Rights Charter,
which is part of the European Union Treaty, states that “everyone has
the right to life. According to Article 2(2), the death penalty may not
be imposed or executed. Formal abolition of the death penalty is a
condition of entry into the European Union. It is also a central plank
of the human rights component of its foreign and security policy.
19 See Christof Heyns, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Execu-
tions (6 August 2014) [A/69/265].
20 Constitutional Court of the Russian Federation, Decision No. 3-P/1999 (2 February 1999).
21 Constitutional Court of the Russian Federation, Decision No. 1344-O-R/2009 (19 Novem-
ber 2009).
22 European Court of Human Rights, Al-Sadoon and Mufdhi v. UK, [no. 61498/08], 2 March 2010,
paragraph 120.
23 European Court of Human Rights, Al Nashiri v. Poland, [no. 28761/11], 24 July 2014, paragraph 577.
224 225
The Organization for Security and Co-operation in Europe also has
an admirable record: Of its 57 participating states, all but six have
abolished the death penalty, and only two—the United States and
Belarus—still carry out executions. It does not explicitly require the
abolition of the death penalty, but participating states have commit-
ted to limiting its use to the most serious crimes and in a manner
not contrary to their international commitments, and to keeping
the question of eliminating capital punishment under consideration
(agreed, respectively, in Vienna in 1989 and Copenhagen in 1990).
In addition, participating states that retain the death penalty have
pledged to ensure transparency regarding its application by making
relevant information available to the public and to other partici-
pating states (agreed at Copenhagen in 1990). The Organization’s
Oce for Democratic Institutions and Human Rights monitors the
situation regarding the death penalty in member states and produces
an annual report.
24
In Africa, 43 states have abolished the death penalty either in law
or in practice, with only 11 having conducted executions in the last
10 years. An Additional Protocol to the African Charter on Human
and Peoples’ Rights on the death penalty has been developed and
is in the process of being adopted.
25
The African Commission on
Human and Peoples’ Rights is also developing a general comment
on the right to life.
There has also been a role for sub-regional mechanisms in Africa
with respect to the death penalty. In 2014, the Community Court
of Justice of the Economic Community of West African States ruled
against Nigeria to uphold the rights of a juvenile defendant, arming
that execution of a minor and execution while an appeals process is
on-going are violations of international human rights protections.
26
In order to become a member the Community of Portuguese Lan-
guage Countries, it is necessary at least to have a moratorium on
24 Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe, Oce for Democratic Institutions and
Human Rights, The Death Penalty in the OSCE Area: Background Paper 2014 (Warsaw, 2014),
available from www.osce.org/odihr/124105.
25 Declaration of the Continental Conference on the Abolition of the Death Penalty in Africa
(the Cotonou Declaration), available from www.achpr.org/news/2014/07/d150.
26 Avocats Sans Frontières France, “West African court nds against Nigeria in abusive capital
cases”, 3 July 2014, available from www.worldcoalition.org/nigeria-ecowas-court-death-penal-
ty-human-rights-minor-appeal.html.
executions. It has been suggested that this may account for the mora-
torium announced in Equatorial Guinea in 2014. Unfortunately, two
weeks before the announcement, the government had executed at
least four people, its rst executions since 2010.
27
In the Americas, the death penalty is still legal in several countries.
However, with the exception of the United States, the region has
been execution free for several years.
28
The Protocol to the American
Convention on Human Rights to Abolish the Death Penalty has
been ratied by 13 states.The Inter-American Court of Human
Rights observed in 1983 that the imposition of the death penalty in
states which have not abolished it must strictly meet international
procedural standards; its application must be restricted to the most
serious crimes; and the personal circumstances of the defendant must
be taken into account.
29
Several rulings have held that the death
penalty may only be imposed for the most serious crimes resulting in
the loss of life.
30
The Association of Southeast Asian Nations Inter-governmental
Commission on Human Rights is developing a thematic study of the
right to life, with a particular focus on the question of a moratorium on
the death penalty. This is an important development with much potential.
The Arab Charter on Human Rights (Articles 6 and 7) established
safeguards regarding the application of the death penalty—that it be
imposed only for the most serious crimes, and always with the right to
seek pardon or commutation, that under no circumstances could it be
applied for political oenses, and that it could not be inicted on those
under 18 or pregnant or nursing mothers.
27 Amnesty International, “Equatorial Guinea: executions just weeks before announcement
of a ‘temporary moratorium’ on the death penalty raise serious questions”, 26 March
2014, available from www.amnesty.org/en/documents/document/?indexNumber=A-
FR24%2F001%2F2014&language=en.
28 The United States ranks fth in the world in terms of number of executions, but within the
country, there is signicant variation. In 2015 Nebraska became the 19th state (in addition to
the District of Columbia) to abolish the death penalty. Governors in Colorado, Oregon, Penn-
sylvania and Washington have also established moratoria. Another ve states, in addition to the
federal government and the US military, have not conducted an execution for 10 years and by
some measures might be considered abolitionist in practice.
29 Inter-American Court of Human Rights, Advisory Opinion OC-3/83 (1983)paragraph 55.
30 Inter-American Court of Human Rights, Hilaire, Constantine and Benjamin et al. v Trinidad and
Tobago, 21 June 2002, IACHR Series C No 94; Dacosta Cadogan v Barbados, Case 1460-01,
Report No. 7/08, IACHR Series L/V/II.130 Doc. 22, rev. 1 (2008); Raxcacó-Reyes v Guatemala,
6 February 2006, IACHR Series C No 143.
226 227
culturally, sensitive. They are forums in which individual member
states often feel more prominently represented. European and Amer-
ican human rights mechanisms have shown how emerging regional
consensus (in advance of global consensus) can be employed to
achieve traction for regional agreements or standards on the issue of
the death penalty. Eorts along similar lines are under way in the Afri-
can Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights and the Association
of Southeast Asian Nations. These eorts are encouraging for those
working more broadly on the right to life, and should be supported.
Of the 53 members of the Commonwealth, 35 still have the death pen-
alty on their statute books, and some (ve in 2013) conduct executions.
The Privy Council’s jurisprudence has played a role in the demise of
the mandatory death penalty in the Commonwealth Caribbean, but
its legitimacy as standard bearer for the constitutional principles of the
Commonwealth could be challenged.
31
CONCLUSION
It is time for the world community to close the chapter on the death
penalty, not only because of its eects on those directly and indi-
rectly involved, but also because it distracts attention from the other
human rights challenges that lie ahead. The international community
has placed violence reduction on the post-2015 development agenda.
If this leads to evidence-based evaluations of the drivers of violence
and best mechanisms for its reduction, then it seems likely that the
anachronistic nature of the death penalty will become increasingly
clear. Ending the death penalty could serve as an inspiration about
the possibility of the greater realisation of the right to life in general.
Public calls for a moratorium from high-prole gures—ranging
from the Secretary-General of the United Nations to the High
Commissioner for Human Rights—speak to an emerging consen-
sus that the practice of executions is no longer beyond the scope of
human rights mechanisms. International law makes clear the desir-
ability of abolition but leaves states to determine the best manner
in which to achieve it. In the 50 years since the pronouncement of
the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, some 160
countries have abolished the death penalty either in law or practice.
While waiting for the remaining states to nd the appropriate vehi-
cle for abolition, it is important that international actors, including
regional organisations, continue to insist that, when the death penalty
is imposed, it is within the very narrow scope allowed by law.
Regional organisations can also act as important forums for discus-
sion of trends toward abolition that are more regionally, and perhaps
31 For a critical appraisal, see Quincy Whitaker, “Challenging the death penalty in the Caribbean:
litigation at the Privy Council”, in Against the Death Penalty: International Initiatives and Implica-
tions, Jon Yorke, ed. (Farnham, UK, Ashgate, 2008), pp. 101-124.
228 229
TOWARDS A MORATORIUM
ON THE DEATH PENALTY
Paul Jacob Bhatti
1
Life is a precious gift from Almighty God, and only God has the right
to give it or take it away. There is no justice without life, and you can’t
appreciate life if you don’t reject death.
Some people believe that the death penalty is warranted under lim-
ited circumstances and with the strictest procedural safeguards. But
even in the best jurisdictions, mistakes happen, evidence is incom-
plete, and innocent people are erroneously executed.
In the worst jurisdictions, and there are many, the death penalty is
used by fanatics and fascists to purge innocent religious and political
minorities in the name of extremist ideologies and agendas. Due to
political strife, war, poverty and famine, the best jurisdictions can and
do devolve into the worst, making even well-reasoned death penalty
schemes a moral landmine.
For these reasons, I see no viable moral basis for capital punishment
to remain a sentencing option in any criminal justice system. The risk
and the injustice of losing innocent human life is too great.
I realize that implementing a moratorium on the death penalty is no
trivial matter. This is a complex question with no simple solutions. Prov-
identially, such a moratorium is now vigorously supported by a wide and
growing array of inuential religious scholars, human rights activists and
political and social leaders. In the 1970s, some 20 countries had abolished
capital punishment. Today about 160 countries have stopped using it, either
by law or on a de facto basis. The momentum is palpable and energizing.
There is growing agreement that the essential objectives the
death penalty is meant to serve—crime control, deterrence and
1 Paul Jacob Bhatti is a surgeon and former Pakistani Minister for National Harmony and Mi-
nority Aairs.
retribution—can be achieved without it, and are often not achieved
with it. And it is necessary to understand that the death penalty
causes loss of innocent human life in two ways: through mistakes and
through deliberate misuse.
First, our criminal justice systems are less than perfect. In many
jurisdictions, money and greed drive biased and corrupt tribunals
or kangaroo courts to adjudicate unjust convictions, resulting in the
imprisonment and execution of the innocent while the guilty rich
and powerful walk free.
Erroneous convictions also occur when poor and poorly educated
defendants cannot aord competent legal counsel, witnesses make
honest mistakes about identities and other facts of the case, evidence
is fabricated or suppressed, and juries are prejudiced or incompetent.
Convictions in these instances can result in the shedding of innocent
blood, an intolerable cost.
The United States is a country with a vigorous and venerable legal
tradition, known for its strong constitutional procedural safeguards
regulating the imposition of capital punishment. But even in this juris-
diction, appellate courts have reversed numerous death sentences based
on procedural and evidentiary errors in the trial courts. A staggering
study by Columbia Law School reported on the exoneration of many
death row convicts using newly available DNA testing technology.
2
The work also underscores the high percentage of reversible errors in
death penalty sentences in the United States from 1973 to 1995.
In July 2013, the Washington Post reported that the Department of
Justice and Federal Bureau of Investigation had agreed to review
thousands of cases in which hair sample analysis methods that modern
scientic assessments have deemed deeply awed may have led to
wrongful convictions. More than 120 convictions have already been
reported as suspicious, including 27 death penalty convictions.
3
If
innocent people are being executed in the United States, a country
with vast legal and technical resources, the problem is likely to be
2 Jerey A. Fagan, Capital Punishment: Deterrent Eects and Capital Costs (New York, Columbia
University School of Law, 2014).
3 Spencer S. Hsu, “Convicted defendants left uninformed of forensic aws found by Justice
Department”,
Washington Post, 16 April 2012.
230 231
much worse in poor and developing countries with limited proce-
dural safeguards and more readily compromised judiciary systems.
Second, there is outright malevolent use of legal systems, and
the death penalty in particular, to purge, control, intimidate and
manipulate populations. And herein lies my main argument. It is
no secret that fanatic extremists, often pursuing religious or racial
purity, twist the criminal justice system to their own ends to extir-
pate religious and political minorities. Hitler and Stalin are obvious
examples. Therefore, protecting religious and racial minorities is a
moral cause of the same order as the ght against human tracking
and child prostitution, or past wars against Nazism and other racist
and fascist tyrannies.
It is a moral cause undergirded by comprehensive and unassailable
arguments. These arguments are self-evident and resonate with fun-
damental principles concerning the value of human life articulated
in the constitutions of the Member States of the United Nations
and the holy scriptures of the world’s great faiths. An international
moratorium on the death penalty is an indispensable component in
our ght to eliminate wrongful executions and the terroristic use of
capital punishment.
State-sanctioned executions of the innocent tend to occur in many
places where the justice system is less than transparent and heavily
inuenced or controlled by fanaticism, extremism, terrorism and
racism; my country, Pakistan, is no exception.
My late brother, Shahbaz Clement Bhatti, was a lifelong human rights
activist. He founded a minority rights movement, the All Pakistan
Minorities Alliance, and courageously promoted religious freedom in
Pakistan and advocated for the protection of the basic human rights
of all peoples, especially the poor. He became the rst Federal Min-
ister of Minorities in Pakistan in 2008. He opposed the death penalty
and, in 2008, worked within the Government of Pakistan to support
the United Nations General Assembly’s proposed moratorium on the
death penalty. He was assassinated in 2011 for his convictions and
faith while driving to work from our mother’s home. Today, the All
Pakistan Minorities Alliance continues to aid victims of oppression,
discrimination and violence. Whenever possible, it seeks to identify
and assist the falsely accused and imprisoned.
Before I discuss moving forward to change policy, I want to discuss
how the death penalty can actually encourage terrorism and perpet-
uate a culture of death.
A government-sanctioned execution broadcasts an unambiguous
message to citizens that punishment by death is justied. But the
problem is that terrorists are co-opting the state’s prerogative for their
own malicious objectives. Death perpetuates death. On the face of
it, the death penalty seems an expedient tool in the ght against
terrorism, but the opposite is true in many countries like Iran, Iraq
and Pakistan. In this environment, the death penalty is not a deterrent
but an incentive to high-risk terror.
In many countries it is not uncommon for convicts under a death
sentence to escape prison by force or subterfuge. Many instances of
these “walking dead” escaped convicts attacking and killing innocent
victims plague our headlines. This is an issue stuck in the morass of an
underfunded criminal justice and prison system.
Even more disturbing is the morbid and warped interplay
between fanatic religious extremism, illiteracy and poverty. The
vast majority of suicide bombers and other criminal extremists
originate in societies where the illiteracy and poverty rates are
high. Entrenched poverty leads to suering, loss of hope and
opportunity and a sense of grievance. In Pakistan, half of all adults,
including two out of three women, are illiterate. In 2012, an esti-
mated 20 million children of all school ages, including 7.3 million
primary-school-age children, did not attend school. Poor and
illiterate people are susceptible to predatory extremist ideologies
and agendas. Empty stomachs and empty heads make children
especially easy prey for extremists.
In many countries children are actively recruited and brainwashed
in extremist ideologies and agendas. They inculcate our children
with the conviction that to kill and/or die a martyr in the name of
their religion is not only the norm, but also the basis for an eternal
232 233
reward. The children grow up with no other objective in life than
to die for their ideology.
No major religion advocates hatred, violence and discrimination. All
condemn killing in the name of religion. In the Holy Koran, killing
one human being is con-
sidered the equivalent of
killing all of humanity. But
there are religions in many
parts of the world that have
been hijacked to attack,
divide, control and create
hatred and fear among
innocent people, including towards dierent faiths. This misuse of
religion is a violation of human rights. It is evil.
In fanatic and fundamentalist societies, the presence of religious minori-
ties sometimes triggers aggressive reactions from those who view them
as a threat. Often, false accusations are made to settle personal scores
and to target easy victims, who mostly belong to the oppressed and
marginalized sector of the community—and to further extremist agen-
das, breeding real acts of violence against them, including execution.
My brother, the late Shahbaz Bhatti, was a strong advocate of a mor-
atorium on the death penalty in Pakistan to protect the poor and
religious minorities from being executed by fanatic extremists under
false charges and lesser forms of overt discrimination and harassment.
Although he is no longer with us, his work continues and there is still
much hope.
Implementing an international moratorium on the death penalty will
reap enormous benets that will cascade through the generations.
First, the execution of innocent defendants caused by judicial
corruption, jury bias and error, technological malfunctions
and defects in procedural safeguards will halt immediately.
Second, fanatic extremists will lose a powerful tool for con-
trolling and intimidating populations, when religious and
“NO MAJOR RELIGION
ADVOCATES HATRED,
VIOLENCE AND
DISCRIMINATION.
Paul Jacob Bhatti
racial identity will no longer be crimes subject to capital
punishment. This will be a great day indeed.
Third, religious extremists may be discouraged from com-
mitting acts of terror if they face spending the rest of their
lives in a jail cell, instead of the delusion of instant glory
through martyrdom by state execution.
I propose that we move forward towards implementing a morato-
rium on the death penalty as a major component in the creation of
a peaceful and better world. It is imperative, in these perilous times,
that the United Nations act now to overcome evil with good. We
seek to promote a fair and just world, where peace, security, welfare
and human dignity are the bedrock and baseline of who we are and
how we live.
Let us join together to impose a universal moratorium on the death
penalty. Let us save all those innocent children who are victims of an
imposed ideology that leads them to kill and die for a false reward.
Let us work together to educate our children so that they have a true
hope of becoming productive and informed citizens. And let us pray
together that Almighty God grant us the strength and resources to
resist and overcome the spirit of terror with whatever is true, noble,
right and pure.
234
“Our mission is to continue advocating, because the matter
is not just about people whom we need to save from a
barbaric and ineective punishment, but also about helping
society advance towards a higher degree of civilization.
— Moncef Marzouki
235
CHAPTER 5
ROLE OF LEADERSHIP
Chapter 5 contains articles dealing with the importance of leadership in
moving away from the death penalty.
Federico Mayor, President of the International Commission against the
Death Penalty, oers practical examples from a number of countries—
such as Haiti, Mexico, Mongolia, Rwanda, Senegal, South Africa and the
United States—of the key role of political leadership in the abolition of the
death penalty. This includes political and judicial leaders but also lawyers,
members of the media, and religious and civil society leaders.
Mai Sato, an academic from Japan working in the UK, demonstrates how
oering a life sentence without parole as an alternative to the death penalty
decreases popular support for the death penalty.
Contributions of Heads of States or Governments reect their commit-
ment and contribution to move away from the death penalty globally or
nationally. Didier Burkhalter, President of the Swiss Confederation (2014)
pledges for a dialogue and experience sharing on the death penalty as
the best way in moving away from it. Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj, President of
Mongolia, describes the process how Mongolia under his leadership moved
away from the death penalty, motivated by human rights concerns. Laurent
Fabius, Foreign Minister of France, explores the long path that France took
towards abolition. Moncef Marzouki, President of Tunisia (2011-2014),
speaks of his personal commitment and dierence it has made in Tunisia.
Matteo Renzi, Prime Minister of Italy, describes the relevance of the UN
moratorium resolutions in moving away from the death penalty. Boni Yayi,
President of Benin, describes the process in his country, calling others to
follow their example.
Prime Minister of Italy, Mr. Matteo Renzi, greats the (former) President of Tunisia, Mr. Moncef Marzouki (sitting), at the high-level event on “Moving Away from the Death
Penalty: National Leadership”, held on the margins of the General Assembly general debate, New York, 25 September 2015; UN Photo/Amanda Voisard
236 237
LEADERSHIP AND THE
ABOLITION OF THE
DEATH PENALTY
Federico Mayor
1
Principled political leadership, within the domestic realm and inter-
nationally, is an essential factor in the momentum that is driving the
movement for the abolition of the death penalty. The role played
by leaders—such as prime ministers, presidents, ministers, author-
ities within ministries dealing with domestic and international
aairs, national human rights institutions, the judiciary (including
judges and magistrates who pass rulings that shape the debate and
jurisprudence), lawyers and bar associations, and key gures in the
media, religious bodies and civil society organisations—has been
and will remain crucial to ensuring progress towards a world free of
capital punishment.
Ultimately, it is the state that must decide to abolish the death penalty
and protect the fundamental human right to life. Political leadership
has been very important in overcoming domestic opposition to abo-
lition in several countries. Political leaders have recognized that while
public opinion is relevant, nations face diculties if popular senti-
ment, which is dicult to gauge accurately, is allowed to determine
penal policy. Experience shows that the majority of the public is
willing to accept abolition of capital punishment once it is achieved.
Leaders of several countries have initially granted clemency or
imposed moratoriums on executions which, in turn, have paved the
way for legislative or constitutional repeal of capital punishment.
Many leaders have recognized the ever-present risk of executing
innocent people, as well as other powerful arguments for abolition,
including the discriminatory and arbitrary nature of judicial pro-
cesses and the danger of capital punishment being used as a tool of
political repression.
1 Federico Mayor is President of the International Commission against the Death Penalty.
International leadership is very important and complements domes-
tic political leadership in abolishing capital punishment. Often, it is
a response to pressure, support and recommendations from inter-
national bodies such as the United Nations General Assembly, the
United Nations Secretary General and the Oce of the High Com-
missioner for Human Rights; treaty bodies such as the Human Rights
Committee, the Committee against Torture and the Committee on
the Rights of the Child; and statements and reports that are drafted by
special procedures. The role of regional bodies such as the European
Union, Organisation of American States and African Union has been
important in ensuring that Europe (barring Belarus), the Americas
(with the exception of the United States of America) and Africa
(with the exception of ve countries) have become execution-free.
The majority of the executions take place in regions such as Asia and
the Middle East where there are no regional organisations spanning
the continent (such as the European Union and organisations men-
tioned above) and where regional leadership is weak or non-existent.
THE INTERNATIONAL COMMISSION AGAINST
THE DEATH PENALTY
The International Commission against the Death Penalty (ICDP),
founded in Madrid in October 2010, is currently composed of 14
people of high international standing from all regions of the world
who act with independence and neutrality. Its commissioners are
leaders, with long and respected experience in public life, who believe
in the fundamental right to life and who are using their moral voice,
inuence and access to advocate with leaders and governments of
death-penalty-retentionist countries for abolition of capital punish-
ment. These individuals include former presidents, prime ministers,
government ministers and senior United Nations ocials, a former
US state governor, a former judge and president of the International
Court of Justice, a senior judge and a leading academic. Each com-
missioner has expertise in international law and human rights and
has shown leadership in and commitment to the global abolition of
capital punishment. Their experience and knowledge enable them
to address politically sensitive issues and engage with senior ocials
from countries where the death penalty is still used. Their knowledge,
inuence and broad geographical representation provide ICDP with
238 239
a high prole in the international arena.
2
ICDP opposes the death
penalty under any circumstances, believing that it violates the right to
life enshrined in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
ICDP works with the United Nations and other international and
regional organizations, governments, parliamentarians, lawyers, media
and nongovernmental organizations to further the abolition of the
death penalty worldwide. Its work is supported by a diverse group of
18 states from all regions of the world that are committed to aboli-
tion. Its secretariat is located in Geneva.
DIFFERENT PATHWAYS TO ABOLITION
Countries have arrived at the same goal—abolishing the death pen-
alty—in dierent ways. A few examples are described below.
In Haiti, political leaders helped prepare the ground for changing
the penal code; the commutation of all death sentences under the
1987 Constitution was a key step in that direction. The penal code
of 1953 had established the death penalty for criminal and political
oences. During the presidency of Francois Duvalier between 1957
and 1971, numerous death sentences were imposed following sum-
mary trials, and executions were frequently carried out in public. A
1985 governmental decree abolished the death penalty for political
oences except high treason. Following the collapse in 1986 of the
Jean-Claude Duvalier government, which had been responsible for
widespread human rights violations, former government ocials
were sentenced to death for human rights abuses. A new Consti-
tution in 1987, approved in a national referendum under President
Henri Namphy, abolished the death penalty. All death sentences were
commuted. The 1987 Constitution was temporarily abolished fol-
lowing a military coup in 1988, but President Leslie Manigat issued
a decree on 12 July 1988 rearming the abolition of the death pen-
alty. Haiti has since supported four resolutions of the United Nations
General Assembly calling for a moratorium on the application of the
death penalty, most recently in 2012. During its Universal Periodic
Review in 2011, Haiti agreed to sign and ratify the Second Optional
Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
2 The ICDP’s website can be found at www.icomdp.org/.
which is the only international treaty with global coverage that calls
for abolition of the death penalty.
Mexico abolished the death penalty in 2005, rst in legislation and
then in a constitutional amendment. The last execution, of a soldier
under the Code of Military Justice, was carried out in 1961. Most
Mexican states had already abolished capital punishment by the end
of the 19th century. The Code of Military Justice did, however, retain
capital punishment for specic oences, and people were occasionally
sentenced to death under its provisions. There was widespread oppo-
sition from Catholic bishops, political leaders, senators and prominent
lawyers to a suggestion by a presidential candidate in 1988 to hold
a referendum on reintroducing the death penalty. In April 2005, the
only remaining provision in the Mexican criminal law permitting
the death penalty was abolished. The Mexican Chamber of Depu-
ties unanimously voted to reform the Code of Military Justice and
replace capital punishment with prison terms of 30 to 60 years for
serious oences. To reinforce abolition at the constitutional level, the
Mexican House of Representatives approved a constitutional reform
bill in June 2005 that explicitly prohibits the death penalty for all
crimes. President Vicente Fox signed the bill amending Articles 14
and 22 of the Constitution of the United Mexican States, and it came
into force on 9 December 2005.
In Senegal, a predominantly Muslim country, the abolition of the
death penalty took place due to a number of factors including
a change in the position of President Abdoulaye Wade to support
abolition, along with the assertion by then Justice Minister Sergine
Diop that crime gures were not lower in retentionist countries than
in abolitionist countries, and advocacy by civil society organisations.
Since independence in 1960, Senegal had carried out two executions,
the last in 1967. The penal code provided for the death penalty for
oences including murder and made it mandatory for, among others,
espionage and treason. Discussion about constitutional reform in
2001 included the possible abolition of the death penalty, though at
that time it was resisted by President Wade, who argued that abolition
should be brought about through legislation. Article 7 of the 2001
Constitution stated that “all human life is sacred and inviolable” and
that everyone has the right to life. When the courts handed down
240 241
death sentences in 2003 and 2004, a vigorous debate on the death
penalty resumed, especially when a bill to abolish it was presented in
parliament in 2004. With the support of Justice Minister Diop, civil
society organisations and, most importantly, President Wade, the bill
was unanimously approved by the Government in July 2004, and on
10 December 2004, the Senegalese parliament abolished the death
penalty by a large majority.
In South Africa, the Constitutional Court played a key role by ruling
that the death penalty violated human rights as a form of cruel, inhu-
man or degrading
punishment. During
the apartheid era, the
death penalty was
widely and dispropor-
tionately used against
the black population.
In 1990, anti-apartheid leader Nelson Mandela, who had been tried for
oences carrying the death penalty and proclaimed it to be a barbaric
punishment, was released from prison, and negotiations for constitu-
tional change started. Abolition of the death penalty became a litmus
test for the creation of a social order, and a tribunal was established to
review all death sentences imposed before July 1990. The last execu-
tion was carried out in 1991, and the Minister of Justice proclaimed a
formal moratorium on executions in 1992 pending the introduction
of a bill of rights. The new Constitutional Court made a landmark
judgement in its rst case, the State v. T. Makwanyane and M. Mchunu,
3
where it concluded that the death penalty was a form of cruel, inhu-
man or degrading punishment, prohibited by the interim Constitution.
Despite opinion polls showing a majority in favour of retaining capital
punishment, the African National Congress supported abolition. South
Africa’s Constitution was adopted in May 1996, and it retained the
wording of the 1993 interim Constitution guaranteeing the right to
life as a fundamental right and abolishing the death penalty. In 1997, the
parliament formally abolished the death penalty for all crimes by pass-
ing the Criminal Law Amendment Act, which removed all references
3 In the Matter of the State v. T. Makwanyane and M. Mchunu, case no. CCT3/94, Constitu-
tional Court of the Republic of South Africa, 1995. Available from www.saii.org/za/cases/
ZACC/1995/3.pdf.
“POLITICAL LEADERSHIP
IS A KEY FACTOR IN THE
ABOLITION OF THE DEATH
PENALTY.
Federico Mayor
to the death penalty from the statute book, and abolition came into
force in 1998. In November 2006, the Constitutional Court ruled that
the Government had fully complied with its 1995 judgement on the
unconstitutionality of the death penalty.
In Mongolia, President Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj has been leading the
move towards abolition of capital punishment, including acceding to
the Second Optional Protocol to the International Convention on
Civil and Political Rights, which is the only treaty with global scope
to abolish the death penalty. President Elbegdorj initially announced
a moratorium on the death penalty in January 2010, emphasising the
need to follow the worldwide trend towards abolition. In a landmark
speech to the State Great Khural (parliament), President Elbegdorj
listed eight reasons for rejecting the death penalty, including the irrep-
arable nature of any error in imposing it, its historical use in political
purges, the international community’s calls for abolition and its lack
of a deterrent eect. He said, “There could be a multitude of reasons
and varying circumstances and settings for committing a crime that
carries a death penalty. Yet the guiding principle for the Head of State
on whether to approve a death penalty must be single. That single
principle is to pardon the oender. As the Head of State of Mongo-
lia, I will remain faithful to this principle because it guarantees and
safeguards the value of human life.
4
In January 2012, the Mongolian
parliament approved a bill to end the death penalty by acceding to
the Second Optional Protocol, and later that year, Mongolia acceded
to the protocol. Although death-penalty provisions remain in the law
until repealed by parliament, accession marked Mongolia’s interna-
tional commitment to abolish the death penalty.
In the United States of America, as of this writing the only country
in the Americas carrying out executions in 2013-2014, a number
of governors and state legislatures are moving to repeal capital pun-
ishment, although at the federal level the death penalty remains in
force. Not only has the number of total executions in the United
States decreased, but several states have either abolished the death
penalty or established an ocial moratorium. Recent states to abolish
4 Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj, “The path of democratic Mongolia must be clean and bloodless”, speech
by the president at the State Great Khural, 14 January 2010, available from www.president.mn/
eng/newsCenter/viewEvent.php?cid=&newsId=122&newsEvent=President%20on%20Cli-
mate%20Change.
242 243
the death penalty include Illinois (2011), Connecticut (2012) and
Maryland (2013); as of this writing, the total number of abolitionist
states was 18. Essential for these developments has been the work
of individual state governors, including Patrick Quinn of Illinois,
Dannel Malloy of Connecticut and Martin O’Malley of Maryland,
who have campaigned for abolition or commuted death sentences
to life imprisonment. In November 2011, Governor John Kitzhaber
of Oregon imposed a moratorium on executions in the state and
said that a re-evaluation of capital punishment was long overdue.
5
In
Washington, Governor Jay Inslee announced a moratorium on the
death penalty on 11 February 2014 for as long as he is in oce.
6
In
Connecticut, a bill abolishing the death penalty was passed by the
state legislature in April 2012. Governor Malloy, who signed the bill
into law, said:
I spent years as a prosecutor.... I learned rst-hand that
our system of justice is ... subject to the fallibility of those
who participate in it. I saw people who were poorly served
by their counsel. I saw people wrongly accused or mistak-
enly identied. I saw discrimination. I came to believe that
doing away with the death penalty was the only way to
ensure it would not be unfairly imposed.
7
Governor Malloy highlighted the important role played by victims’
families who lobbied the state legislature against the death penalty.
When the death penalty was abolished in Connecticut, 48 percent
of the voters of the state were reported to be in favour of the death
penalty, with 43 percent against.
8
In Rwanda, the death penalty was abolished in the aftermath of
the 1994 genocide, in which an estimated 800,000 Rwandans
were murdered. The involvement of the international community
5 Death Penalty Information Center, “Gov. John Kitzhaber of Oregon declares a moratorium on
all executions” (Washington, DC, 26 November 2011).
6 Amnesty International, “Momentum against death penalty continues as Washington state
governor announces moratorium on execution” (AI Index No. AMR/51/011/2014,
12 February 2014).
7 International Commission against the Death Penalty, “How states abolish the death penalty”
(Geneva, 2013), p. 31.
8 Ibid., p. 31.
in establishing accountability triggered Rwanda’s move towards
abolition of capital punishment. Prior to the genocide, capital pun-
ishment existed in Rwanda for a wide range of criminal oences,
and the State Security Court had jurisdiction over cases of a politi-
cal nature, including oences punishable by death. Executions were
occasionally carried out. In 1987, President Juvenal Habyarimana
commuted all existing death sentences to life imprisonment, a
move that benetted 537 prisoners. Some of those charged with
involvement in the 1994 genocide were tried in Rwandan domestic
courts, and in 1998, 22 people convicted of leading the genocide
were executed.
Meanwhile, when the United Nations Security Council had estab-
lished the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) in
November 1994, the death penalty was excluded as punishment in
spite of strong opposition from Rwanda. This decision presented a
problem for the government: A fundamental injustice would occur
if suspects tried in domestic courts were sentenced to death while
thousands of genocide suspects living abroad, some held by the
ICTR, including alleged ringleaders, received life imprisonment at
most. Indeed, governments detaining suspects who had ed abroad
as well as the ICTR refused to extradite them to Rwanda, because
of the death penalty as well as concerns about the lack of fair trial
guarantees, which had been a long-standing concern in cases related
to the death penalty. These concerns rst prompted the enactment, in
2007, of a special transfer law prohibiting execution of suspects due to
be transferred from the ICTR to local Rwandan courts. In October
2006, the political bureau of the ruling party strongly recommended
abolition, and in January 2007, the cabinet approved plans to abolish
capital punishment. The Chamber of Deputies and the Senate passed
abolition bills, and the Law Relating to the Abolition of the Death
Penalty entered into force in July 2007 when it was ratied by Pres-
ident Paul Kagame. It abolished the death penalty for all crimes and
removed it from the Penal Code. President Kagame observed that his
country’s history of genocide was a primary factor in the abolition of
the death penalty. All death sentences (about 600) were commuted
to life imprisonment.
244 245
ICDP COMMISSIONERS’ CONTRIBUTIONS
ICDP commissioners
9
all have a strong record of promoting human
rights and are committed to providing political leadership to the
cause of abolishing the death penalty worldwide. Their experience
and knowledge enables them to address politically sensitive issues and
engage with senior ocials from countries where the death penalty
is still retained. This section highlights the leading role some of the
commissioners have played in the cause of abolishing the death pen-
alty in their home countries.
Robert Badinter (Minister of Justice, 1981-1986, France) was
well known for challenging the death penalty in the courts before
becoming Minister of Justice. As a lawyer, he argued successfully, six
times between 1976 and 1980, against the death penalty as cruel and
inhuman punishment that risked innocent people being executed.
French President François Mitterrand, who had declared his opposition
to the death penalty a few weeks before the 1981 elections, appointed
Mr. Badinter to be Minister of Justice in his new Socialist government.
President Mitterrand’s call for abolition during the election campaign
was controversial, as public opinion largely favoured capital punishment.
Mr. Badinter, as Minister of Justice, introduced a death penalty abolition
bill in the National Assembly in September 1981 under the quick vote
procedure. In October 1981, after the bill passed the National Assembly
(363 to 117) and the Senate (160 to 26), the death penalty was abolished
for all civil and military oences in France. Abolition followed a long
public debate, presidential pardons, a cross-party study group, legal action
in the courts and decisive action by President Mitterrand and Minister
of Justice Badinter. In 2007, abolition of the death penalty was incorpo-
rated in the French Constitution by President Jacques Chirac by means
of a constitutional amendment passed in parliament. Article 66-1 of the
French Constitution provides that “no one shall be sentenced to the
death penalty.
10
Glor ia Macapagal-Arroyo (President, 2001-2010, the Philippines)
commuted all death sentences to life imprisonment during her
9 Navi Pillay, former High Commissioner for Human Rights, has recently been appointed as
ICDP commissioner.
10 Ibid., pp. 13-15; International Commission against the Death Penalty,
Annual Review 2010-
2012 (Geneva, 2013), p. 21.
presidency and signed a law abolishing the death penalty in 2006.
Philippines presidents played a very important role in the abolition
of capital punishment. The Philippines was the rst country in Asia
to abolish the death penalty for all crimes, in 1987 under President
Corazón Aquino. The death penalty was reintroduced in 1993, and
executions were resumed in 1999; the last execution was carried out
in 2000. In early 2000, the Philippines had one of the highest rates
of death sentences in the world. Shortly after assuming the presi-
dency in 2001, Ms. Macapagal-Arroyo announced a death penalty
moratorium. This decision followed a campaign against reimposi-
tion of capital punishment by civil society organisations including
the Catholic Bishops’ Conference and the Philippines Commission
on Human Rights. On 15 April 2006, on the occasion of Easter,
President Macapagal-Arroyo announced the commutation of all
death sentences to life imprisonment, aecting over 1,200 people.
She wrote a letter to then Senate President Franklin M. Drilon on
the urgent need for “abolishing the death penalty as its imposition
was shown to have not served its principal purpose of eectively
deterring the commission of heinous crimes,
11
adding that abolition
would remedy the ndings that the death penalty was anti-poor as
it was often those who could not aord legal representation who
were sentenced to death. The Philippines Congress took swift action
and in June 2006, the Senate (16 to 0, with one abstention) and the
House of Representatives (119 to 20) passed bills abolishing the death
penalty. President Arroyo issued a statement saying, “We celebrate the
victory of life as I thank Congress for its immediate action in abolish-
ing the death penalty law.
12
The law entered into eect on 24 June
2006, with President Macapagal-Arroyo signing the Act Prohibiting
the Imposition of the Death Penalty in the Philippines.
13
Ibrahim Najjar (Minister of Justice, 2008-2011, Lebanon),
an eminent lawyer, scholar and law professor, is seen as one of the
leaders of the death penalty abolitionist movement in Lebanon. As
Minister of Justice, he promoted laws in many elds, including pre-
vention of arbitrary detention and protection of human rights, and
11 International Commission against the Death Penalty, “How states abolish the death penalty”,
p. 21.
12 Ibid., p. 21.
13 Ibid., pp. 20-22; International Commission against the Death Penalty,
Annual Review 2010-
2012, p. 21.
246 247
worked to repeal capital punishment in Lebanon’s Penal Code. His
tenure as Minister of Justice is considered one of the most produc-
tive periods for the judiciary and the promotion of draft laws. After
recognising that abolition of the death penalty in Lebanon was a
contentious issue, he continued working towards the achievement
of a “more humane and more ecient justice system.
14
In 2008, he
introduced a draft law to abolish the death penalty in Lebanon. Had
it been accepted, capital punishment would have been replaced by
life imprisonment.
15
In 2010 he was awarded the National Medal for
Human Rights in recognition of his draft law to abolish the death
penalty in Lebanon. Mr. Najjar continues to advocate the abolition
of capital punishment in Lebanon. In June 2014, he was part of a
delegation of ICDP commissioners which I led. We held discussions
related to the death penalty with Prime Minister Tammam Salam,
members of parliament, lawyers, diplomats and important members
of civil society. During a speech in Lebanon as an ICDP delegate in
June 2014, he said, “In Lebanon, we are witnessing a tendency to steer
away from the death penalty when we take note [that] the Parliament
has introduced no new legal sanctions constituting expansion of the
death penalty in the recent past. The dependence on death penalty
has ended. For me, the death penalty is premeditated murder; it is not
objective. Its abolition has to be achieved through constant consensus
and placed within the context of Lebanese and regional peace.
16
Lebanon remains a death-penalty-retentionist country; the last
executions, of three men, were carried out in January 2004. (The
last public executions were carried out in May 1998 and sparked
uproar because the gallows did not work properly.) In July 2001, the
Lebanese parliament voted unanimously leave the application of the
death penalty to the discretion of judges. The Lebanese Constitution
requires the signature of the president, the prime minister and the
minister of justice to carry out an execution. In September 2011, the
Lebanese parliament approved a bill amending law No. 463/2002 on
the implementation of sentences, creating a formal status for those
14 International Commission against the Death Penalty, Annual Review 2010-2012, p. 23.
15 Ibid., p. 21.
16 International Commission against the Death Penalty, “President of ICDP Mr Federico Mayor,
Commissioners Ms Hanne Sophie Greve and Mr Ibrahim Najjar leads ICDP mission to
Lebanon” (Geneva, 16 June 2014), available from www.icomdp.org/cms/wp-content/up-
loads/2014/06/18-ICDP-Press-Statement-Lebanon-16-June-2014.pdf.
“sentenced to death without being executed. Although this amend-
ment did not abolish the death penalty, it has enhanced the unocial
position of the Lebanese authorities in favour of a de facto morato-
rium on executions. As of June 2014, there were at least 57 prisoners
sentenced to death in Lebanon.
Bill Richardson (Governor, 2002-2010, New Mexico, USA)
signed a death penalty abolition bill into law in March 2009,
makingthe state of New Mexico the15th US state to abolish cap-
ital punishment. He was then in his second term as Governor of
New Mexico, re-elected in 2006 with the support of 69 per cent of
voters, representing the largest margin of victory for any governor
in state history.Since the resumption of executions in the United
States in 1977, New Mexico had carried out one execution, in 2001.
A statewide poll in 2008 showed that 64 percent of New Mexi-
cans supported replacing the death penalty with life imprisonment
without parole and restitution to victims’ families. In New Mexico’s
case, factors that helped abolition included lobbying against the death
penalty by prominent voices within the Catholic Church and fami-
lies of murder victims, legislators citing the high cost of executions,
and a 2008 study by the New Mexico Law Review on the application
of capital punishment between July 1979 and December 2007 that
found that the imposition of the death penalty was inuenced by
where or when the crime was committed and the race or ethnicity
of the victim and the defendant. The death penalty abolition bill was
passed with cross-party support by the State Senate (24 to 18) and
House of Representatives (40 to 28) in March 2009. Governor Rich-
ardson then sought the views of citizens and was urged by former US
President Jimmy Carter to support the bill.
Governor Richardson justied his decision to sign the death penalty
abolition bill, which he called the most dicult of his life, by refer-
ring to inmates who had been exonerated after being sentenced to
death: “The sad truth is that the wrong person can still be convicted
in this day and age, and in cases where that conviction carries with it
the ultimate sanction, we must have ultimate condence, I would say
certitude, that the system is without aw or prejudice. Unfortunately,
248 249
this is demonstrably not the case.
17
He also commented: “In a society
which values individual life and liberty above all else, where justice
and not vengeance is the singular guiding principle of our system of
criminal law, the potential for wrongful conviction and, God forbid,
execution of an innocent person stands as anathema to our very sen-
sibilities as human beings.
18
Another factor had been the worldwide
trend towards abolition of the death penalty: “From an international
human rights perspective, there is no reason the United States should
be behind the rest of the world in this issue.
19
CONCLUSION
Political leadership is a key factor in the abolition of the death pen-
alty, which has gained momentum in recent years, with the United
Nations now estimating that over 160 countries have abolished capital
punishment or do not execute. In Haiti, political leaders have helped
lay the groundwork for change in the penal code, while in Senegal,
abolition came about due to a change in the President’s viewpoint,
backed up by the Justice Minister’s view that there was no evidence
of a deterrent eect. The role of the President was key in Mongolia,
which acceded to the Second Optional Protocol to the Interna-
tional Convention on Civil and Political Rights, thereby voluntarily
making an international commitment to abolish capital punishment
prior to removing it from national law. In Mexico, abolition was a
consequence of constitutional amendment, while in South Africa, the
Constitutional Court played a key role, during the era ending apart-
heid, upholding the abolitionist ideals of leaders like Nelson Mandela.
Abolition in Rwanda came in the aftermath of the 1994 genocide,
with an international tribunal leading the way in ensuring the end of
capital punishment. In the United States, governors of 18 states have
led the move to abolish capital punishment.
While States have adopted dierent pathways to end the cruel, inhu-
man and degrading practice of the death penalty, it is evident that
17 Death Penalty Information Centre, “Governor Bill Richardson signs repeal of the death penal-
ty” (Washington, DC, 19 March 2009).
18 “Bill Richardson”,
International Commission against the Death Penalty, available from www.
icomdp.org/bill-richardson.
19 International Commission against the Death Penalty, “How states abolish the death penalty”,
p. 32.
political leadership has played a crucial part in ensuring and deepen-
ing the abolitionist trend. The four ICDP commissioners highlighted
in this article have played a leading role in the abolition of the death
penalty in their countries. The ICDP itself is a manifestation of the
need for this political leadership to expand eorts to abolish capital
punishment from the national to the international arena. ICDP, I
believe, is able to bring experienced, eminent, respected voices to the
cause of abolition, in a way that complements the work of other insti-
tutions. Rejecting capital punishment is about choosing what kind of
society we want to live in, and which values—including human rights
and dignity, democracy and the rule of law—we want to uphold.
250 251
VOX POPULI, VOX DEI?
A CLOSER LOOK AT THE
“PUBLIC OPINION” ARGUMENT
FOR RETENTION
Mai Sato
1
For countries and organisations that oppose the death penalty, any
state execution is a violation of human rights or risks a miscarriage
of justice that is both severe and uncorrectable. Abolitionist states
and organisations have urged retentionists—through international
treaties, soft-power diplomacy and other campaigns—to change their
point of view. An eminent legal scholar predicted nearly 20 years ago
that abolition may become a customary norm and reach the status of
jus cogens [a fundamental principle of international law from which
no derogation is permitted]. . . in the not too distant future.
2
Today,
while abolitionist states have become the clear majority, it is also true
that retentionist states have continued to carry out the death penalty.
Japan was the rst country in the world known to have abolished the
death penalty; no executions were carried out from 810 to 1156.
3
Today, however, Japan retains the death penalty.
4
While its use is far
from aggressive, with about ve executions per year during the last
20 years, prisoners on death row have been hanged every year (except
for 2011). The United Nations Human Rights Committee (hereafter
the Committee) has repeatedly raised concerns over Japan’s failure to
full its obligations under the International Covenant on Civil and
1 Mai Sato is Research Ocer at the Centre for Criminology, University of Oxford. This chapter
summarises the main arguments in her book The Death Penalty in Japan: Will the Public Toler-
ate Abolition? (Berlin, Springer, 2014).
2 W. A. Schabas, The Abolition of the Death Penalty in International Law (Cambridge, Cam-
bridge University Press, 1997), p. 20.
3 D. T. Johnson and F. Zimring, The Next Frontier: National Development, Political Change, and
the Death Penalty in Asia (Oxford and New York, Oxford University Press, 2009); K. Kikuta,
Q&A: Shikei Mondai no Kiso Chishiki / Q&A: Basic Knowledge of the Issues Surrounding
the Death Penalty (Tokyo, Akashi Shoten, 2004).
4 In Japan, 18 crimes are eligible for the death penalty. In practice, however, its use is restricted to
a limited subset of these crimes, with almost all prisoners sentenced to death for one of three
crimes: murder, robbery resulting in death, or rape on occasion of robbery resulting in death. In
relation to murder (as with all other oences on the list), the death penalty is discretionary rather
than mandatory and is normally imposed only when a defendant is convicted of multiple killings.
Political Rights,
5
and the Council of Europe has made numerous
resolutions critical of Japan, even threatening to take away its observer
status.
6
However, Japan has retained its observer status and, despite
condemnation by the Committee, has openly and without much (if
any) political damage continued to carry out executions.
This illustrates an important limitation of international human rights
law: The implementation of human rights norms is possible only if states
choose to be bound by them. Human rights is a socially constructed
concept that needs to be embraced and accepted to be eective, rather
than a set of self-evident principles that exists independently—not a
“truth” that people will one day naturally “come round to” but a con-
cept that requires negotiation and persuasion to become operational.
This perspective is often neglected or forgotten when abolitionist
scholars and international organisations engage with retentionist states.
Public opinion and government legitimacy
The clearest example of this in the Japanese context relates to public
opinion, which the Japanese government has raised as the main obsta-
cle to abolition for over 30 years. However, the Committee has not
fully engaged with this argument, either to respond to it or to refute
it.
7
For example, in responding to Japan’s state party report, which
consistently makes the public opinion argument, the Committee
5 UN Human Rights Committee, “Concluding observations of the Human Rights Commit-
tee: Japan”, 19 November 1998 (CCPR/C/79Add.102); UN Human Rights Committee,
“Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee: Japan”, 18 December 2008
(CCPR/C/JPN/CO/5); UN Human Rights Committee, “Concluding observations of the
Human Rights Committee: Japan”, 20 August 2014 (CCPR/C/JPN/CO/6) Documents
available from: http://tbinternet.ohchr.org/_layouts/treatybodyexternal/TBSearch.aspx-
?Lang=en&TreatyID=8&DocTypeID=5. Japan ratied the Covenant in 1979 but has not yet
signed or ratied the Second Optional Protocol to the Covenant.
6 Council of Europe, “Resolution 1253 (2001): Abolition of the death penalty in Council of Eu-
rope in observer status” (Strasburg, Council of Europe, 2001); Council of Europe, “Resolution
1349 (2003): Abolition of the death penalty in Council of Europe in observer status” (Strasburg,
Council of Europe, 2003); Council of Europe, “Doc. 10911: Position of the Parliamentary
Assembly as regards the Council of Europe member and observer states which have not abol-
ished the death penalty (Report of the Committee on Legal Aairs and Human Rights of the
Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe)” (Strasburg, Council of Europe, 2006). Japan
was granted Council of Europe observer status in 1996. Under Statutory Resolution (93) 26,
Japan must accept the principles of democracy, the rule of law and the enjoyment of all persons
within its jurisdiction of human rights and fundamental freedoms.
7 For a more detailed discussion of the dialogue between the Japanese government and interna-
tional organisations, see M. Sato, “Challenging the Japanese government’s approach to the death
penalty”, in
Confronting Capital Punishment in Asia: Human Rights, Politics, Public Opinion and
Practices, Roger Hood and Surya Deva, eds. (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013) pp. 205-217.
252 253
in 2008 wrote, “regardless of opinion polls, the state party should
favourably consider abolishing the death penalty”; its 2014 response
did not address the issue at all.
8
The following statement is what the Japanese government wrote in
its most recent state party report:
Presently, the death penalty is believed to be unavoidable
by a large number of Japanese people in cases of extremely
malicious or atrocious crimes (armed by 85.6 percent
in the latest opinion survey conducted from November to
December 2009 . . . and there is no end to atrocious crimes
in Japan.
9
The Japanese government’s argument is twofold. First it makes a the-
oretical claim that the decision to retain or abolish should depend
on public opinion, based on the idea of popular sovereignty and the
importance of maintaining the legitimacy of criminal justice agencies
and criminal law. Second, it presents its own survey evidence to sup-
port its theoretical position.
While deferring to public opinion on human rights issues is often
criticised as unprincipled, the concept of popular sovereignty is in fact
enshrined in instruments such Article 1 and 2 of the United Nations
Charter and Article 25 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights. It is based on the idea that the legitimacy of the state
is formed by the will or consent of its people. The interdependence of
law and public opinion, and the need for legal systems to command
popular support, have long been recognised.
10
Public perception of
the legitimacy of government policies and laws is a key determinant
8 UN Human Rights Committee, “Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee:
Japan”, 18 December 2008 (CCPR/C/JPN/CO/5), paragraph 6; UN Human Rights Com-
mittee, “Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee: Japan”, 20 August 2014
(CCPR/C/JPN/CO/6). Documents available from: http://tbinternet.ohchr.org/_layouts/
treatybodyexternal/TBSearch.aspx?Lang=en&TreatyID=8&DocTypeID=5
9 UN Human Rights Committee, “State party report to the Human Rights Committee: Japan”,
9 October 2012 (CCPR/C/JPN/6), paragraph 104. Document vailable from: http://tbinter-
net.ohchr.org/_layouts/treatybodyexternal/TBSearch.aspx?Lang=en&TreatyID=8&DocType-
ID=45&DocTypeID=29
10 P. Robinson, “Empirical desert”, in Criminal Law Conversations, P. Robinson, S. Garvey and K.
Ferzan, eds. (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2009); P. Robinson and J. Darley, Justice, Liability,
and Blame. Community Views and the Criminal Law (Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press,
1995).
of public acceptance of and compliance with them. Criminologists
have also argued for the importance of maintaining legitimacy and
warned against disregarding public opinion completely.
11
“It is only
when the perspectives of everyday members are enshrined in insti-
tutions and in the actions of authorities that widespread legitimacy
will exist.
12
Legitimacy based on public perceptions is often called subjective or
empirical legitimacy.
13
It can be contrasted with objective legitimacy,
which occurs when an institution can be shown to meet criteria
for legitimacy, however these criteria are derived. Objective legiti-
macy involves normative judgments about the criteria to be applied
and assessments as to whether these criteria have been met. It is
within this top-down perspective that the human rights approach
ts. Subjective/empirical legitimacy occurs when citizens perceive
an institution as legitimate, regardless of the objective standards that it
may (or may not) meet. Clearly it is possible for political and justice
institutions to achieve objective legitimacy without subjective legit-
imacy or vice versa.
The relevance of public opinion to penal policy is not conned to the
death penalty debate. For instance, penal populism can result in over-re-
sponsiveness to public opinion in penal policy, manifesting itself in
counterproductive laws such as “three strikes” provisions for mandatory
imprisonment.
14
More positive examples of responsiveness to public
opinion include victim impact statements and the use of jury trials.
What happens if subjective legitimacy is eroded? What are the con-
sequences of going against public opinion? One example is Mexico’s
attempt to combat drug tracking, which has led to clear damage to the
rule of law.
15
A combination of ineectiveness in policing and extralegal
11 D. Garland, “A note on penal populism”, in Globalised Penal Populism and Its Countermea-
sures, Japanese Association of Sociological Criminology, ed. (Tokyo, Gendaijinbunsha, 2009);
J. Roberts and M. Hough, Understanding Public Attitudes to Criminal Justice (Maidenhead:
Open University Press, 2005).
12 T. Tyler, Why People Obey the Law (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2006).
13 M. Zelditch, “Theories of legitimacy”, in The Psychology of Legitimacy: Emerging Perspectives
on Ideology, Justice, and Intergroup Relations, J. T. Jost and B. Major, eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2001).
14 F. E. Zimring, G. Hawkins, and S. Kamin, Punishment and Democracy: Three Strikes and You’re Out
in California (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
15 T. R. Tyler, ed., Legitimacy and Criminal Justice (New York, Russell Sage, 2007).
254 255
practices led to loss of public trust in the criminal justice system, which
in turn led to the establishment by activists of a new grass-roots system
operating outside the formal legal structure. Unpaid volunteers have
acted as police, court and penal system, often using torture and vigi-
lantism. Governments are naturally concerned that their penal policies,
including abolition of the death penalty, do not erode public percep-
tions of the legitimacy of the criminal justice system—which could
result in noncompliance with the law, lack of cooperation with the
criminal justice system, and vigilantism. One country where the death
penalty policy was at least claimed to be central to popular trust in the
criminal justice system was the Philippines. The government explained
to the Committee in 2002
that the abolition of the death
penalty had “undermined the
people’s faith in the Govern-
ment and the latter’s ability to
maintain peace and order in
the country.
16
As noted earlier, the public-opinion-based argument for retention of
the death penalty has two elements. It must demonstrate that reten-
tion is central to popular trust in the criminal justice system and
that abolition would result in the erosion of political and judicial
legitimacy. This would establish a theoretical basis for the argument.
However, my view is that the biggest challenge to this approach is in
proving empirically that legitimacy depends on retention. For example,
the Japanese government’s argument for retaining the death penalty
is based on the assumption that the survey it conducts has accurately
captured public opinion—a claim that is challenged below.
A closer look at the Japanese survey results
Some retentionist states may claim that there is strong public sup-
port for retention without oering evidence or based on a survey
conducted elsewhere on an ad hoc basis. The Japanese government
16 UN Human Rights Committee, “State party report to the Human Rights Committee:
Phillippines”, 18 September 2012 (CCPR/C/PHL/2002/2 ), paragraph 494. Document
vailable from: http://tbinternet.ohchr.org/_layouts/treatybodyexternal/TBSearch.as-
px?Lang=en&TreatyID=8&DocTypeID=45&DocTypeID=29
takes the argument more seriously by carrying out its own survey
(hereafter the survey), which is contracted to an independent market
research company and has been carried out approximately every ve
years since 1956. Each survey has interviewed nationally represen-
tative samples of Japanese men and women aged 20 and over, using
two-stage stratied random sampling. This needs to be acknowledged
as a systematic attempt to measure public opinion. But does the result
demonstrate that retention of the death penalty is critical to main-
taining social order and legitimacy?
The most recent survey was conducted at the end of 2014; reportedly, 80
percent of respondents were in favour of retention. The result has been
cited by the Ministry of Justice as proof that abolition is not yet possible.
17
Arguably, however, the survey results do not prove that abolition of the
death penalty would harm the criminal justice system’s legitimacy.
For the last ve sweeps of the survey, the government has used the
same measure of support for retention. Respondents are invited to
choose from two statements the one that reects their viewpoint. The
retentionist position is phrased in broad terms: “The death penalty is
unavoidable in some cases. By contrast, the abolitionist option states,
“The death penalty should be abolished under all circumstances. The
80 per cent response reported as supporting the death penalty refers
to respondents who considered that the death penalty is unavoidable
in some cases rather than enthusiastically embracing retention.
18
The retention option also includes an option to support future abo-
lition. Of the 80 per cent of respondents who considered the death
penalty to be unavoidable in some cases, 41 per cent (a third of the
total sample) supported future abolition. When respondents who sup-
port future abolition are not included, under half (46 per cent) of the
total sample can be considered to whole-heartedly support retention.
In addition to the question concerning future abolition, one new
question was added to the 2014 survey. It concerned the introduc-
tion of life imprisonment without parole as an alternative to the
17 Minutes of the press conference available from the MoJ website: http://www.moj.go.jp/
hisho/kouhou/hisho08_00616.html).
18 Even with this wording, the percentage of people who chose this option dropped by 6 percent
from the 2009 survey.
“WHETHER OR NOT THERE
IS A DETERRENT EFFECT IS
A MATTER OF EVIDENCE
AND NOT OPINION.
Mai Sato
256 257
death penalty. This question further qualies public commitment to
retention.
Of the respondents, 38 per cent said that the death penalty
should be abolished if life imprisonment without parole was intro-
duced, 52 per cent said that it should be kept, and 11 per cent said
they didn’t know.
19
Based on the 2014 survey results, it is possible to argue that respon-
dents who (1)consider the death penalty to be unavoidable in some
cases, (2) do not accept the possibility of future abolition, and (3) do
not agree with replacing the death penalty with life imprisonment
without parole amount to only 34 per cent of all respondents. In
other words, behind the 80 per cent support reported in headlines,
the majority of the public do in fact accept the possibility of future
abolition, especially if alternative punishments are available. If hard-
core retentionists make up only 34 per cent of the public, it does
not seem persuasive to argue that abolition would erode trust in the
criminal justice system.
Another vulnerability of this argument is the question: What gure
should be the threshold when judging how essential retaining the
death penalty is to maintaining legitimacy? The Japanese government
has not attempted to answer this question. It is obviously not an easy
question to answer, but it is essential to any public-opinion-based
argument for keeping the death penalty.
One further point undermines the presumed importance of reten-
tion for the Japanese public. Those who are committed to retaining
the death penalty tend to hold inaccurate beliefs about its eect. The
survey asks respondents about their perception of the deterrent eect
of the death penalty. In the 2014 survey, 58 per cent of respondents
thought crime would increase if the death penalty were abolished, 14
per cent thought it would not increase, and 28 per cent chose “don’t
know/cannot say”—which is the correct answer if one accepts the
increasing academic consensus that it is virtually impossible to prove
or disapprove a deterrent eect.
20
19 The percentages do not add up to 100 due to the rounding up of gures.
20 See National Research Council, Deterrence and the Death Penalty, Daniel S. Nagin and John V.
Pepper, eds. (Washington, DC, National Academies Press, 2012).
In addition, whether or not there is a deterrent eect is a matter of
evidence and not opinion. Hence, it is puzzling as to why the survey
has consistently included this question for over 50 years. Nothing has
been done to address public misconceptions about deterrence, nor
has any analysis taken into account those respondents who express
support for the death penalty based on inaccurate beliefs.
Linked to the issue of inaccurate public beliefs, secrecy is a salient
feature of the Japanese death penalty system. In December 2007 the
Japanese government, for the rst time, announced the names of pris-
oners and the crimes they committed after each execution. Before this,
the number of executions was published in newspapers in just one sen-
tence such as, “Today, two people were executed. It is still the case that
prisoners about to be executed are notied only a few hours before
the execution, which gives no time for them to get in touch with their
lawyer or their family.
21
In most cases, the families of prisoners are
informed only after the execution has taken place. Furthermore, there
is still no ocial information regarding how prisoners are selected for
execution, the treatment of prisoners on death row, or the cost of exe-
cutions. This has led scholars to state that “the secrecy that surrounds
capital punishment in Japan is taken to extremes not seen in other
nations”
22
and that the public only has a very abstract idea of the pun-
ishment.
23
Recently, a series of social experiments showed that the vast
majority of the public did not possess basic knowledge about the death
penalty, including whether an execution had taken place in the current
year, and that many people changed their views when they received
additional information.
24
The government has so far failed to reconcile
its secrecy on the use of the death penalty with its delegation of power
to the (poorly informed) public to decide whether to retain it.
Examination of the 2014 survey demonstrated that the wording of a
question and the knowledge of a respondent can dramatically aect
survey results. Does this render surveys unreliable? Furthermore, critics
who question the relevance of public opinion to death-penalty policy
21 K. Kikuta, Q&A, pp. 73-78.
22 D. T. Johnson, “When the state kills in secret: capital punishment in Japan”, Punishment and
Society, vol. 8, no. 3 (2006), pp. 251-285, at p. 251.
23 S. Dando, “Toward the abolition of the death penalty”, Indiana Law Journal, vol. 72 (1996), pp.
7-19, at p. 10.
24 M. Sato, The Death Penalty in Japan.
258 259
argue that almost all countries that abolished the death penalty did so
through judicial or political leadership, despite public support for the
death penalty.
25
In my view, these criticisms do not disprove the value
of survey evidence as a social barometer to inform policy decisions. If,
contrary to expectations based on survey results, countries have abol-
ished the death penalty without eroding the legitimacy of the criminal
justice system, this should cause us to question the reliability of those
survey results—and more importantly, their interpretation—not to
negate a role for public opinion in the death penalty debate.
Concluding remarks
The Japanese government’s justication for retaining the death pen-
alty is that abolition would erode the legitimacy of and public trust in
the criminal justice system, leading to victims’ families taking justice
into their own hands. This justication is based on the results of a
regularly administered public opinion survey, which is said to show
strong public support for the death penalty. However, a close analysis
of the results of the 2014 survey fails to validate this claim. Just over
a third of respondents were committed to retaining the death penalty
at all costs, while the rest accepted the possibility of future abolition,
with some of them seeing this as contingent on the introduction of
life imprisonment without parole as an alternative sentence. These
ndings hardly describe a society that expects the strict application of
the death penalty and whose trust in justice depends on the govern-
ment’s commitment to retaining it. My reading of the 2014 survey
is that the Japanese public is ready to embrace abolition. Japan, after
all, is a signatory to the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, which calls on states not to delay or prevent abolition, so this
should be welcome news for the Japanese government!
25 P. Hodgkinson, “Replacing capital punishment: an issue of eective penal policy”, in The
International Leadership Conference on Human Rights and the Death Penalty, Conference Brochure 1
(European Commission, American Bar Associations, and Japan Federation of Bar Associations,
unpublished, 2005); R. Hood and C. Hoyle, The Death Penalty: A Worldwide Perspective (Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 2015); D. T. Johnson and F. Zimring, The Next Frontier: National Devel-
opment, Political Change, and the Death Penalty in Asia (Oxford and New York, Oxford University
Press, 2009). Hodgkinson (p. 46) argued that “universally public opinion supports the death
penalty and this is important in that politicians many of whom are mesmerised by such polls
are reluctant to question them or to encourage a more authoritative evaluation. . . . Few coun-
tries would have abolished the death penalty if they had waited for public approval.
LEADERSHIP THROUGH
DIALOGUE
Didier Burkhalter
1
Each country has its own way of dealing with the death penalty,
and Switzerland is no exception. In the Swiss case, use of the death
penalty had been steadily declining when legal experts working on
the unication of the Swiss penal code in the 1930s decided that
it was time to end the problematic punishment. Thus, abolition of
the death penalty for ordinary crimes entered into force in 1942
and for military crimes in 1992. Since 2000, the Swiss Constitution
has forbidden the use of the death penalty. The Swiss experience
demonstrates the length of time an abolition process can take, from
initial questioning to full de jure abolition. This is a process that needs
to be driven by leadership.
Switzerland’s ambition is to act as a catalyst in the universal abo-
litionist movement. One cannot create political will in countries
where there is none, nor can one impose abolition where there
hasn’t been a mature and serious debate on the death penalty. But
we can kindle the ame already burning in those countries that
have yet to complete their abolition process. As foreign minister, I
have set universal death penalty abolition as a Swiss foreign policy
priority and as a goal, shared with many colleagues around the
world, to be reached by 2025.
Switzerland’s strategy is straightforward. Bilaterally, we foster and sup-
port discussions between key actors who are open to sharing their
views on the death penalty. We nourish those discussions with facts,
expert analyses and technical support. Where there is growing agree-
ment that steps can be taken towards abolition, we remain ready to
provide pragmatic assistance when appropriate. Multilaterally, we also
play a proactive role in shaping international norms and standards
towards a more restrictive use of the death penalty.
There is increasing awareness that the death penalty cannot be car-
ried out without violating international human rights law. Executions
1 Didier Burkhalter is a member of the Federal Council and the minister of foreign aairs of
Switzerland.
260 261
justice system is an accepted norm of international law, enshrined in
the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. Countries
from every region of the world have set an example in ending the
use of capital punishment, including Benin, Cambodia, Canada, Cap
Verde, Costa Rica, Latvia, Mexico, Mongolia and Timor-Leste.
CHALLENGING THE MYTH OF DETERRENCE
Though a conversation on abolition is always possible, it isn’t always
easy. There are often technical issues that need to be resolved, such as
penal code reform. In countries willing to revisit the death penalty
issue, revising sentencing practices and nding alternatives to capital
punishment can be a lengthy but necessary process. And there is always
a need for local experts to lead the work on legal reform, at times
also to exchange experiences with international experts from countries
with similar justice systems, before abolishing the death penalty.
The persisting myth of deterrence is a challenge almost everywhere.
It is tempting to assume that the threat of execution must discour-
age heinous crimes. However, compelling research has shown that
the death penalty does not deter violent crime any more than harsh
alternative sanctions such as life imprisonment. Other factors, such as
having an ecient police force, are the ones that actually matter in
eectively ghting crime.
Executing drug mules would not stop the ow of illicit drugs. Tracking
will continue as long as there are consumers, as well as people desper-
ate enough to risk entering the drug tracking business for rapid but
often small economic gain. Executing the mentally ill would not make
the community safer, but putting in place programs to address mental
illness will. Both of these scenarios would not only violate international
law, they would also be unethical, inhumane and ultimately pointless.
Yet one of the most common arguments in defence of the death pen-
alty is linked to the same illusion of deterrence. Executing individuals
who are incarcerated, and thus have already ceased to be a threat to
society, is not being tough on crime. Emphasizing the deterrence
rationale is fear mongering, and it is dishonest towards citizens who
have legitimate concerns about their safety. We need to move away
from reliance on this cruel punishment and to focus instead on eec-
tive and ecient crime prevention.
constitute inhumane and degrading treatment and fundamentally
contradict Article 10 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights, which states that the essential aim of any penitentiary
system shall be the reformation and social rehabilitation of prisoners.
The death penalty also takes a heavy toll on prisoners’ families, par-
ticularly their children, violating the fundamental right of each child
to have a family. These are but a few of the principles that Switzer-
land defends in international forums, foremost the United Nations
Human Rights Council and General Assembly.
Through the strength of its convictions and its openness to sharing
ideas and experiences, Switzerland is committed to remaining active
in eorts to abolish the death penalty.
THE MANY FACETS OF THE DEATH PENALTY
DEBATE
The global trend towards abolition of the death penalty is undeniable.
In December 2014, Madagascar adopted a bill to abolish the death
penalty. In February 2015, Fiji completed its full de jure abolition
process. In March, Côte d’Ivoire and Suriname both scrapped the
death penalty. Whilst a few countries have resumed executions, there
is a growing international consensus that the death penalty is neither
a useful nor a viable sentence.
In the handful of countries where there seems to be little or no hope
of abolition in the near future, what we confront is not a hard bed-
rock of unshakable opposition, but rather a sturdy door. Trying to
break down the door will only alienate those on the other side. But
by respectfully ringing the doorbell and showing patience, one can
engage in productive conversations with those who disagree. However
strong the dierences, it is the experience of Switzerland that when
it comes to the death penalty, there is always room for discussion.
Sometimes the exchanges can be technical, on topics such as criminal
justice reform and alternative sentencing. Other times they are ideo-
logical, philosophical, or even theological, for instance on the purpose
of criminal justice. Overall, though, abolition of the death penalty is
a human rights issue that transcends cultural barriers and speaks to
our common humanity. Compassion is common to every civilization,
religion and region. Rehabilitation as the central goal of the criminal
262 263
is a strong empirical argument to be made that its use inevitably
violates human rights—a case Switzerland is making with a broad
coalition of like-minded countries in international forums.
Public opinion is important, but can be a double-edged sword in the
push for universal abolition, as few people are genuinely committed
to learning about the death penalty’s true consequences. To make
matters worse, some politicians misuse perceived majority support
for the death penalty as the primary justication for not opposing
it. In the numerous countries where abolition took place in spite
of majority opposition, opinions evolved gradually to favour aboli-
tion. Indeed, opinions can change quickly when people are presented
with facts. This has for instance been the case in California, the most
populous state in the United States, where there has been a gradual
shift in public attitudes towards the death penalty. Support for cap-
ital punishment dropped from 63% in 2000 to 52% in 2012, when
the state voted on abolition. Criminologists in particular have been
instrumental in demonstrating that public support for capital punish-
ment, even in the most hard-line countries, is limited at best.
Transparent reporting and public action can be a substantial force
for abolition. Victims’ families in countries including the United
States and Japan have been vocal in saying that the death penalty
does not oer closure for the loss of a loved one; rather, it per-
petuates violence and hatred. Hundreds of innocent people have
now been exonerated from death row because of wrongful convic-
tions and, knowing better than anyone the pain of that experience,
several have been touring the world to tell their story or have it
recorded by the media. Hearing about the injustice of wrongful
convictions and executions is uncomfortable, but it is important to
realize the implications of what can otherwise be too easily forgot-
ten: No criminal justice system is without error. Prosecutors and
judges are human, and despite the best eorts and safeguards, they
make mistakes like anyone else.
“DEATH PENALTY CANNOT BE CARRIED OUT
WITHOUT VIOLATING INTERNATIONAL HUMAN
RIGHTS LAW.
Didier Burkhalter
For Switzerland, leadership is expressed in action rather than grand
discourse. My country is opposed to the death penalty everywhere
and under all circumstances, but it is unrealistic to expect that reten-
tionist countries will accept this stance immediately. Long-term
engagement, incremental action, attentiveness and fact-based discus-
sion are the means by which to move forward. With the right amount
of research, and dissemination to the right actors, it is possible to
revive dialogue everywhere, even where it seems to be dying out.
THE INTERNATIONAL MOVEMENT FOR
ABOLITION
Finding the right interlocutor and the proper approach can be daunt-
ing challenges, as every abolition process is dierent, with its own
context and opportunities. In some countries, abolition requires
the political courage of a few committed leaders. This was famously
the case in France, where Robert Badinter, then minister of justice,
spearheaded abolition through incisive and eloquent prose. In most
countries, however, there is no single event or single politician that
changes the political landscape. Instead it is often a lengthy process,
edged forward by the tenacity of committed parliamentarians and
political leaders. These commendable women and men deserve the
support of the international community.
In other countries, the judiciary can be the best entry point for
addressing capital punishment. Though the death penalty is technically
permitted under international law, legally putting someone to death
is impossible. International law restricts the use of the death penalty
to only the most serious crimes, while mandatory death sentencing is
illegal. In the rarest-of-the-rare cases where the death penalty could
be applicable, there has to be due process. Every prisoner has the right
to appeal up to the highest judicial body of his or her country, as well
as to request clemency. Appeal and clemency procedures invariably
take years, during which the condemned is subjected to the intense
psychological hardship of impending death. Any individual would be
severely psychologically aected by such a process, which amounts to
cruel and degrading treatment. In addition, in every country that still
practices the death penalty, it is disproportionately imposed on the
marginalized, the weak, the poor and the vulnerable. Though capital
punishment may at rst seem consistent with international law, there
264 265
Switzerland will continue to lead through dialogue in the years to
come. We are counting on the support of many partner countries
interested in open and comprehensive engagement. I believe addi-
tional partners will join us soon, and working together with the few
countries still using the death penalty, we can achieve universal abo-
lition by 2025.
SMART LEADERSHIP
The death penalty debate is complex, multifaceted, politically sensitive
and often misunderstood. Doing research, disseminating information
and holding conferences, seminars and workshops - all of these are
important, but they are not sucient to achieve abolition. Leadership
is always necessary to instigate major change.
The abolitionist movement needs to adapt to remaining challenges
and move forward by committing to a new, smart form of leadership,
in which governments, parliamentarians, judges, academics, members
of the media, artists and activists all build on each other’s comple-
mentary strengths. An unwaveringly principled stance needs to be
combined with inclusive and respectful engagement. Switzerland has
been proactive in consolidating a network of smart leaders, many of
whom have years of experience working for universal abolition of
the death penalty. To facilitate the emergence of new leaders, espe-
cially where nearly everything has yet to be done, is a gratifying task.
Dialogue may not be what immediately comes to mind when talking
about leadership. Yet some of the greatest progress towards abolition
has been achieved thanks to individuals willing to engage in pro-
ductive dialogue. Spending time and resources, fostering dialogue,
providing facts, listening to arguments and striving to nd a way for-
ward is in itself a valuable form of leadership. There is enough work
remaining to be done for each of us to have a leadership role to play.
There is also potential for complementarity between gentle support
and full-throated advocacy, as long as actors in both these roles take
the time to study and strategize together. This collaborative planning
is the essence of smart leadership.
I am personally convinced that there are no good arguments in favour
of the death penalty. Quite the contrary: the death penalty creates
more problems than it purports to solve. I believe that under no cir-
cumstances is it just for a human being to take the life of another
human being. We are all awed, we make mistakes, and our imperfec-
tion needs to be acknowledged in the way in which we construct our
criminal justice systems. The death penalty does not make the world
safer, and it most certainly does not make it better.
266 267
Mongolia was one of the few countries to re-introduce the death
penalty. In 1953, the Presidium of the People’s Great Khural adopted
Decree 93, which resolved to abandon capital punishment, but 10
months later it retreated from this decision. Most of those sentenced
to death were people in their 20s to 40s. And most of them had
committed a crime for the rst time.
I would like to mention the main arguments that led me to oppose
the death penalty:
Removing the death penalty does not mean removing pun-
ishment. Criminals fear justice, and justice must be imminent
and unavoidable. But we cannot repair one death with another.
The state has no right to risk making a judicial or procedural
mistake when deciding a question of life and death. Such
mistakes are unacceptable. Mistakes and miscarriages of jus-
tice in applying the death penalty can only be prevented by
closing the door to it altogether. Only then will we be able
to genuinely honour human life and human rights and create
conditions to safeguard them.
On 13 March 2012, the Mongolian Parliament ratied the Second
Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Politi-
cal Rights, indicating that the country is poised to completely abolish
the death penalty.
Mongolia is taking steps to abolish the death penalty both in law and
practice. The criminal code is being amended to comply with the
Second Optional Protocol. Comments from Amnesty International
and specialized United Nations agencies were solicited in the course
of the drafting. The draft Law on Crimes proposed life imprisonment
as the harshest criminal sentence.
Mongolia is committed to contributing to international cooperation to
abolish the death penalty. Mongolia shares the concern over the contin-
ued use of the death penalty in a number of countries. Consistent with
our opposition to capital punishment, Mongolia calls upon all states that
have not yet done so to join the vast majority of countries that do not
execute in the name of the law. It is important to underline the role and
critical importance of international and regional organizations, particu-
larly the United Nations, in the eort to abolish the death penalty.
MONGOLIA HONOURS
HUMAN LIFE AND DIGNITY
Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj
1
I am glad to be part of the movement away from the death penalty,
and I am condent that this book will be an indispensable reference
to national leaders working to advance a moratorium on the imposi-
tion of the death penalty and its eventual abolition.
In 2010 Mongolia announced a mor-
atorium on executions as a rst step
towards abolition of the death penalty.
Our decision received acclamation
internationally and set the standard for
other countries in the “worst execu-
tioner” region. It was a dramatic decision. No known human society
has been fully able to prevent humans from killing one another. Every
community demands from its state severe punishment of criminals.
Yet states have the ability to stop taking citizens’ lives. None of the
abolitionist countries repealed the death penalty under pressure from
public opinion. But the number of countries that have abolished this
punishment grows year by year.
Mongolia is a dignied country, and our citizens are dignied people.
As president, I encouraged my people to end the death penalty, which
degrades our dignity. I said I wanted to be a president who can tell his
citizens: “I will not deprive you of your life under any circumstances,
knowingly, on behalf of the state. Our people say that a human life is
more precious than all the wealth that the Earth can carry. The road
that a democratic Mongolia takes should be clean and bloodless.
Mongolians have suered enough from the death sentence. Between
October 1937 and April 1939, in 51 sessions of the Special Full-Power
Committee, which then functioned in place of the courts, 20,474
Mongolian citizens were sentenced to death. In just one session, a mass
death sentence for 1,228 people was issued, including eight women.
1 Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj is president of Mongolia. This article draws on the statement he made at
the Leadership and Moving Away from the Death Penalty event at the United Nations in New
York on 25 September 2014.
“WE CANNOT
REPAIR ONE DEATH
WITH ANOTHER.
Tsakhiagiin Elbegdorj
268 269
The majority of States already share the conviction that the death
penalty is the opposite of justice.
During the last few decades, the death penalty has lost ground. Two
thirds of the world have already abolished it or have adopted a mor-
atorium, as compared to only 16 in 1977. Each time an execution is
stayed, each time a death sentence is commuted or a new moratorium
is adopted, it is a victory.
But we should stay engaged, as the ght for universal abolition has
not ended yet.
First of all, because a moratorium remains reversible, and a number of States
have broken what until now they had respected, at times for long periods.
Also, because every year worldwide thousands of women and men
are still sentenced to death: in 2014, the number of death sentences
increased by 28% compared to the previous year, according to the
latest report by Amnesty International.
Finally, because every year more than a dozen of countries continue
to execute hundreds or even thousands of people on death row.
In view of these long-term advances but also taking into account
short-term backtracking, it is essential to ensure a strong mobilization
towards universal abolition, for all crimes.
This is the reason why I chose to prioritize this ght in the context
of the French diplomacy, by launching a world campaign towards
universal abolition of the death penalty. This campaign mobilizes our
entire network at dierent levels.
What do we do concretely?
Our embassies and cultural centers are active on the ground to alert,
mobilize, advocate. By organizing conferences, partnerships with
NGOs, media awareness campaigns, creation or strengthening of abo-
litionist networks around the world, our diplomats are consistently
engaged in the abolitionist ght.
TOWARDS UNIVERSAL ABOLITION
OF THE DEATH PENALTY
Laurent Fabius
1
France’s commitment to universal abolition of the death penalty is a
ght for the progress of mankind.
It is a ght that we share with the whole abolitionist movement.
It is by joining our eorts that all of us, governments, regional and
international organizations, parliamentarians, militants, researchers,
advocates, and citizens, will get there.
The articles that appear in the publication that you are holding reect
the mobilization of all sectors of society and regions of the world
towards abolition. France is especially pleased to contribute to spread-
ing this publication in francophone and Arabic-speaking regions, and
I hereby thank the High Commissioner for Human Rights for his
active engagement in this cause.
The testimonies of individuals who have been wrongly convicted, the
studies of the researchers, the articles written by NGO representatives
remind us that the death penalty is ineective, it is unjust and it is
inhumane.
The evidence is in that it is not an eective punishment against crim-
inal behavior: it doesn’t deter crime.
The unjust nature of the death penalty is conrmed by the inequality
it perpetuates: the punishment varies depending on social status or
ethnic aliation. How can one accept that those factors determine
life and death?
Because mistakes are unavoidable and irreversible, the death penalty
is fundamentally a human rights violation. It is not justice. It is the
failure and the negation of justice.
1 Laurent Fabius is the Minister of Foreign Aairs and International Development of France.
270 271
society, show it the way. To this end, one needs courage, determina-
tion and perseverance.
The abolitionist cause requires speaking out against fake certitudes,
ghting bias. Public opinion, urgent priorities or the need to ght
threats such as terrorism or drug tracking are often invoked to jus-
tify the death penalty. These arguments cannot justify maintaining
such a cruel, degrading and inhumane punishment. Those who sup-
port the death penalty often see it as a trade o against the need for
security. One can support the need for security – we all do – while at
the same time opposing the death penalty.
In view of the obligation to protect life, each political or judicial actor
should appeal to his/her courage.
The French experience conrms that courage will pay o. Today, the
majority of the French population supports the choice made by our
leaders thirty years ago, despite the then public opinion. Abolition has
been reected in our constitution in 2007. It is now part of our heritage.
The decision to abolish capital punishment is not a matter of political
expediency. It is not a matter of culture, despite what some claim. It
is a matter of principle.
We must pursue our eorts to advocate that it is both just and pos-
sible to abolish capital punishment, regardless of the circumstances.
The path towards abolition is long and winded. But in view of our
shared ideals of justice and human dignity, each person on death row
is one too many.
To those who still resort to the death penalty or remain hesitant
we say, using the words of Victor Hugo, you may not abolish capital
punishment today, but make no mistake about it, you will abolish it tomorrow
or your successors will”.
Let’s not waste time or lives. Abolishing the death penalty is allowing
justice and mankind to evolve. All those who commit to this path,
will nd France standing by their side.
We engage with all key stake-
holders: parliamentarians, as
abolition is the result of legislative
revision; attorneys, who are on
the frontline defending people
on death row and who contrib-
ute to evolving the thinking on the death penalty; journalists, who can
inform about the reality surrounding the death penalty, especially in
those countries where executions are carried out in secret; but also the
youth, because they are tomorrow’s citizens and decision-makers.
We are also engaged, together with our EU partners, at the mul-
tilateral level. In the context of the UN, we use our inuence to
strengthen the abolitionist movement.
In the General Assembly, France is fully engaged in the ght for the
adoption of the resolution on a universal moratorium, as a rst step
towards complete abolition. In the Human Rights Council, France
has made the ght against the death penalty a priority, including by
acknowledging the human rights violations stemming from it.
The international community has a special responsibility, as capital
punishment is a threat to the universal principles it supports.
However, we should not forget the role that each individual can play,
our personal responsibility on the path towards abolition.
All the countries that have succeeded in the ght against capital pun-
ishment have been able to do so because of the strong political will
and determination of a few individuals.
This is exactly what happened in France. Our path towards abolition
was particularly long: the rst attempts to abolish capital punishment
date back to the beginning of the French Revolution. This issue divided
France, one of the last countries in Western Europe to abolish it, in 1981.
At the time, public opinion was mostly in favor of the death penalty.
However, public opinion cannot be used as a pretext to maintain
capital punishment. In order to abolish it, one needs to be ahead of
“PUBLIC OPINION
CANNOT BE USED AS A
PRETEXT TO MAINTAIN
CAPITAL PUNISHMENT.
Laurent Fabius
272 273
In other words, I was digging my own political grave by systemati-
cally pardoning people who were sentenced to death and pardoning
other detainees on national holidays.
What complicated things further for me was the constitutional strug-
gle, as I strived for the inclusion of an article on the abolition of the
death penalty. I had been working for abolition since the early 1990s,
as soon as I became chairman of the Tunisian League for Human
Rights. I remember that the ght started when a well-known news-
paper made a call in a large headline to execute 12 times a criminal
who had raped and killed 12 children. That day even the members
of the executive board of the League preferred not to take an active
stance against the death penalty, as society was deeply shocked by this
atrocious crime. But I insisted that it was, on the contrary, an oppor-
tunity for us to assume our intellectual responsibility and confront the
(understandably tense) public with our ideas.
In articles and heated public debates, I reiterated the usual arguments
against capital punishment, and these were the same arguments that I
used in my speech to Tunisia’s National Constituent Assembly to call
for abolition:
The death sentence neither cancels nor compensates for the
atrocity of the crime, but rather adds another layer of atrocity.
There is no proven link between the application of this sen-
tence and a decline in crime rates; sometimes the opposite
happens.
Most convicts receiving the sentence come from the poor-
est sections of society as well as minorities and the political
opposition.
Judicial errors are more common that we think, and they
cannot be redressed after an execution is carried out.
These logical arguments, which reject the use of a cure that is more
painful than the disease itself, failed to convince the 217 members of
the Constituent Assembly, and therefore the draft law was not debated.
CHALLENGES RELATED TO
ABOLITION OF THE DEATH
PENALTY IN ARAB AND ISLAMIC
COUNTRIES: TUNISIA’S MODEL
Mohamed Moncef Marzouki
1
A few days after my election as president of the Republic of Tunisia on
12 December 2011, I discovered to my astonishment that there were
220 prisoners on death row. Many in this group had been sentenced
to death a long time ago, but they had neither been executed nor had
their sentence commuted to life imprisonment. Before he was ousted
by the revolution, the dictator had adopted the policy of neither apply-
ing the sentences (as they would further tarnish his dark record of
human rights violations) nor commuting them (as he did not want to
turn public opinion, which supported the death penalty, against him).
I signed a decree to replace the death penalty with life imprisonment,
a decision that in my opinion has changed the lives of many people
who had to bear the weight of psychological torture for years. I was
soon faced with the consequences of this act. Each time the amnesty
committee brought me an amnesty decree, I signed it as a matter of
principle, without even looking at the case. On one occasion the
Minister of Justice insisted that I hear the details of the case, perhaps
with the hope that I would not readily approve the amnesty. So I
went through the details of a horrendous crime. To everyone’s aston-
ishment I signed the amnesty in the midst of what felt like silent yet
heavy disapproval. I knew that that move would further complicate
matters for me, including at the political level.
It was customary to reduce overcrowding in prisons by releasing
young or sick detainees, or those convicted of minor crimes, on
national holidays. But on each occasion the opposition accused me of
releasing dangerous criminals. These attacks were widely supported
by the media, which used to report on every crime that occurred as
a crime committed by someone who was pardoned by the president.
1 Mohamed Moncef Marzouki is the former president of the Republic of Tunisia.
274 275
nowhere, because it gives us only two choices: Advocate for abolition
outside the Islamic framework, or accept the death penalty and give up
our hope of seeing Tunisia in the circle of civilized countries.
But because I am a faithful Muslim and cannot extract myself from
the value system within which I grew up, I found an answer in the
following verse: “Whoever kills a soul unless for a soul or for corrup-
tion in the land, it is as if he had killed all mankind, and whoever saves
it, it is as if he saved all mankind. In my opinion, this verse warns
against killing an innocent person mistakenly or unfairly—which is
common under capital punishment—because the act of killing all
mankind, even symbolically, is an extraordinary responsibility no one
is able to bear.
This is why I argue that we have to give up a right which the Koran
considers lawful but which, when interpreted and applied by humans,
has led to killing all mankind on countless occasions. The Koran does
not accept this.
The intellectual debate on this issue will certainly continue for years,
and it will be dicult to convince society even after terrorism has
been defeated. But our mission as human rights defenders is to con-
tinue advocating, because the matter is not just about people whom
we need to save from a barbaric and ineective punishment, but also
about helping society advance towards a higher degree of civilization.
I was appalled that my closest friends and colleagues in human rights
organizations did nothing either.
I am very proud of the constitution ratied by the Constituent Assem-
bly on 27 January 2014, which guarantees many rights and freedoms.
But I would have been even more proud had Tunisia become the rst
Arab country to join the circle of democratic countries and civilized
nations that have abolished this barbaric punishment.
We need to make sense of this failure in a country that was oered an
historic opportunity, having known a democratic revolution, a strong
human rights movement, and a fervent opponent of capital punish-
ment as head of state.
There are two causes for this failure, one contextual and one structural.
Contextually, the drafting of the constitution, which started after the
October 2011 elections and lasted until January 2013, was marred
with terrorist attacks that resulted in many losses in the ranks of the
army and the police. At these martyrs’ funerals and subsequent meet-
ings with their families at the Carthage Palace, all I could hear were
the cries of these families for retaliation against those who killed their
sons, sometimes expressed with extremely violent imagery. In such
circumstances it is very dicult to advocate for abolition.
The structural cause was even more dicult to overcome: the dom-
inant religious culture that considers capital punishment part of
Islamic sharia law, and therefore not open to debate. For many years
in the human rights struggle, I consistently made reference to verses
of the Koran that encourage pardon, forgiveness and mercy, all of
which are core values of our noble Islamic religion.
But every reference I made was countered by a reference to other parts
of the Koran that explicitly call for retaliation. Such a position leads
“I WAS DIGGING MY OWN POLITICAL GRAVE
BY SYSTEMATICALLY PARDONING PEOPLE WHO
WERE SENTENCED TO DEATH.
Mohamed Moncef Marzouki
276 277
Every country has a responsibility to respect human rights for the
good of their own people and for the rest of humankind. We should
exercise our individual and shared responsibility not just in the inter-
est of people living today, but for all future generations.
As prime minister of Italy, I take pride in the fact that my country is
highly regarded for its engagement in the campaign for a moratorium on
the death penalty. This endeavour is deeply rooted in the Italian identity;
historical, cultural and religious factors have all played a fundamental role.
But let me be clear: This is also a success story about good leadership.
More than two centuries ago, in 1786, the Grand Duke of Tus-
cany, Leopold I, abolished capital punishment in his territories. This
decision was inspired by the philosophical and juridical reection
of another great Italian, Cesare Beccaria, who 20 years before had
published a book titled On Crimes and Punishments, in which he con-
demned the use of torture and capital punishment and underlined
the lack of scientic evidence on the deterrent value of the death
penalty. Beccaria was able to show that the death penalty is useless
and unnecessary, arming at the same time that its abolition would
represent a signicant contribution to human progress.
In the 18th century Italy was not the unied state it is today, but in
many aspects it was already a nation, with a common heritage, lan-
guage, history and values. The arguments provided by Cesare Beccaria
and the example set by Grand Duke Leopold have remained vivid in
the hearts and minds of Italians until today. Great leadership inspired
by ideas and a clear vision of the future can make change happen. In
1889, the now unied Kingdom of Italy abolished the death penalty,
except in the military code. Under fascism, the death penalty was rein-
troduced, but as soon as democracy was re-established after the Second
World War, the death penalty during peacetime was completely abol-
ished. Further steps were later taken to completely abolish the use of
capital punishment under all circumstances, and today Italian legislation
is fully compliant with the standards set by the United Nations and
the Council of Europe. But even in a country where the campaign for
abolition of the death penalty has deep roots in history and enjoys a
wide consensus among the population, it has taken time and eort to
introduce the necessary legislative reforms to fully enact it.
THE ROLE OF LEADERSHIP
Matteo Renzi
1
As a country that has traditionally supported multilateralism and
is inclined towards dialogue and mediation, for both historical and
geographical reasons, Italy has always attached great importance
to the promotion of human rights in international relations. In
particular, Italy has been actively engaged in the campaign for a
moratorium on the death penalty, which was one of the priorities
of the Italian rotating Presidency of the Council of the European
Union for the second semester of 2014.
2
I am therefore very grateful
for the opportunity to contribute to this publication and elaborate
on the role of leadership in advancing this campaign.
The United Nations plays a unique role in calling on the entire
international community to work in a more coordinated and eec-
tive manner to ensure the respect of human rights and fundamental
freedoms. I would like to thank in particular Secretary-General Ban
Ki-moon for his tireless work in advocating for a moratorium of
the use of the death penalty worldwide. His strong leadership, deep
personal commitment and inspiring words are instrumental to the
success of the campaign. I would also like to thank the Assistant
Secretary-General for Human Rights Šimonovic´ and the Oce
of the High Commissioner for Human Rights for their excellent
work in assisting and coordinating activities in this eld.
Since my appointment as prime minister of Italy, I have grown even
further in my rm belief in the importance of promoting and pro-
tecting human rights and fundamental freedoms. Promoting respect
for human rights for all without distinction is not only a matter of
ethics, but a necessary condition to maintain international peace and
security and foster economic and social development.
1 Matteo Renzi is president of the Council of Ministers of the Republic of Italy.
2 The Italian Presidency had the following priorities in the eld of human rights: to further the
campaign for a moratorium on executions, to ensure freedom of religion and belief and the
protection of religious minorities, and to promote women’s rights (in particular, by combating
gender-based violence, female genital mutilation and early and forced marriages).
278 279
When we rst started the campaign for a moratorium on the death
penalty, many looked with scepticism at our eorts and our chances of
success. Some argued that a resolution should not cover a topic that is
still considered by many states to be a matter of domestic jurisdiction;
for others, the non-binding nature of the resolutions meant they were
unlikely to bring about signicant change. However, we believed, and
we still do, that every battle for the promotion of human rights is worth
ghting. And it pays o. The increasing number of countries that over
the years have voted in favour of the moratorium (or abstained) shows
a clear international trend in favour of limiting the scope and conse-
quences of the death penalty. In a true testimony to the importance and
universality of this campaign, the United Nations General Assembly
resolutions have received the support of ever more countries from all
regions of the world, at dierent stages of economic development, with
populations belonging to dierent religions.
By emphasising the need to establish a moratorium on executions
with a view to abolishing the death penalty, the resolutions have been
supported by countries that have legally abolished the death penalty
(perhaps a long time ago), as well as by countries that have introduced
a de facto moratorium or intend to do so, while the death penalty
remains part of their legal framework. Many countries have not been
able to abolish the death penalty but have taken steps in this direction.
The campaign for the moratorium has kept the momentum going
and focused the attention of the international community on this
important topic.
One of the lessons we have learned in this experience is that no single
strategy can be considered more successful than others to advance
the movement in favour of the moratorium. However, undoubtedly,
strong leadership is always necessary.
Political leaders have a special responsibility in this regard. First and
foremost, they can build consensus in favour of a moratorium within
“POLITICAL LEADERS ARE CALLED TO PLAY A
GUIDING ROLE AND MAKE THE CASE FOR THE
ABOLITION OF THE DEATH PENALTY.
Matteo Renzi
Italian opposition to the death penalty is grounded in history, but
it looks to the future as well. Building on the progress achieved at
home, it was natural for Italy to set out on a worldwide campaign for
a moratorium on the death penalty and to put it at the forefront of its
foreign policy priorities. Italy rst tabled a draft resolution on a mor-
atorium at the United Nations General Assembly in 1994. While the
resolution failed (by only a handful of votes), this outcome conrmed
the importance and the urgency of the campaign. There was wide
support for our initiative, but it became clear that enhanced eorts
were needed to win the hearts and minds of all members of the inter-
national community. Indeed, Italy continued to work on building a
broad international coalition in favour of the moratorium, in close
cooperation with its European partners and with the strong support
of civil society organisations. I personally remember the initiatives
and debates on this topic within Italian civil society, including the
youth movement. It was thanks to these tremendous collective eorts
that the rst resolution on a moratorium on the use of the death
penalty was adopted in 2007. This was indeed a historical moment for
the entire international community!
Four more resolutions were approved in 2008, 2010, 2012 and 2014.
Each resolution has been a landmark for the campaign on the mor-
atorium as it has focused attention on dierent aspects of this issue.
For instance, the 2012 resolution called for the rst time on states
to progressively restrict executions involving children and pregnant
women. It also more clearly identied the information states should
make available on their use of the death penalty—the number of
people sentenced to death, the number of people on death row and
the number of executions carried out.
The most recent resolution was tabled for approval at the 69th Session
of the United Nations General Assembly in December 2014. Italy
worked with enhanced eorts alongside the cross-regional group of
co-sponsors to obtain the widest possible support for the new reso-
lution. I am honoured to have contributed to the outreach to other
countries by participating in the supporting event Moving Away from
the Death Penalty: National Leadership, organized by Italy and the
United Nations—along with Benin, Mongolia and Tunisia—during
the 69th General Assembly session in September 2014.
280 281
Italy’s experience as a useful example of positive synergy between
national governments and civil society organisations. The Italian
Ministry of Foreign Aairs and International Cooperation has estab-
lished a special partnership with Comunità di Sant’Egidio, Hands
o Cain and the Italian branch of Amnesty International. These
organisations have been engaged for a long time in awareness-rais-
ing projects. Their global outreach has signicantly contributed to
the success of the campaign for a moratorium on the death penalty.
Their eorts have eectively complemented activities undertaken at
the institutional level.
In many countries, religious leaders can also play a role in the cam-
paign for the moratorium, in particular where religion and politics
are closely intertwined, or for instance the judicial power is held by a
religious authority. In some cases such a positive interaction could be
more complex, but constructive dialogue is always the best tool for
promoting human rights, even in the most dicult contexts.
Other examples of successful outreach include initiatives carried out
together with the academic or judiciary community of countries
where capital punishment is still practised. Although in such countries
the abolition of the death penalty may not be possible in the short
term, dialogue between human rights experts and legal practitioners
could produce signicant results and pave the way for future changes.
In this regard, the support of the United Nations, mainly through the
activities of the Oce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights,
can provide invaluable help.
In conclusion, the conditions of individual countries may dier, but
the campaign for a moratorium on the use of the death penalty with
a view to its eventual full abolition will only be successful if it can
count on strong leadership at all levels. Successful political leaders
are able to overcome setbacks and diculties by reaching out to all
interested parties at the institutional level and within civil society.
This continuous dialogue is instrumental to building the consensus
we need to steadily progress towards a world where justice does not
require the loss of a human life.
the wider political community of their country. I am honoured that
all Italian political actors and institutions have shown full and unwav-
ering support for the campaign. This level of support is particularly
important in countries where capital punishment still exists. In these
circumstances, political leaders are called to engage constructively with
parliaments to facilitate the legal reforms required, so that changes to
establish a de jure moratorium or abolition can be enacted according
to a sustainable reform path and within an appropriate time frame.
Political leaders also play an important role in mobilising public opin-
ion in favour of the abolition of the death penalty, for instance through
awareness campaigns, public debates and specic educational programs
in schools. I am deeply touched by the experiences of those political
leaders that have directly witnessed the eects of the use of the death
penalty and are actively engaged in the campaign for the moratorium.
Such strong leadership is even more necessary when countries con-
front signicant threats to their security, including organized crime and
terrorism. Although there is increasing evidence that the death penalty
is not an eective deterrent to crime, statistics are not always enough
to sway public opinion. The sense of insecurity caused by extremism
and widespread violence may lead people to believe that the death
penalty could restore security. It is exactly in such cases, however, that
political leaders are called to play a guiding role and make the case
for the abolition of the death penalty, even if it may seem dicult to
justify. Political responsibility to stop crime and violence does not need
to lead to compromises in terms of human rights. On the contrary, it
makes the promotion and protection of human rights and fundamental
freedoms even more necessary. For instance, enhanced eorts could be
made to ensure that terrorists and those responsible for violations of
international humanitarian or human rights law are held to account
through existing international criminal justice mechanisms.
The success of the campaign for a moratorium does not depend
only on the contribution of political leadership. All international and
national institutions and all sectors of civil society should play a lead-
ing role. It is crucial, for example, to enhance cooperation between
political institutions and nongovernmental organizations that possess
specic expertise on the subject. In this regard, I would like to recall
282 283
The main challenge the gov-
ernment faces is the need to
mobilize the necessary means
and nancial resources to
refurbish or build modern
infrastructure including
high-security prisons, in line
with international standards, to carry out life sentences. The goal is
to ensure that perpetrators of armed robberies resulting in casualties
are not released to resume their criminal activities at the expense of
society.
We consider that the international community should pursue and
strengthen its outreach eorts to convince an increasing number of
states to adopt a moratorium with a view to abolishing the death
penalty. The abolition of the death penalty is a ght for the progress
of humanity, and Benin wishes to thank civil society organisations for
their remarkable work towards an evolution of minds and mentalities
to that end.
At the United Nations, this progress is already visible and needs to
be strengthened. It is heartening to see that several states that used to
abstain or vote against the resolution on the moratorium are changing
their vote, and we have to pursue our eorts to support them further.
“THE DEATH PENALTY
HAS TURNED OUT TO BE
INEFFECTIVE IN THE FIGHT
AGAINST CRIME.
Boni Yayi
A FIGHT FOR THE PROGRESS
OF HUMANITY
Boni Yayi
1
The death penalty has turned out to be ineective in the ght against
crime. It never helped curb the crime rate in the countries that make
use of it; in fact, as criminals know what fate is in store for them, they
become more aggressive.
The death penalty does not provide satisfaction to the families of the
victims, as an execution cannot soothe their pain. Also, the numerous
judicial errors that have been discovered, leading to stays of execution,
should force a reection in society about the need to abandon this
form of punishment.
The Republic of Benin has fully adhered to the Second Optional
Protocol of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,
aiming at abolishing the death penalty, since 2013.
Even before 2013, death sentences imposed by the courts of Benin
were not carried out. The last execution took place in 1987; after
that, Benin observed a de facto moratorium. Since Benin became
party to the Second Optional Protocol, no court in Benin can
sentence people to death. The government informed all courts
of Benin accordingly, specifying the new international norm to
which Benin had become a party. Benin’s new draft penal code
has annulled all provisions relating to the death penalty, based on
the principle of the superiority of ratied international law over
domestic legislation.
It is important to recognize that the practice followed in Benin is
the result of a process of sensitisation which gained the trust of the
people of Benin, who traditionally value human life and believe that
the death penalty is not justice but rather a failure of justice. These
outreach campaigns have been very successful.
1 Boni Yayi is the president (chief of state and head of government) of the Republic of Benin.
284
“Rejecting capital punishment is about choosing
what kind of society we want to live in, and which
values—including human rights and dignity,
democracy and the rule of law—we want to uphold.
— Federico Mayor
285
CHAPTER 6
TRENDS AND PERSPECTIVES
This chapter deals with empirically measurable trends regarding the death
penalty and the role of political leadership in shaping those trends. Although
there is a clear long-term trend away from the death penalty, data about
increases in passed death sentences in 2014 are deeply concerning. Political
leadership is urgently needed to keep us on the abolitionist track.
Salil Shetty, Secretary General of Amnesty International, oers a cau-
tiously optimistic analysis of global trends in the death penalty from 2014.
Amnesty International has been monitoring trends in the use of the death
penalty for more than three decades. There is no doubt that the world has
moved away from the death penalty during this time. In 1945 only eight
countries had abolished the death penalty; today, 100 countries have fully
abolished it. However, each year there is both good and bad news. According
to Amnesty International, in 2014, the number of passed death sentences
rose by 28 per cent compared to the previous year.
In 2014, an alarming number of countries used the death penalty to
respond to real or perceived threats to state security and public safety posed
by terrorism, crime (especially drug tracking) or internal instability. As
in the past, unfair trials, “confessions” extracted through torture or other
ill-treatment, the use of the death penalty against juvenile oenders and
people with mental or intellectual disabilities, and for crimes other than
“intentional killing” continued to be concerning features of the use of the
death penalty.
Peaceful protesters against the death penalty. © Credit: EPA/Sedat Suna
286 287
GLOBAL DEATH PENALTY
TRENDS IN 2014
Salil Shetty
1
Amnesty International has been campaigning for abolition of the
death penalty since 1977. As part of this work, the organization
monitors the use of capital punishment globally and publishes annual
gures on the number of countries known to have carried out judi-
cial executions, as well as the number of people known to have been
sentenced to death or executed. This annual report also looks at how
capital punishment is applied and at trends in its use, as far as these
can be determined.
One of the greatest challenges we face each year is the lack of ocial
information on the application of the death penalty in most countries
that retain it. Using a variety of non-governmental sources, we are
able to establish what we term credible minimum gures—meaning
that we can say that at least this number of people were executed or
sentenced to death. The true gures are often higher.
THE 2014 FIGURES
Amnesty International recorded executions in 22 countries in 2014,
the same number of countries as in 2013.
2
Although the number
remained constant, there were some changes in the countries carry-
ing out executions. Seven countries that executed in 2013 did not do
so in 2014 (Bangladesh, Botswana, Indonesia, India, Kuwait, Nigeria
and South Sudan), while seven others resumed executions (Belarus,
Egypt, Equatorial Guinea, Jordan, Pakistan, Singapore and the United
Arab Emirates).
At least 607 people were executed, and at least 2,466 people were sen-
tenced to death. These gures represent a decrease in the number of
executions compared to in 2013 (at least 778) but a sharp increase in
1 Salil Shetty is secretary-general of Amnesty International.
2 All data in this article are drawn from Amnesty International, Death Sentences and Executions in
2014 (London, Amnesty International, 2015), available from www.amnestyusa.org/research/
reports/death-sentences-and-executions-2014.
the number of death sentences (at least 1,925). Whilst the challenges
of data collection referred to above mean that year-on-year com-
parisons should be treated with caution, some specic developments
during 2014—such as mass death sentences imposed in Egypt—shed
light on the increase in this gure.
At least 509 death sentences were imposed in Egypt in 2014. These
included the mass death sentences handed down by Egyptian courts
after mass trials that were grossly unfair. For example, the Minya
criminal court imposed death sentences on 37 people in April 2014
and 183 people in June 2014.
3
In December 2014, the Giza criminal
court recommended death
sentences against 188 people
for involvement in the killing
of 11 police ocers in Giza
in August 2013.
Amnesty International’s
annual gures do not include
the thousands of people
sentenced to death and executed in China. In 2009, Amnesty Interna-
tional stopped publishing estimates for China, where data on capital
punishment are considered a state secret. Instead, we challenge the
Chinese authorities to prove their claims that they are reducing the
application of the death penalty by publishing the gures themselves.
In 2014, as in 2013, it was also impossible to conrm if judicial exe-
cutions took place in Syria. In addition, no information could be
conrmed on North Korea.
The following methods of executions were used: beheading (Saudi
Arabia), hanging (Afghanistan, Bangladesh, Egypt, Iran, Iraq, Japan,
Jordan, Malaysia, Pakistan, Palestine, Singapore, Sudan), lethal injec-
tion (China, United States, Viet Nam) and shooting (Belarus, China,
Equatorial Guinea, North Korea, Palestine, Saudi Arabia, Somalia,
Taiwan, United Arab Emirates, Yemen). As in previous years, there
3 The death sentences followed referrals from the court to the grand mufti, Egypt’s highest reli-
gious ocial. Egyptian criminal courts must refer a case to the grand mufti for review before
handing down a death sentence; however, the opinion of the grand mufti is advisory and not
binding.
“WHEN IT COMES TO
THE DEATH PENALTY,
HUMANITY’S GOAL
IS CLEAR”
Salil Shetty,
Amnesty International
288 289
were no reports of judicial executions carried out by stoning. In the
United Arab Emirates, one woman was sentenced to death by ston-
ing for committing “adultery” while married. Public executions were
carried out in Iran and Saudi Arabia.
Justifications for the use of the death penalty
In 2014 an alarming number of countries used the death penalty to
respond to real or perceived threats to state security and public safety
posed by terrorism, crime or internal instability. This is not a new
phenomenon, but it has become a serious concern for the abolition-
ist movement as we see more countries and politicians attempt to
defend the use, or resumption, of executions as a solution to crime
and terrorism. As this publication and others have made clear, there
is no evidence that the death penalty has a greater deterrent eect
on crime than imprisonment. When governments present the death
penalty as a solution to crime or insecurity, they are not only mis-
leading the public but also failing, in many cases, to take the necessary
action to prevent and respond to crime through robust and rights-re-
specting criminal justice systems.
4
China, Iran, Iraq and Pakistan executed people convicted of terrorism
in 2014, while Cameroon and the United Arab Emirates expanded
the scope of the death penalty to include terrorism-related crimes.
On 17 December 2014, Pakistan lifted a six-year moratorium on
civilian executions for terrorism-related oences. The decision was in
response to a horric attack the day before on a school in Peshawar
that left more than 149 people dead, including 132 children. Seven
people, all of whom had been convicted under an anti-terrorism law,
were executed in less than two weeks. The government also pledged
to execute hundreds of people on death row who had been con-
victed of terrorism-related oences. By 28 April 2015, the country
had already executed 100 people.
4 See Amnesty International, Not Making Us Safer: Crime, Public Safety and the Death Penalty
(London, Amnesty International, 2013), available from www.amnesty.org/en/documents/docu-
ment/?indexnumber=act51%2f002%2f2013&language=en.
Also in December 2014, Indonesia announced its intention to resume
executions for drug-related oences to confront what it called a
national emergency. On 19 January 2015, six people were executed
and the Indonesian authorities announced plans to put more people
to death throughout the year. On 28 April, eight people, including
Indonesian and foreign nationals, were executed by ring squad. All
of them had been convicted of drug tracking. The executions went
ahead despite international calls for clemency.
China made use of the death penalty as a tool in the Strike Hard
campaign against terrorism and violent crime in the Xinjiang Uighur
Autonomous Region. Three people were sentenced to death in a
mass sentencing event that was held in an outdoor sports arena in
May 2014. Those sentenced had been convicted of terrorism, separat-
ism and murder. Between June and August, 21 people were executed
in the Xinjiang Uighur Autonomous Region in relation to various
terrorist attacks.
Jordan resumed executions at the end of 2014 after an eight-year
hiatus, executing 11 men for murder. The executions followed the
establishment, weeks before, of a special committee of the Cabinet
to look into lifting the suspension on executions as a deterrent to
murder and in response to public demand.
The ongoing use of the death penalty in
contravention of international law
In 2014, as in the past, many of the states that retain the death penalty
continued to use it in contravention of international law and stan-
dards. Unfair trials, “confessions” extracted through torture or other
ill-treatment, and the use of the death penalty against juvenile oend-
ers and people with mental or intellectual disabilities and for crimes
other than intentional killing continued to be concerning features of
the use of the death penalty.
People with mental or intellectual disabilities were under sentence of
death in several countries including Indonesia, Japan, Malaysia, Paki-
stan, Trinidad and Tobago and the United States.
290 291
Several countries continued to hand down death sentences and
execute people for crimes that did not involve intentional killing
and therefore did not meet the threshold of “most serious crimes”
prescribed by Article 6 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights, which is widely understood to mean crimes involving
intentional killing. The death penalty was imposed or implemented
for drug-related oences in China, Indonesia, Iran, Malaysia, Saudi
Arabia, Singapore, Sri Lanka, Thailand, the United Arab Emirates and
Viet Nam.
Other capital crimes that did not meet the standard of “most seri-
ous crimes” but for which the death penalty was imposed in 2014
included economic crimes such as corruption (China, North Korea
and Viet Nam), armed robbery (Democratic Republic of the Congo),
committing adultery while married (United Arab Emirates), rape
that resulted in death (Afghanistan), rape committed by a repeat rape
oender (India), rape (Saudi Arabia, United Arab Emirates), kidnap-
ping (Saudi Arabia), torture (Saudi Arabia), insulting the prophet of
Islam (Iran), blasphemy (Pakistan), and witchcraft and sorcery (Saudi
Arabia).
Finally, acts described as treason, acts against national security, col-
laboration with a foreign entity, espionage, participation in an
insurrectional movement, terrorism and other crimes against the state,
whether or not they led to a loss of life, were punished with death
sentences in Lebanon, North Korea, Palestine (in the West Bank and
in Gaza), Qatar and Saudi Arabia.
REGIONAL DEVELOPMENTS
Amnesty International recorded at least 46 executions in three coun-
tries in sub-Saharan Africa in 2014, compared to 64 in ve countries
in 2013. The countries known to have executed people were Equa-
torial Guinea, Somalia and Sudan. Sub-Saharan Africa also saw several
positive developments with states taking steps towards abolition, as
discussed in the next section.
The number of judicial executions conrmed in the Middle East and
North Africa decreased from at least 638 in 2013 to at least 491 in
2014. However, it should be noted that obtaining complete and reli-
able data on the use of the death penalty in the region is particularly
dicult, especially for countries such as Iran, Iraq, Saudi Arabia and
Yemen. The internal armed conict in Syria meant that informa-
tion on the use of the death penalty in the country could not be
conrmed.
In the Americas, the United States remained the only country to
carry out judicial executions. However, the number of executions
dropped from 39 in 2013 to 35 last year, reecting a steady decline in
executions over the past years.
5
Only seven states executed in 2014
(down from nine in 2013), with four (Texas, Missouri, Florida and
Oklahoma) responsible for 89 per cent of all executions. The state of
Washington imposed a moratorium on executions in February 2014.
The overall number of death sentences decreased from 95 in 2013 to
77 in 2014.
Amnesty International recorded 32 executions in the Asia-Pacic
region (excluding China), compared to 37 in 2013. The number of
death sentences recorded in 2014 decreased by 335 compared to
2013 (from 1,030 to 695—again, excluding China). Pakistan and
Singapore resumed executions in 2014, and Indonesia announced its
intention to end a moratorium on civilian executions—acting on this
statement of intent in 2015, as noted above.
The Pacic continued to be the world’s only virtually death-penal-
ty-free zone, although the governments of both Papua New Guinea
and Kiribati took steps to resume executions or introduce the death
penalty.
In Europe and Central Asia, Belarus—the only country in the region
that executes people —put at least three people to death during the
year, ending a 24-month hiatus. The executions were marked by
secrecy; family members and lawyers were informed only after the fact.
5 Death Penalty Information Center, “Executions in the United States, available from www.
deathpenaltyinfo.org/executions-united-states; Amnesty International, “Death penalty, www.
amnesty.org/en/what-we-do/death-penalty/.
292 293
POSITIVE DEVELOPMENTS IN 2014
There were positive developments recorded in 2014 that are worth
celebrating. In December 2014, the National Assembly of Mada-
gascar adopted a bill to abolish the death penalty. Similar bills were
pending before legislative bodies in Benin, Chad and Mongolia and
were approved by the parliaments of Fiji and Suriname early in 2015.
The Parliament of Barbados has started considering draft legislation
aimed at abolishing the mandatory death penalty.
States gave more support to international treaties and resolutions
favouring abolition of the death penalty. El Salvador, Gabon and
Poland became state parties to the Second Optional Protocol to the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, aiming at the
abolition of the death penalty. In May 2014, Poland also ratied Pro-
tocol No. 13 to the (European) Convention for the Protection of
Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, concerning the aboli-
tion of the death penalty in all circumstances.
In December the UN General Assembly adopted its fth resolution on
a moratorium on the use of the death penalty. The number of votes in
favour of Resolution 69/186 increased by six, from 111 in 2012 to 117 in
2014, while 38 countries voted against and 34 countries abstained. New
votes in favour of the 2014 resolution came from Equatorial Guinea,
Eritrea, Fiji, Niger and Suriname. In a further positive sign, Bahrain,
Myanmar, Tonga and Uganda moved from opposition to abstention.
Amnesty International recorded 112 exonerations of death row pris-
oners in nine countries: Bangladesh (4), China (2), Jordan (1), Nigeria
(32), Sudan (4), Tanzania (59), United States (7), Viet Nam (2) and
Zimbabwe (1). These are minimum gures, and the real gures may
be higher. The release of prisoners from death row on the grounds
of innocence exposes the fallibility of human justice and has sparked
debates on the death penalty in several countries, including countries
where support for it has traditionally been strong, such as China,
Japan, the United States and Viet Nam.
In 2014, activism by people committed to abolition of the death
penalty helped to stop executions in several countries. Chandran s/o
Paskaran was spared execution in Malaysia on 7 February 2014 after an
outcry from human rights groups, including Amnesty International.
ThankGod Ebhos was sentenced to death in Nigeria in 1995. On
23 June 2013, he was taken to the gallows with four other men, all
of whom were hanged in front of him. At the last minute, the prison
authorities realized that ThankGod Ebhos’s death sentence required
a ring squad and he was returned to his cell. On 24 October 2014,
following campaigns against his execution, ThankGod Ebhos was
released from death row.
Meriam Yehya Ibrahim was released from prison in Sudan on 23 June
2014. Her death sentence for apostasy, imposed by a Khartoum court
on 15 May, was overturned by an appeals court. Meriam Yehya Ibra-
him’s case attracted widespread international attention, with over one
million people responding to Amnesty International’s appeal for her
release.
Although each year Amnesty International records both negative and
positive developments on the death penalty, the long-term global
trend is unmistakably positive. In 2014, 22 countries executed; two
decades ago, in 1995, that number stood at 41. Today 100 countries
have fully abolished the death penalty, and many more have not exe-
cuted anyone for so long that Amnesty International considers them
to be “abolitionist in practice. In total 140 countries, over 70 per
cent of the countries in the world, are abolitionist in law or practice.
Amnesty International opposes the death penalty in all cases without
exception regardless of the nature or circumstances of the crime; guilt,
innocence or other characteristics of the individual; or the method
used by the state to carry out the execution. The death penalty vio-
lates the right to life and is the ultimate cruel, inhuman and degrading
punishment; it should be totally abolished.
294 295
AFTERWORD
It is vital that we encourage people to join the movement to end the
death penalty, which negates the right to life and raises important
human rights concerns.
No judiciary is mistake-free. In practice, the decision to put someone
to death is often arbitrary, and the odds are often stacked against the
poor, the powerless, and people who belong to racial, religious, ethnic
or sexual minorities. An alarming body of evidence also indicates that
even well-functioning legal systems have sentenced to death men and
women who were subsequently proved innocent. When a miscarriage
of justice results in someone being put to death, the state becomes a
murderer. Furthermore, there is no evidence that the death penalty
deters crime. The real deterrent is not the severity of punishment but its
certainty. We need to focus resources and policy on strengthening the
justice system—not on the brutal and arbitrary practice of executions.
The global trend towards the abolition of the death penalty has accel-
erated remarkably in recent years, and today most countries either have
abolished it or observe a moratorium. Distressingly, among the states
that do continue to execute people, several use this penalty for oences
that do not meet the threshold of “most serious crimes, after legal
proceedings that clearly violate human rights standards for a fair trial.
I urge every reader to consider the facts with an open mind. To me,
the arguments are convincing and decisive: On every level—from
principle to practice—the death penalty is wrong.
Zeid Ra’ad Al Hussein
United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights
“CONSIDER THE FACTS WITH AN OPEN MIND.
Zeid Ra’ad Al Hussein
296 297
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Many people contributed to this publication in dierent ways.
Secretary-General Ban Ki-Moon not only provided the preface for
this book, he participated in four of our death-penalty-related events
as the keynote speaker. His involvement helped to mobilise a large
participation by Member States as well as civil society, including aca-
demia, at the events.
Amnesty International and
others helped us establish
contacts with many pan-
ellists whose contributions
are included in this book.
The Governments of Benin,
Chile, Italy, Mongolia, the
Philippines and Tunisia co-
organised events with us,
and the Government of Italy
contributed nancially to the
production of this publication.
Colleagues from the Oce of the High Commissioner for Human
Rights in Geneva led by Navi Pillay, the High Commissioner for
Human Rights until recently and the new High Commissioner Zeid
Ra’ad al-Hussein, have been extremely supportive of the New York-
based panels on the death penalty as well as this publication.
Daily challenges would not have allowed me to edit this book
without help and support from all New York Oce of the High
Commissioner sta.
Thank you all!
Ivan Šimonovi´c
Editor
The Colosseum is illuminated with the ‘Cities of
Life’ logo to support the campaign against the death
penalty, in Rome, Italy, 30 November 2011.
© EPA/Alessandro di Meo
298
1975 2015
MOVING AWAY FROM THE DEATH PENALTY
ARGUMENTS, TRENDS AND PERSPECTIVES
Between 2012 and 2015 OHCHR organised in New York a series of knowledge
events on moving away from the death penalty. These events brought together
representatives of Member States, academia and civil society, as well as legal
experts and victims of wrongful convictions. This publication consists of a
series of articles from the panellists, and reflects a diversity of geographic
experiences – Africa, Americas and the Caribbean, Asia and Europe, with
articles exploring compelling arguments relevant in deciding in favour of
moving away from the death penalty.
Despite the greatest judicial eorts, wrongful convictions are simply not
avoidable. Capital punishment is too final and irrevocable. It prohibits the
correction of mistakes by the justice system and leaves no room for human
error, with the gravest of consequences.
There is no evidence of a deterrent eect of the death penalty. Statistics
from countries that have abolished the death penalty indicate no increase
in serious crime.
The death penalty is not imposed in a just and equal way. Those sacrificed
on the altar of retributive justice are almost always those who are vulnerable
because of their poverty, minority status or mental disability.
Not all victims and their family members support the death penalty. And even
for those who seek it, long delays and the small percentage of executions
actually carried out often cause frustration and delay closure.
Furthermore, as long as the death penalty exists, it can be misused, to target
particular social groups or political opponents.
ISBN 978-92-1-154215-8